<<

NBER WORKING SERIES

MEDIA

Sendhil Mullainathan Andrei Shleifer

Working Paper 9295 http://www.nber.org/papers/w9295

NATIONAL BUREAU OF ECONOMIC RESEARCH 1050 Massachusetts Avenue Cambridge, MA 02138 October 2002

We are extremely grateful to Alberto Alesina, Gene D'Avolio, Ed Glaeser, Simon Johnson, Larry Katz, and Richard Posner for comments. The views expressed herein are those of the authors and not necessarily those of Bureau of Economic Research.

© 2002 by Sendhil Mullainathan and Andrei Shleifer. All rights reserved. Short sections of text, not to exceed two paragraphs, may be quoted without explicit permission provided that full credit, including © notice, is given to the . Bias Sendhil Mullainathan and Andrei Shleifer NBER Working Paper No. 9295 October 2002 JEL No. D23, L82 ABSTRACT

There are two different types of . One bias, which we refer to as , reflects a outlet's desire to affect reader opinions in a particular direction. The second bias, which we refer to as , reflects the outlet's attempt to simply create a memorable story. We examine competition among media outlets in the presence of these . Whereas competition can eliminate the effect of ideological bias, it actually exaggerates the incentive to spin stories.

Sendhil Mullainathan Andrei Shleifer MIT Department of Department of Economics 50 Memorial Drive, E52-251C M9 Littauer Center Cambridge, MA 02142 Cambridge, MA 02138 [email protected] [email protected] and NBER and NBER

1 Intro duction

The descriptiveaccounts of the media industry (Mencken 1975, Goldb erg 2002), as well

as textb o oks (Jamieson and Campb ell 2002) recognize that media outlets

do not just rep ort plain facts. One commonly noted bias in rep orting is ideological.

During PresidentClinton's imp eachment trial, the right-leaning media supp orted im-

peachment, arguing that even a small lie in a civil dep osition constitutes a ma jor crime.

The left-leaning media, in contrast, saw the trial as a witch-hunt, treating the very same

violations condemned by the conservative press as trivial. Another, p erhaps less com-

monly noted, bias is not ideological at all, but rather results from the need to tell a

memorable story. Thus b oth the conservative and the lib eral media condemned Wen

Ho Lee as a Chinese spy, without entertaining the p ossibility that he was scap e-goated

by dishonest ocials. The media were surely biased, and probably wrong.

In this pap er, we draw a sharp analytical distinction between these two kinds of

biased rep orting. We call the traditional left or right bias ideology, and the less tradi-

tional bias - one based on the need to tell a story { spin. We see ideology as coming

directly from the preferences of either editors or rep orters. For example, left wing

newspap ers may simply prefer to rep ort news one way. We see spin, on the other

hand, as coming from a newspap er's attempt to tell a simple and memorable story.

The act of simplication leads to bias since some is necessarily discarded.

We examine the consequences of both ideology and spin for the accuracy of news re-

porting. Our principal interest is how comp etition a ects accuracy. We show that,

even with comp etition, the truth may not always come out, esp ecially when spin is

imp ortant.

We consider the case of private media outlets maximizing the welfare of their owners,

which dep ends on ideology and pro ts. We b egin with the case of a monop oly news

supplier. We establish that, with Bayesian readers, only the ideology of the media

outlet is a source of bias in rep orting. But we also consider the case of readers who

are categorical thinkers - have limited memory, and can only remember the \b ottom

line." This psychological assumption allows us to analyze the commonly noted need 2

by media outlets to tell a memorable story, the so-called \ imp erative". With

categorical readers, it pays the monop olist news supplier to spin the news in order to

make them memorable even in the absence of any ideology. This spin - the need to tell

the story - is also a source of rep orting bias.

The more interesting issues arise when we consider comp etition among media out-

lets. Such comp etition is an imp ortant argument for free press: despite the ideological

biases of individual news suppliers, the truth comes out through comp etition. We

show that, with Bayesian readers, this is indeed the case: comp etition undo es the

biases from ideology. With readers who are categorical thinkers, however, the conse-

quences of comp etition are more complex. We show that, in the absence of ideology,

comp etition actually reinforces the adverse e ects of spin on accuracy. Not only do the

media outlets bias news rep orting, but the stories reinforce eachother. As each pap er

spins stories, it increases the incentives of later outlets to spin. This piling on of stories

means non-ideological comp etition worsens the bias of spin. Moreover, spin can exac-

erbate the in uence of one-sided ideology. When the rst news outlet that uncovers

the story is ideological and later ones are not, the rst one sets the tone and later ones

reinforce this spin. This can explain why and how inside sources leak information to

news outlets: their principal motivation is to control how the story is eventually spun.

Our theory of news rep orting falls between two extremes. The traditional view

is that readers demand, and media outlets supply, pure information ab out p olitical

and economic markets, and thereby facilitate b etter consumer and voter choice (Coase

1974, Besley and Burgess 2001, Besley and Prat 2002, Djankovetal. 2002, Stromb erg

1

2001, Dyck and Zingales 2002). The opp osite but also plausible view, pursued by

Mencken (1920) and Jensen (1976), sees the media as entertainment, with no obvious

grounding in . The p ersp ective of this pap er is that media outlets provide neither

unadulterated information, nor pure entertainment. News outlets may be biased for

ideological reasons. And consumers, while not desiring pure entertainment as mightbe

the case with sensational or human interest stories, do indirectly a ect news content

1

Dyck and Zignales (2002) go further and examine how private incentives might bias corp orate news

rep orting. 3

b ecause of how they pro cess information. So for reasons of ideology news outlets may

bias information to please their owners, and for reasons of consumer psychology they

may bias the information to please their readers.

These results have signi cant implications for media accuracy. They explain, in

particular, how the media in the aggregate are likely to get to the bottom of a news

story with signi cant ideological dimension. Ideological diversityserves as a safeguard

against spin. Our results are consistent with Richard Posner's (1999) highly favorable

assessment of in the coverage of the Clinton a air. Our results also showwhy

media bias is most severe in the cases where no or little ideological diversity b ears on

the story, suchas the investigation of Wen Ho Lee. In this case, the bias comes from

spin, and spin causes the followers to pile on. Comp etition among media outlets is not

a solution to the problem of spin - indeed, it makes the problem worse. Our pap er

makes the case for extreme ideological diversity in the media - in suchdiversityliesthe

2

b est hop e against spin.

2 Mo del Setup

3

There are two players: the newspap er and the reader. The newspap er is either go o d

or bad. A go o d newspap er has access to some information that the reader wants. A

4

bad newspap er, on the other hand, has no useful information. The reader uses the

newspap er to improve his estimate of some value t. We b egin by assuming that t is

a single real numb er. This value could be many things: for example, the quality of a

2

p olitician or the nancial health of a rm. The common prior is t  N (0; ), .e. t is

2

normally distributed with variance  .

There are three p erio ds. In the rst p erio d, the reader receives a signal r ab out

the truth. This signal re ects the reader's prejudice ab out the topic b efore he reads

2

At a more level, this pap er is part of a broader on the interaction b etween comp etition

and individual psychology, e.g. Russell and Thaler (1985), De Long et. al. (1990) and Camerer (1998).

3

For simplicity,we use this terminology of \newspap er" and \reader" but nothing we discuss is sp eci c

to this . Our analysis applies to news outlets generally sp eaking.

4

A bad newspap er cannot manufacture stories to app ear go o d. We use these twotyp es merely as a way

to mo del the incentives of the go o d newspap er to create memorable stories. If no stories are rememb ered

the newspap er is p erceived to b e bad and loses subscrib ers. 4

the newspap er. This prejudice could b e shap ed by basic b eliefs ab out how the world

op erates. For example, in the Wen Ho Lee case readers may have started with the

presumption that the Chinese are likely to be spying on the U.S. Alternatively, this

signal may itself be the result of other newspap er stories or rumors the person has

5

heard. In short, r is summary of the reader's prior convictions and prejudices b efore

he reads the newspap er. The signal r is a noisy estimate of the truth, so

r = t + e

r

2

where e is distributed normally N (0; ). The reader uses this signal to up date his

r

r

b eliefs.

The newspap er may also receive a signal. Go o d newspap ers receive a signal for sure

and bad newspap ers receive no signal. The signal they receive is denoted n and equals

the truth plus some noise: n = t + e , where e is normally distributed with variance

n n

2

 . Though we make n uni-dimensional for simplicity, one can think of n as really a

n

bundle of facts.

In the second p erio d, the newspap er decides what to rep ort. A bad newspap er has

no news to rep ort. A go o d newspap er, in contrast, has news n which it may mo dify

b efore rep orting. Let s denote this mo di cation, so the pap er rep orts  = n + s.

We are thinking of a newspap er receiving a lot of facts ab out a particular issue, all

p otentially p ointing in somewhat di erent directions, and needing to distill them into

a memorable story. We think of the mo di cation s not as invention or fabrication of

new facts, but rather as a way to emphasize some facts, and de-emphasize others, so

the readers extract from the story a synthesized b ottom line.

Manipulation of information can take avariety of forms. In some countries, news-

pap ers just make up facts to corrob orate their stories, but we do not b elieve that this

phenomenon is imp ortant in the U.S. Rather, we are mo deling the situation where a

newspap er biases stories in more subtle ways. Rep orts can ignore or omit information

inconsistent with the message of the story, \build up" information sources that corrob-

orate the story, ignore or undermine information sources that contradict the message,

5

We formally study this second case when we consider multiple newspap ers. 5

or use colorful but misleading language and images that supp ort the story. These

typ es of information manipulation need not involve inaccuracies, but at the same time

address \the narrative imp erative".

Mo di cation is costly to the newspap er. First, it requires costly story-telling and

research necessary to b olster the theme of the rep ort. Second, and far more imp ortantly,

b oth the newspap ers and the rep orters that work for them care ab out accuracy, and

excessive mo di cation of the news raises the risk of b eing wrong. Let c(n  )denotethe

0

cost of mo difying the news We assume that c(0) = 0 and that sig n(c (x)) = sig n(x) > 0

00

and c (x)=0, lim c(x)=1 and lim c(x)=0. These assumptions mean that

x!1 x!0

manipulation, in either direction, is costly to the newspap er.

In the third period, the reader reads the story. He then combines what he reads

^

with his priors to an assessment of t. De ne this b elief to be t. After b eliefs are

formed, the reader may forget the story or not. If he rememb ers the story, he presumes

the newspap er is go o d. If he do es not he presumes the pap er is bad.

2.1 Reader Psychology

The mo del turns on how we assume readers form beliefs and remember information.

At one extreme, we might supp ose p eople form Bayesian b eliefs and have p erfect recall.

In this case, after reading the news  , the individual up dates and forms b eliefs:

^

t = r + k ( r )

1

2



n

. where k is a constantthatequals

2 2 1

 +

r n

But this Bayesian framework do es not allow us to think ab out the media's desire to

tell a story. To understand reader's demand for \stories", we consider a mo del where

readers think in coarse categories rather that in precise ne-tuned priors (Mullainathan

2002). Coarse categories capture the idea that readers carry away general impressions

of the situation rather than tracking all the details. In our simple case of a one-

dimensional signal, the coarse categories may be something like \go o d" and \bad".

Clinton is either a p ersecuted mo dern man or a villain. Wen Ho Lee is a spy or a

victim. In more complicated situations with more dimensions, the categories would b e 6

more nuanced. But the \go o d" and \bad" in our simple one-dimensional case captures

the imp ortant feature of categorization: readers have coarse rather than ne-tuned

b eliefs. Sp eci cally, de ne t and t to be the p ositive and negative categories and

+

6

assume these are symmetric in that t = t . Denote the categorical thinker's b eliefs

+

^

to b e t . We assume that he b elieves in the category closest to what the Bayesian would

c

b elieve. In this context, that means that he b elieves t when the Bayesian would have

+

b elieved a p ositive t andhecho oses t if the Bayesian would have exp ected a negative

t. Formally:

8

>

<

^

t if t>0

+

^

t = (1)

c

>

:

^

t if t<=0

For example, supp ose the reader has several pieces of evidence most of which suggest

Wen Ho Lee is a spy but some of which suggest the scap e-goated him.

A categorical thinker walks away having placed Wen Ho Lee in the spy category,

7

essentially collapsing his information into this simply summary.

A key feature of story telling is that stories need to be memorable. To capture

this idea, we assume that readers forget some of the stories they read. Sp eci cally,

we assume that the reader selectively forgets information that is inconsistent with his

8

category. This selective recall is an extension of the reader holding coarse b eliefs. He

recalls data that justify these coarse b eliefs. In the ab ove example, once the categorical

thinker places Wen Ho Lee in the spy category, he is less likely to remember stories

9

which suggest that the government scap e-goated him. Formally,we assume that recall

probabilities are a function of consistency with the reader's category after he reads the

^

story. So a story is more likely to be rememb ered if sig n( )=sig n(t ). Sp eci cally,

c

inconsistent stories have probability f of b eing rememb ered and consistent stories have

6

Allowing more categories do es not change the results.

7

It is worth noting that not every category or story-line is equally likely. The background for any particular

news item determines which stories t. The purp ose of our mo del is not to elucidate exactly howany one

story is spun, but to understand how the narrative imp erativeinteracts with comp etition.

8

Several psychology exp eriments suggest that category consistent information is more likely to b e remem-

b ered than category inconsistent information. This is discussed in greater detail in Mullainathan (2002).

9

One mightwonder whether extreme incosistent stories would also b e remembered. In this -up, they

would b e if they are big enough to change the reader's category. In this case, they b ecome consistent with the

new category. If they are inconsistent but not enough to change the reader's mind, then they are discarded

since they don't t the simpli ed, summary world-view of the reader. 7

^

probability 1 of b eing rememb ered. Denote this probability of recall as (; t ).

c

In this pap er, we examine what these two di erent assumptions ab out reader psy-

chology imply for media bias. We consider b oth Bayesian and categorical readers not

b ecause we think readers are one or the other typ e. Instead this split allows us to

make clear which results are driven by reader psychology and which are driven bythe

structure of comp etition itself.

2.2 Newspap er Payo s

A newspap er's payo dep ends on several factors. First, it dep ends on whether the

newspap er is p erceived to b e go o d, since presumably go o d newspap ers sell b etter. The

pap er receives a payo  if it is thought to be go o d and zero otherwise, where  is

the capitalized value of the incremental pro ts from b eing rememb ered. Second, the

newspap er mayhave an ideology  whichiseither0,+1or 1. A newspap er with an

ideology of +1 prefers to rep ort p ositive stories whereas a newspap er with an ideology of

1 prefers to rep ort negative stories. We assume the newspap er recevies an ideological

b ene t equal to   . In this sense measures the intensity of the newspap er's ideology.

10

We further assume that readers form inferences ignoring the newspap er's ideology.

When readers are Bayesian, there is no confusion of go o d or bad newspap ers since

all stories are rememb ered. A go o d newspap er no matter what it rep orts has its story

rememb ered and is recognized as go o d. And by assumption a bad newspap er can never

app ear go o d. A go o d newspap er therefore receives a payo of:

 +   c(n  )

and a bad newspap er receives a payo of:

  c(n  )

When readers are categorical, however, go o d newspap ers can be confused with

bad ones. If a go o d newspap er's story is forgotten, it is thought of as a bad one.

10

This assumption is merely to simplify the calculations. Atthe opp osite extreme, readers would know

and recognize these and would de-bias stories b efore incorp orating them into b eliefs. Media biases

would have no e ect on b eliefs at all. Our assumption is a simple version of the more realistic case where

readers partly but not fully recognize the bias. 8

Readers presume that, since they remember no story, the pap er must have been bad

11

and rep orted nothing. A go o d newspap er's exp ected payo therefore dep ends on the

probability of recall in this case:

^

  (; t )+   c(n  ) (2)

c

A bad newspap er is never confused for a go o d one. Even when its stories are remem-

b ered they are seen as worthless. Consequently its payo is as b efore:

  c(n  )

With these payo s, it is clear why categorical thinking provides a non-ideological

reason for newspap ers to manipulate stories. Newspap ers want their stories to b e mem-

orable b ecause the reader who do es not remember any story presumes the newspap er

12

to b e bad. To b e memorable, a newspap er then has an incentive to alter its story so

13

that it b etter ts the readers' category. In the Wen Ho Lee case, unless the newspa-

p er can change the reader's mind, it has an incentive to rep ort a story consistent with

the reader's categorization of Wen Ho Lee as a spy.

It is worth noting that this sp eci c mo del is only one way to op erationalize the

elementofreaderpsychology westress. What is critical to us is that the reader values

stories which match his b eliefs except when these stories are so large as to change b eliefs.

In our mo del this preference arises indirectly b ecause of the di erential memorability

of stories, but there are other ways to mo del it. An alternative is that readers su er

from con rmatory bias: they dismiss stories that are inconsistent with what they

b elieve (Lord, Ross and Lepp er 1979). In fact, our mo del could be reinterpreted in

11

Thus a newspap er's quality (i.e. whether it is good) is assessed solely through recall. We could have

allowed quality to be also assessed by how close the newspap er was to the eventual truth, but chose not

to for simplicity. All this do es is to create an added force for the newspap er to reveal its signal with no

manipulation. But in the current mo del, the cost of manipulating the signal serves the same purp ose. It is

worth noting that even if the newspap er is judged only on distance from the nal truth, it still has a motive

to make stories memorable since it receives no credit for b eing correct if nob o dy rememb ers what it rep orted.

12

One could get similar results by making the less drastic assumption that readers \rationally" infer that

the pap er might have b een good and they simply forgot the story. Even in this case a forgotten story

increases the readers' p erceived likeliho o d that the pap er is bad and as suchhurts its payo .

13

This could happ en through several mechanisms. First, editors may use their control to directly spin

stories. Second, rep orters may resp ond to or owner preferences by trying to write memorable

stories to raise their pro le within the pap er. 9

this light. Supp ose that readers nd it easy to dismiss mo derately inconsistent news

but not grossly inconsistent news. In this case, we can reinterpret the recall function

as a dismissal function. When the reader dismisses news as fallacious, he presumes

the pap er is bad, which is isomorphic to presuming that a newspap er whose story has

been forgotten is bad. Similarly,the fact that very big stories cannot b e dismissed is

equivalent to the fact that categorical thinkers change their mind to big enough news

14

and hence remember the story. This re-interpretation pro duces the same results as

ours. Once again newspap ers with mildly inconsistent news bias stories so as not to b e

dismissed. But for big news, they do not fear dismissal and rep ort the news accurately.

Wechose the mo del with recall and categorization for two reasons. First, it b etter

matches descriptive accounts of the media, which suggest that newspap ers are inter-

ested in writing a comp elling story. The commonly used phrase \narrative imp erative"

captures exactly the pressure newspap ers feel to distill complicated situations into a

simple message. They cater to reader's prior prejudices b ecause this is one easy way

to make stories memorable. Second, our sp eci cation provides a b etter framework

for thinking ab out what kinds of spin o ccur. Newspap ers attempt to spin stories so

that they b etter t a particular category. Nevertheless, aside from interpretation, the

results we provide b elow are the same with the alternative mo del as well.

3 Results

3.1 Two Typ es of Bias

We b egin with the case where the reader is Bayesian and there is only one newspap er.

Here, the newspap er has only one reason to bias the news: if it has an ideology it wants

to pursue. If it has no ideology, it gains nothing from manipulating the news. The rst

15

prop osition formalizes this idea.

14

Sp eci cally one would replace the recall function in equation 2 with a dismissal function that is non-

linear. The proability of dismissal would b e increasing as the news is further from priors until it gets large

enough at which p oint the probability of dismissal would diminish.

15

All pro ofs are in the app endix. 10

Prop osition 1 If the newspaper has no ideology ( =0), then it does not manipulate

news:  = n. If it has an ideology, then it wants to manipulate news in the direction of

its ideology so that sig n( n)=sig n( ). The magnitude of manipulation is increasing

in the strength of the ideology ( ) and decreasing in the size of the news (jnj) and in

the cost of manipulation (c()).

This prop osition suggests one source of bias: the p olitical ideology of the newspap er.

But when agents are categorical thinkers, another bias may arise. Newspap ers may

manipulate news not b ecause of their p olitical ideology but b ecause they cater to

readers' interests. The pap er wants to have its story rememb ered and, therefore, may

manipulate news stories to make them more memorable. The following prop osition

formalizes this notion of spin.

Prop osition 2 When the reader is a categorical thinker, the newspaper biases the

news even when it has no ideology ( = 0). If it biases news, it does so in one of

two ways. First, if the news is smal l enough and inconsistent with priors, it biases the

story towards priors. Second, if the news is large enough and inconsistent with priors,

it biases the story away from priors in an attempt to change the reader's category.

A simple example illustrates this prop osition. Supp ose the reader b elieves 2 and the

newspap er receives a signal 1. Supp ose the newspap er rep orts the truth in this case.

Since 1 is not enough to switch b eliefs, the categorical reader continues to b elieve

16

t . But since the story that the newspap er rep orted is negative, it contradicts the

+

nal category and therefore has a go o d chance of being forgotten. The newspap er

therefore has an incentive to alter the story to make it p ositive and therebymorelikely

to be remembered. In other words, if the news is not enough to change the reader's

mind, the pap er has an incentive to spin it to match the reader's prior convictions.

But if the signal is large enough, the newspap er may want to go against b eliefs.

In the ab ove example, if the newspap er sees a signal of -3, it knows that by rep orting

the truth it can change the reader's mind. Once the reader's mind is changed, the

1

16

. And assume for nowthattherelativevariances of noise and signal are equal so that k =

1

2 11

news story and category match and therefore the story is rememb ered. In this case the

newspap er no longer has the incentive to spin the story to increase memorability.

These two prop ositions emphasize that underlying the notion of media bias there

are really two distinct phenomena. One is driven by the p olitical ideology of the

newspap er and arises from an attempt to convince the public of a particular view-

point. The other bias is driven by an attempt to app eal to the reader in our case by

creating a memorable story. This kind of \spin" is merely an attempt by the newspap er

to cater to the reader's psychological make-up.

3.2 Comp etition

In this section, we consider whether comp etition delivers . Sp eci -

cally,we ask whether the reader who wants to get to the b ottom of a story by reading

and listening to all the media outlets covering it in the end obtains unbiased infor-

mation. An economist might reason that comp etition between media outlets should

eliminate media bias and lead to suchrevelation of the truth.

To investigate this issue, we consider the case where multiple newspap ers instead

of just one rep ort the news. Supp ose there are N of them. Each newspap er releases

news in a sequential manner with newspap er indexed 1 releasing rst, followed bythe

one indexed 2 and so on. Each newspap er receives an indep endent signal ab out the

truth and rep orts on this signal. Moreover, for simplicity, assume all newspap ers are

identical in that they have the same cost functions and receive signals of the same

precision; at most they di er in their ideologies.

The reader reads all the newspap ers and aggregates the stories sequentially. He

forms a category after each news story bycombining what he reads with the stories he

rememb ers and his priors. After the new category is formed, the reader rememb ers the

news story if it is consistent with his new category and do es not if it is inconsistent. If

the story is rememb ered (or forgotten) it is rememb ered (or forgotten) p ermanently.

The assumption that the reader reads all stories is intended to describ e a reader

who is exp osed to multiple media outlets either b ecause he generally uses multiple

sources or b ecause he searches them out to understand a particular story. Assuming 12

exp osure to multiple sources is a necessary feature of any mo del of comp etition b ecause

that is the source of comp etition. If readers are in contrast isolated and read only one

source, we would simply apply the results of the previous section and assume it is a

case of lo cal monop oly. In what follows, when we sp eak of the numb er of newspap ers,

17

we mean the numb er that the reader is actually exp osed to.

Finally,we assume that newspap er payo s are indep endent. That is, a newspap er

receives the same payo  for b eing p erceived as go o d indep endentof the number of

other newspap ers. The e ects of comp etition we discuss arise purely from information

aggregation rather than structure.

Supp ose that agents are Bayesian. If newspap ers have di erent enough ideologies,

the average news story is an unbiased estimate of the truth. Each newspap er may bias

news towards its ideology but these di erences wash out in the aggregate.

Prop osition 3 Suppose agents are Bayesian and the number of having a

positive ideology is the same as the number of newspapers having a negative ideology.

Then in aggregate there is no bias in beliefs. That is, the reader's beliefs after reading

al l the newspaper stories ( ) are the same as if he could see the true news (n) himself.

If there are enough left-wing and enough right-wing pap ers, the truth ab out Clinton

emerges. Each side may exaggerate the story in its preferred direction, but these

exaggerations cancel out.

While comp etition eliminates the bias caused by ideology, it do es little to reduce

spin, the bias caused by categorization. To understand why this is the case, note that

each newspap er rep orting a story still feels the need to go along with the reader's priors.

But now that e ect is reinforced b ecause each newspap er knows that future newspap ers

will also cater to the reader's b eliefs at the time. Since each of the prior newspap ers has

biased the news, the reader is now stronger in his b eliefs. Each newspap er, therefore,

feels an even greater pressure to bias toward priors.

17

This caveat must b e kept in mind when interpreting our results on ideological comp etition. In our mo del,

ideological comp etition refers to comp etition within the set of news-pap ers a reader reads. If every reader

is segmented to a particular ideological pap er, then ideological diversitywould of course create an adverse

e ect on accuracy which is not in this mo del. But rememb er that we are interested in the case of a motivated

reader who is trying to get to the truth by consulting many sources. 13

Prop osition 4 Suppose agents arecategorical and newspapers have no ideology. Then

there always exists a constant k such that if each newspaper receives news n smal ler

i

than k , newspapers continue to bias news towards priors. In this case, agents con-

tinue to believe in false facts even with an arbitrarily large numbers of news-stories.

Moreover, a newspaper has greater incentives to spin the story with competition than

without.

This Prop osition applies to stories where newspap ers have no ideology. For example,

newspap ers mayhave had little ideological interest in characterizing Wen Ho Lee as a

spy. In this case wewould interpret what happ ened as a piling on by the newspap ers.

If readers b egan with a mo derate prior that the Chinese are spying on the U.S., then

the rst newspap er has an incentive to spin the story in this direction. This reinforces

the prior and increases the incentive of the next newspap er to spin its story in the same

direction, further reinforcing the b elief. Each newspap er piles on to this particular spin,

18

making it more likely that successive newspap ers follow suit. Unless a newspap er

receives some extremely comp elling evidence that Wen Ho Lee is not a spy, the piling

19

on results in a very biased outcome.

The prop osition also applies to some cases where newspap ers have an ideology if

the rep orters themselves do not have one and the editors exercise little control. Most

notably, on smaller p olitical issues, even if newspap er editors have particular ideologies,

editors will not nd it worthwhile to control exactly howeach story is written.

To summarize, comp etition do es not necessarily remove media bias. If the bias is

due to the ideology of newspap ers, then increasing the diversity of opinions helps get

the truth out. But if the bias is spin, then comp etition only exaggerates it and keeps

18

The assumption that a story's recall is determined by the category after it is read is imp ortant for this

result. If recall were determined solely by the nal category (after reading all the news), then newspap ers

would not want to cater to priors. Instead they would want to cater to their best guess of the p osteriors

that will eventually materialize.

19

These results are analogous to the literature on herding (Banerjee 1992, Bikchandani, Hirshleifer and

Welch 1992 and Scharfstein and Stein 1990). An alternativeway to generate simple herding by newspap ers

is to sp ecify that rep orters simply rehash what others havesaidto savethe cost of having to go out and

generate new information. While this might b e happ ening, this kind of herding is qualitatively di erentfrom

that in our mo del. In our mo del, newspap ers are not simply rep eating what others have said, they are in

fact exaggerating the new news to t the story. Thus in contrast to simple herding explanations, there is

new \news" pro duced each p erio d; sometimes it is just rep orted in a way that is biased towards priors. 14

aggregate information away from the truth.

3.3 Interaction between Spin and Ideology

In a comp etitive environment, spin and ideology interact in interesting ways. First,

when agents are categorical, the bias from ideology can be exaggerated by spin. Con-

sider the case where the rst newspap er rep orting the story has an ideology and other

newspap ers do not. The rst newspap er knows that, by manipulating its story, not

only is it a ecting b eliefs to day, it is also a ecting future rep orting. The following

prop osition formalizes this idea.

Prop osition 5 Suppose that there are two newspapers, one of which has an ideology

and the other of which does not. If agents arecategorical thinkers and each newspaper

receives only a smal l bit of news, then the aggregate bias is more in the direction of the

ideological newspaper if it reports rst.

This result emphasizes the case where a single ideological newspap er can bias stories

in a particular way and exploit later newspap ers' desire to be consistent with priors.

Prop osition 5 has one imp ortant implication, namely the opp ortunity for p oliticians

themselves to control spin. If a p olitician can get out his story to a friendly newspap er

rst, and thereby create a particular image of himself or his prop osals, future newspa-

p ers will b e in uenced by the priors created by this rst story. As a consequence, the

image will stick, comp etition notwithstanding.

To formalize this intuition, supp ose we are in a setup where there are a N newspa-

p ers without any ideology. Now supp ose there is a third party, called the source, who

can leak information to one of these newspap ers. The source receives a payo if the

reader b elieves a p ositivevalue. The source knows his signal value as well as the true

value of the parameter. For simplicity, supp ose that he can cho ose which newspap er to

release the information to. The chosen newspap er receives no other signal that p erio d.

In this framework, the following is true.

Prop osition 6 If the signal is too negative, the source never releases it. If the signal

is positive, the source releases it to the rst newspaper. 15

The rst part is very intuitive. The source has no incentivetoreveal negative informa-

tion since his payo dep ends on the public having a p ositive p erception. The second

result clearly follows from Prop osition 5. By giving the rst newspap er the story, the

source maximally b ene ts from the piling on e ect. Later newspap ers spin stories

consistent with his initial message.

Prop osition 5 and 6 fo cus on cases with no ideological comp etition, where newspa-

p ers passively accept the early spin b ecause they have no ideologies of their own. The

following prop osition shows that when newspap ers' ideologies are very di erent, the

incentive for newspap ers to pile on to the early spin falls.

Prop osition 7 Suppose the number of newspapers with a positive ideology equals the

number with a negative ideology and that agents arecategorical thinkers. As the strength

of ideologies ( ) increases, newspapers' incentives to spin stories decreases and the total

amount of bias in reporting decreases.

Prop osition 7 is p erhaps the crucial result of the pap er. It shows that newspap er ideol-

ogy, far from b eing a problem to b e lamented, is in fact crucial for accuracy in media.

Without ideological diversity, spin causes newspap ers to pile on, and to sacri ce accu-

racy in order to rep ort memorable stories. When newspap ers have di erent ideologies,

however, the comp etitive pressures to follow the leader are countered by the pressures

of ideology. Ideological diversityisanantidote to spin.

4 Case Studies

These results ab out media bias can b e crisply illustrated in two case studies. The rst,

involving NBA star Allen Iverson, highlights how non-ideological media outlets spin

stories to b e consistent with pre-existing categories. The second, involving academics

Lawrence Summers and Cornel West, illustrates how ideological bias of newspap ers

can undo the e ects of spin. Each of these examples also gives a sense of the exact

mechanisms through which newspap ers bias stories. 16

4.1 Allen Iverson

4.1.1 Facts

On July 7, 2002, following the previous day's rep ort in the Daily News,

rep orted that 76ers guard Allen Iverson was being investigated

by the p olice for threatening two men at a West Philadelphia apartment complex in

the middle of the night of July 3rd. The p olice said that the complainants did not

allege that they were physically assaulted. Iverson is an outstanding basketball player,

who had earlier brushes with the law. He is also known for his taste for argument and

for skipping practices, as well as well as for a $50 million contract with Reeb ok for

sho es.

On July 10, 2002, the story explo ded with the 1st page rep ort in the Philadelphia

Inquirer that the p olice are to push for charges against Iverson. In the next several

days, characterizations of what transpired on July 3 b ecame increasingly evo cative.

According to the rep orts, Iverson had a ght with his wife Tawanna, and around mid-

night\kicked her out" of their $2.4 million \mansion", either \naked" or \half-naked."

A few hours later, he and his uncle, Gregory Iverson, wenttolookforTawanna and a

relative, Shaun Bowman, in Bowman's apartment. Neither was there, but Bowman's

ro ommate Charles Jones, and Jones's neighb or Hakim Carey, were in the apartment.

According to the news stories, Iverson \stormed into," \forced his wayinto," \barged

into," or \burst into" the apartment, lo oking for his wife and in the pro cess \threaten-

ing two men with a gun" and \making terroristic threats." Several hours after Iverson

left, Jones called the p olice. On July 11, the District Attorney charged Iverson with

4 felonies and 10 lesser o enses, including criminal trespass, conspiracy, assault, and

terroristic threats, which could \add up to a maximum of 70 years in prison."

Over the following several days, the media a orded this \alleged armed assault"

the extensive and thorough coverage it required. At some p oint, the New York Times

and other outlets rep orted that p olice found \broken glass and smeared blo o d" inside

avehicle frequently driven byIverson's wife, but it later turned out to b e \unidenti ed

substance," probably ketchup. Iverson was resoundingly criticized, with commentators 17

lamenting that the NBA p enalties for felonious players are insuciently harsh. \Iverson

Fouls Out," said Op ed.

Then, at a preliminary court hearing on July 29, the judge threw out all criminal

charges except two misdemeanor counts of \making terroristic threats" against Iverson.

It transpired that Iverson actually paid the rent on the Bowman/Jones apartment, and

had the righttoenter it. Hakim Carey admitted that he did not see Iverson brandish

a gun and that he lied to the p olice at Jones's request. Jones admitted that he talked

to a p ersonal injury lawyer b efore calling the p olice 10.5 hours after his encounter with

Iverson. Bowman also testi ed that, following the incident, Jones tried to blackmail

Iverson. In dismissing the charges, the municipal court judge describ ed the case as \a

relative lo oking for a relative in the house of a relative." Eventually, the remaining

two chargers against Iverson were also dropp ed.

4.1.2 Analysis

Other than its obvious , the Iverson coverage illustrates three p oints

ab out our mo del. First, it shows how comp etition b etween the newspap ers results in

piling on, with no evident interest in considering alternative p ossibilities. The story

ab out Iverson t the readers' priors ab out him and all the newspap ers were happyto

tell it. Because of his dress, demeanor, race and past, Iverson is often describ ed with

phrases such as \thug " or \gangster image". Kicking his wife out naked and

then breaking into an inner- apartment brandishing a gun is quite consistent with

this category. Second, even if one reads the rep orts chronologically, without knowing

the end, it is striking how non-credible Iverson's accusers app ear (Mullainathan raised

this with Shleifer before the court hearing on July 29). The p olice - and the press -

knew from the very b eginning ab out the 10.5 hour delay in Jones' 911 call. Residents

of the very apartment building noted the accusers' shady p ersonalities, identifying one

of them as a known con man. Yet none of the national press we saw app ears to have

considered the identity of the accusers, and their p ossible interests, presumably b ecause

this line of inquiry could not have b olstered the story b eing told. Finally,theIverson

coverage demonstrates very clearly the \ rst mover advantage" in rep orting. The story 18

was leaked to the press by the p olice, which itself did most of the sensationalizing, and

was obviously lo oking for . The press did not makeanything up; it only to ok

the story b eing o ered and spun it.

4.2 Summers and West

4.2.1 Facts

On Decemb er 22, 2001, Boston Glob e rep orted that, according to Harvard faculty mem-

bers, the University's PresidentLawrence Summers \rebuked [Afro-American Studies

Professor Cornel] West for leading the p olitical committee for Rev. Al Sharpton's

p ossible presidential campaign, and for writing more likely to be reviewed in

The New York Times than in academic journals. He also rep ortedly criticized West

for allowing grade in ation in his intro ductory course on black studies." The Glob e

rep orted that, after the Octob er meeting between Summers and West in which the

conversation to ok place, several Afro-American studies professors, Harvard's \dream

team," were thinking of leaving for Princeton. Summers was describ ed as \a bull in

a China shop" who had not emphasized the imp ortance of diversity as clearly as his

predecessor.

In the following week, the coverage of the controversy explo ded, all of it complimen-

tary to West and critical of Summers. The New York Times ran stories on December

29 and January 4, the Glob e on Decemb er 31, and January 2, 3, 4, and 5. The stories

rep orted that b oth Jesse Jackson and Al Sharpton b ecame involved, the latter threat-

ening to sue Harvard as \an aggrieved p erson." On January 4, the Glob e describ ed

Summers as Harvard's \embattled new president" and summarized the Octob er events

in stark terms: \Summers called West to his oce and in a private meeting insulted

the 48-year-old professor, raising questions ab out his scholarship, grade in ation in his

classes, his cutting a rap CD, and his supp ort for the presidential campaign of Reverend

Al Sharpton, professors close to West said."

Then, on January 5, wrote a story making fun of West and his CD

(sample lyric: \No other people in the mo dern world have had such unprecedented 19

levels of regulated violence against them") and suggesting that \Mr. Summers clearly

has a p oint." The Wall Street Journal joined the coverage, with an editorial critical of

West on January 7, and a piece on January 8 calling West an academic \lightweight."

The coverage continued into the Spring - sympathetic to West in the Boston Glob e

and the New York Times, sympathetic to Summers in the Wall Street Journal and the

New Republic. On January 20 the Glob e describ ed the tension, explaining that West

is a pre-eminent blackintellectual to his admirers, and a charlatan in a three piece suit

to his critics. Finally, in mid-April, West decided to move to Princeton, announcing his

decision on National Public , and calling Summers \Ariel Sharon of American

higher education". Press reaction to West's departure to Princeton divided along

the previous ideological lines, with the Glob e lamenting that \the impact of West's

departure will hit Harvard hard," and the New Republic blasting him with a sarcastic

\Congratulations Princeton. You haveyour public ."

4.2.2 Analysis

The Summers-West saga, like the Iverson example, illustrates the workings of the

narrative imp erative, and the pile on suggested by our mo del. Consistent with our

mo del, none of the articles in the early coverage showed b oth sides of the story until

the Economist and the Wall Street Journal questioned whether the claims made by

West and his supp orters were true or whether Summers mighthave had a p oint. But

far more imp ortantly, the ideological divide of the press ultimately assured that b oth

sides were eventually presented to the public: with the Boston Glob e and the New York

Times presenting the lib eral p ersp ective, and the Economist, the Wall Street Journal,

and the New Republic the conservative one. It is precisely because of the ideological

comp etition that a reader could if he wished b e exp osed to b oth p ersp ectives.

The Iverson example thus illustrates the workings of Prop osition 5 - the piling on

without an ideological dimension, whereas the Summers - West story illustrates Prop o-

sition 7 - the presentation of b oth sides when ideology is recruited. This analysis, how-

ever, raises a deep er issue: why did the Summers-West story b ecome ideological, while

the Iverson one did not? One can imagine, for example, the lib eral media worrying 20

that the all out attackonIverson by the Philadelphia p olice was racist, and taking his

side in the coverage. Likewise, one can imagine the conservative press never entering

on the side of Summers, who after all is a former Treasury Secretary in the Demo cratic

administration of . West was not help ed by Jesse Jackson and Al Sharpton

entering his dispute with Summers, so the conservative press saw red and the story

b ecame ideological. Had it not, the coverage would have remained utterly one-sided.

5 Conclusion

When do careful consumers of comp etitive media sources come away with an accurate

picture of facts? In this pap er, we try to answer this question by fo cusing on twosources

of media bias: ideology and spin. We show that, in the absence of spin, comp etition

undo es the biases from ideology. However, in the absence of ideology, comp etition only

20

promotes the biases from spin.

These results help shed light on the kinds of issues where we exp ect accuracy in the

media, at least in the aggregate. For news that have signi cant right-left ideological

dimensions, such as presidential elections, comp etitive media are likely to pro duce

accurate rep orting, on average. On the other hand, for news that do not have such a

dimension, such as cases involving law enforcement or many asp ects of foreign p olicy,

spin rather than ideological diversityislikely to shap e comp etitive rep orting. For such

stories, comp etition do es not eliminate the media bias, and there is no go o d reason to

exp ect accuracy in media.

20

This reasoning resembles Becker's (1956) analysis of racial discrimination. He argues that comp etition

eliminates discrimination derived from employer preferences, but not discrimination derived from consumer

preferences. In our case, media bias that is driven by pro ducer preferences{ the p olitical bias of a media

outlet{is eliminated by comp etition. But media bias driven by consumers{the need to tell a simple story{is

reinforced by comp etition. Of course to interpret our results in a broader supply and demand framework,

one would need to understand whether the supply of media outlets' ideology is itself a resp onse to reader

demand. 21

References

Banerjee, Abhijit, 1992. \A Simple Mo del of Herd Behavior," Quarterly Journal of

Economics, 107(3), pp. 797-818.

Becker, Gary, 1956. The Economics of Discrimination. University of Chicago

Press.

Besley, Timothy and Robin Burgess, 2001, \The Political EconomyofGovernment

Resp onsiveness: Theory and Evidence from India," mimeo, LSE.

Besley, Timothy and Andrea Prat, 2001. \Handcu s for the Grabbing Hand? Media

Capture and Government Accountability," mimeo, LSE.

Bikchandani, Sushil, David Hirshleifer and Ivo Welch, 1992. \A Theory of Fads,

Fashion, Custom, and Cultural Change as Informational Cascades, " Journal of Polit-

ical Economy, 100 (5), pp. 992-1026.

Camerer, Colin, 1998. \Can asset markets be manipulated? A eld exp eriment

with racetrack b etting." Journal of Political Economy, 106 (3), pp. 457{482.

Coase, Ronald, 1974. \The Market for Go o ds and the Market for Ideas," American

Economic Review, 64(2), pp. 384-91.

De Long, Brad, Andrei Shleifer, 1990, Lawrence Summers and Rob ert Waldmann,

\Noise Trader Risk in Financial Markets," Journal of Political Economy, 98 (4), pp.

703-738.

Djankov, Simeon, Carlee McLiesh, Tatiana Nenova, and Andrei Shleifer, 2002.

\Who Owns the Media?" Journal of Law and Economics, forthcoming.

Dyck, Alexander and Luigi Zingales, 2002. \The Corp orate Governance Role of the

Media," mimeo, University of Chicago.

Goldb erg, Bernard, 2002 Bias: a CBS Insider Exposes How the Media Distort the

News,Washington, DC: Regnery Pub.

Jamieson, Kathleen Hall and Karlyn Kohrs Campb ell, 2002, The Interplay of In-

uence, Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thompson Learning.

Jensen, Michael, 1976. \Toward a Theory of the Press," mimeo, Harvard Business

Scho ol. 22

Lord, C. G., L. Ross and M. R. Lepp er, 1979. \Biased Assimilation and Attitude

Polarization: The E ect of Theories on Subsequently Considered Evidence, " Journal

of Personality and Social Psychology,37(11), pp. 2098-2109.

Mencken, H. L. 1975 [1920], A Gang of Pecksni s, New Ro chelle, NY: Arlington

House Publishers.

Mullainathan, Sendhil, 2002, \Thinking Through Categories," MIT mimeo ( rst

draft, 2000).

Posner, Richard 1999, An A air of State: The Investigation, Impeachment, and

Trial of President Clinton,Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard UniversityPress

Russell, Thomas and Richard Thaler, 1985. "The Relevance of Quasi Rationality

in Comp etitive Markets," American Economic Review,75(6),pp. 1071-1082.

Scharfstein, David S. and Stein, Jeremy, C., 1990. "Herd Behavior and Investment,"

American Economic Review. 80(3), pp. 465-479.

App endix

Pro of of Prop osition 1

Since agents are Bayesian, they remember everything they read. Consequently a

go o d newspap er with no ideology receives a payo of:

 c( n)

Since this is strictly decreasing in j nj, there is no incentive to manipulate. Hence

 = n.

An ideological newspap er receivesapayo :

 +   c( n)

Supp ose that  =+1. De ne s to b e  n. Di erentiating with resp ect to s gives the

rst order condition

0

k = c (s)

1

for some constant k (which is a function of the signal to noise ratios). Thus the extent

1

of manipulation (s) is increasing in . The same logic holds when  = 1. 23

Pro of of Prop osition 2. A go o d newspap er worries ab out b eing rememb ered.

When it has no ideology,itspayo is

^

(; t ) c(n  ))

c

Consider three cases. First, supp ose the news is consistent with priors. Then if the

newspap er rep orts truthfully its payo is  . Since it cannot do b etter than this, it has

no incentive to manipulate.

Second, supp ose that the news is inconsistent with priors but that if rep orted

truthfully it would cause a change of categories. Then truthful rep orting yields a

payo of  so the newspap er again has no incentive to manipulate.

Third, supp ose that the news is inconsistent with priors and that if rep orted truth-

fully it would not cause a change of categories. Now the news-pap er must decide

whether to manipulate. For simplicity, fo cus on the case where the reader's priors

are p ositive and the news story is negative. The newspap er has three choices: do not

manipulate, make the story p ositive or make it so negative that the reader changes

21

categories. No manipulation means that the pap er's payo is   f . Making the story

p ositive means b earing the cost c(n) and results in a payo of  c(n). Supp ose that

x is the size of news story the reader needs to change categories. Then making the

story very negative means getting a payo of  c(x n).

Putting all this together, the news-pap er biases news if

f < c(jnj; jx nj)

or when c(min(jnj; jx nj)) < (1 f ) . And if it cho oses to bias the news it biaes

x

p ositively if n> and negatively otherwise.

2

The same logic applies when priors are negative, proving the result.

Pro of of Prop osition 3. Any newspap er receives a payo of  c( n)+

    , which is indep endent of other newspap er's actions. If s is the bias  n,

then di erentiating with resp ect to s shows that there is an optimal bias of s > 0 for

+

p ositive ideology newspap ers and s < 0 for negative ideology newspap ers. And since

21

Any other kind of manipulation results in the pap er b earing the costs of manipulation with no gain in

recall. 24

c() is symmetric, s = s . If n are the news stories, the sum of the rep orted stories

+ i

P

equals n since the numb er of p ositive and negative newspap ers are equal.

i

Pro of of Prop osition 4. By the logic in Prop osition 2, if news is small enough

it is manipulated. Let x be the constant such that if jnj

22

is biased towards priors. Consider the rst newspap er. If it receives news of size less

than x,italways makes it consistent with priors.

Now consider the optimization problem of the second newspap er. It faces the same

problem as the rst newspap er except that the readers are even more convinced in

their priors b ecause in the rst newspap er's consistent news. Consequently, it also

manipulates news towards the reader's priors. In fact, the size of news for whichthe

second newspap er still manipulates is even larger b ecause of the reader's strengthened

b eliefs. This is the sense in which comp etition raises the incentivetospin.

Pro ceeding inductively,we see that each successive newspap er has an incentive to

bias the news if it is small enough.

Pro of of Prop osition 5. This follows from the logic of Prop osition 4. If the

ideological pap er rep orts rst, the neutral pap er has an incentive to spin toward the

p osteriors created by the ideological pap er. If the neutral pap er rep orts rst, however,

it only has an incentive to spin toward the priors. Consequently, b eliefs are more likely

to b e biased by ideological pap er if it rep orts rst.

Pro of of Prop osition 6. If the signal is very negative, reader b eliefs only get

more negative b ecause of the leak. Therefore, the source has no incentivetoleak. If the

signal is p ositive, by the logic in the pro of of Prop osition 4, the leak has a greater e ect

if released early. Later newspap ers are more likely to spin their signals consistently

with it.

Pro of of Prop osition 7. Consider the incentiveoftheany newspap er to spin a

story. It faces an incentive to spin the story as well as incentive to bias for ideological

reasons. The incentive to spin dep ends on the priors of the reader after having read all

previous newspap ers. Ideological bias, however, is indep endent of priors. Consequently,

as increases, the newspap er is less likely to spin, indep endent of what previous

22 0

Suchanx will always exist since c (x) ! 0asx ! 0 while the gain in b eing consistent is discrete. 25

newspap ers have done.

Since half the newspap ers are biased in one way and half are biased in the other,

the biases induced by ideology cancel as in Prop osition 3. Consequently, the total bias

decreases. 26