Science Series by Erik Meira

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Science Series by Erik Meira Science Series By Erik Meira Originally published as a 5 part series released over the course of 5 days, this is all 5 posts as one continuous thread. You can read the entire thread at ptpodcast.com/pt-inquest/science-series/ A little background. I am a science geek, I have been since I was a kid, long before I became a physical therapist. I also love philosophy, discourse, and reason and devoted a large amount of my time to this as an undergrad. When I hear physical therapists discuss Evidence-Based Practice, I find that many can sound really scientific but often make mistakes in logic – mistakes that science inherently avoids. Much of this has to do with a lack of understanding of the history of the philosophy of knowledge and how science accounts for these known issues of knowledge. So if you are not familiar with René Descartes, David Hume, William of Ockham, or Karl Popper – you may be missing something… I Think Therefore I Am Philosophers have sought to find absolute knowledge for centuries. Absolute knowledge is something that can be known with 100% certainty. This has always been difficult to define. Almost anything that could be claimed to be known would always result in some kind of challenge taking that certainty below 100%. One of the best examples of this is Meditations on First Philosophy published in 1641 by René Descartes. Meditations was an attempt by Descartes to break down all knowledge to only those things that we can know with absolute certainty and then build from there. I’m not going to give you a play by play of the entire treatise, you can download the book for free onto any computer or e-reader (all classical texts are free now). I’ll just jump to the conclusion – the butler did it. It is in Meditations that Descartes developed the “Evil Demon” argument. What he points out is that there could be an “Evil Demon” that cannot be known or perceived who alters all of our reality so that we cannot trust any of our senses. Of course this is an unreasonable belief, but how do we KNOW with 100% certainty that this is not the case? If you are uncomfortable with this antiquated concept, you may also imagine the more contemporary allegory known as thebrain in a vat. You may be more familiar with this – The Matrix made a lot of money off of this concept. So in Descartes’ world of the Evil Demon, we cannot know anything about our external world with absolute certainty. We cannot even be sure of the existence of the world itself including other people and their thoughts. So what are we left with? Well, three things according to Descartes: • Mathematics • Logic (deduction) • Self existence Mathematics and logic exist because they are abstract tools not based in any kind of reality (they can be used to process knowledge, but are not knowledge themselves). That leaves you with only one thing that is absolutely certain – You exist. Not me, not your co-workers, not that guy who was talking to a lamppost this morning. Just you, YOU exist. That is all that you know for certain. Hence Descartes famous line, “I think therefore I am” (Cogito ergo sum for the Latin nerds out there). This is the primary problem of seeking knowledge – perceptions can be deceived and are not to be trusted. In its infancy, science went through a lot of growing pains with many dead ends to get around this problem. It is learning about these failures that we develop an understanding of modern science. Continuity of Nature So René Descartes really tied our hands here. He effectively took away all deduction (except mathematics and logic) and left us with imperfect induction. What does this mean? In critical thinking, we have deductive reasoning and inductive reasoning. Deductive reasoning is when you start with a premise that is 100% certain and build your argument from there. Inductive reasoning is when you start with an assumption to build your argument. The more likely that assumption is true, the stronger the induction, but you cannot say anything with 100% certainty. The problem is amplified when people use induction to conclude one premise, and then use that premise to build a new induction. The more that you do this, the weaker the induction becomes. Also, no matter how strong your inductive reasoning, you can never be 100% sure that you have anything amounting to real knowledge or validity. This is known as “The Problem of Induction”. How can we know anything with any kind of certainty? Monty Python has a great example of induction in their famous witch scene from The Holy Grail. I’ll supply the synopsis below, but if you have five minutes, watch the clip for yourself - it’s worth it. The villagers have a woman that they suspect is a witch and would like to burn her (as villagers like to do). They bring her to Sir Bedevere who is a “man of science” for an objective decision. Here is his “scientific” argument. Witches burn. Wood burns. Therefore, a witch must be made of wood. Wood floats. Ducks float. Therefore wood must weigh the same as a duck. If a woman weighs the same as a duck, then she must be made of wood. If she is made of wood, then she must be a witch. Therefore, if a woman weighs the same as a duck, she must be a witch. Now obviously there are many unsound conclusions and logical fallacies committed here, but you can see how simple inductions can lead to quite absurd conclusions, especially if it “sounds right”. Now, I’m not going to go into depth on validity of arguments and logical fallacies here, it is not the point of this series. If you would like to learn all about that, why don’t you take Critical Reasoning for Beginners at Oxford University? Did I mention that it is free, online, only 7 hours in total length, and can be downloaded to your iPod? So maybe we can try to give some guidance to induction to give us a little more substance. Here is where the Scottish philosopher David Hume comes in. In the 1700s, he made one of the first more effective attempts to tackle the Problem of Induction. What he points out is what is known as The Continuity of Nature. In a nutshell, we can observe natural occurrences and look for patterns. If we find that these patterns have always occurred, we can assume that they will continue to occur. He was quick to point out that this will fail to determine causation, but at least you can define continuity. From here you can make more accurate predictions about future outcomes. Definitely the underpinnings of science but there are still holes. The continuity is still based on assumptions with no real certainty. Great way to develop hypotheses, but we still have no concrete knowledge. Also we still have the problem of basing future premises on these assumptions, weakening our certainty even greater. Better than Sir Bedevere, but not by much. It is still susceptible to circular reasoning. Induction gives us only ideas, no reality. We need a better definition. We need a better way of verifying ideas. What is Ockham’s Razor? A philosophical razor is a device used to define and/or evaluate an idea. Often it can be used to force an idea or method of reasoning into or out of a category. The razor that most people are familiar with is Ockham’s Razor. When I was an undergrad, I had a philosophy professor who cautioned the use of Ockham’s Razor. It is one of the most misused and least understood positions in philosophy. Often summarized incorrectly as something along the lines of, “When comparing two ideas, the simpler explanation is better than the complex one.” Well, that is not exactly true. There are countless examples of the more complex being better such as Einstein’s Theory of Relativity vs. Classical Physics, Theory of Evolution vs. Intelligent Design, Germ Theory vs. “Succumbing to the Vapors”. Turns out, simpler in this respect is rarely better. Another problem is that simplicity depends on perspective. To quote Dieter Gernert: “Beyond trivial cases, the term ‘simplicity” remains a subjective term. What is compatible with somebody’s own pre-existing worldview, will be considered simple, clear, logical, and evident, whereas what is contradicting that worldview will quickly be rejected as an unnecessarily complex explanation and a senseless additional hypothesis. In this way, the principle of simplicity becomes a mirror of prejudice, and, still worse, a distorting mirror, since this origin is camouflaged.” (Read the whole article) A “mirror of prejudice” is not a lofty goal. Just because something fits simply into your worldview doesn’t make it accurate or even necessarily the most simple. You can just use the principle of simplicity to dismiss ideas that are complicated TO YOU and continue to believe whatever you want to believe. So how does one use Ockham’s Razor appropriately? Let’s start with a more accurate summary: “When faced with competing hypotheses, select the one that makes the fewest assumptions.” It is a desire to strip the qualifiers from an idea. For example, Einstein’s original Theory of Relativity only worked if you assume that the universe is expanding. Since he assumed that it was static he added the “cosmological constant” to the equations to cancel out the expansion problem. Hubble (the man not the telescope) later demonstrated that the universe was in fact expanding making Einstein refer to the cosmological constant as, “The greatest mistake of my life.” Did Einstein fail to employ Ockham’s Razor by adding the cosmological constant? Well, constants are not new to science and there are several examples (such as the Avogadro constant).
Recommended publications
  • Descartes' Arguments for Distinguishing Mind and Body
    © Michael Lacewing Descartes’ arguments for distinguishing mind and body THE KNOWLEDGE ARGUMENT In Meditation II, having argued that he knows he thinks, Descartes then asks what kind of thing he is. Discussions of identity seek to establish the essential properties of something, what makes it the thing that it is. The question ‘what am I?’ can be answered by considering the question of what it is for me to exist. Descartes is trying to identify his essence, those properties which, if he lost them, would mean he was no longer what he is. (An island, for instance, must be surrounded by water. If the water dried up, joining it to the mainland, it would cease to be an island.) He remarks that he can continue to doubt whether he has a body; after all, he only believes he has a body as a result of his perceptual experiences, and so the demon could be deceiving him about this. But he cannot doubt that he has a mind, i.e. that he thinks. So he knows he exists even though he doesn’t know whether or not he has a body. From this Descartes concludes that it is possible for him to exist without a body. He is essentially a mind, not a body. He would not necessarily cease to be himself if he ceased to have a body, but he would necessarily cease to be himself if he didn’t have a mind. APPEAL TO GOD’S OMNIPOTENCE Descartes’ argument so far is that minds can exist without bodies. However, on its own, it doesn’t establish dualism.
    [Show full text]
  • These Disks Contain My Version of Paul Spade's Expository Text and His Translated Texts
    These disks contain my version of Paul Spade's expository text and his translated texts. They were converted from WordStar disk format to WordPerfect 5.1 disk format, and then I used a bunch of macros and some hands-on work to change most of the FancyFont formatting codes into WordPerfect codes. Many transferred nicely. Some of them are still in the text (anything beginning with a backslash is a FancyFont code). Some I just erased without knowing what they were for. All of the files were cleaned up with one macro, and some of them have been further doctored with additional macros I wrote later and additional hand editing. This explains why some are quite neat, and others somewhat cluttered. In some cases I changed Spade's formatting to make the printout look better (to me); often this is because I lost some of his original formatting. I have occasionally corrected obvious typos, and in at least one case I changed an `although' to a `but' so that the line would fit on the same page. With these exceptions, I haven't intentionally changed any of the text. All of the charts made by graphics are missing entirely (though in a few cases I perserved fragments so you can sort of tell what it was like). Some of the translations had numbers down the side of the page to indicate location in the original text; these are all lost. Translation 1.5 (Aristotle) was not on the disk I got, so it is listed in the table of contents, but you won't find it.
    [Show full text]
  • Contrastive Empiricism
    Elliott Sober Contrastive Empiricism I Despite what Hegel may have said, syntheses have not been very successful in philosophical theorizing. Typically, what happens when you combine a thesis and an antithesis is that you get a mishmash, or maybe just a contradiction. For example, in the philosophy of mathematics, formalism says that mathematical truths are true in virtue of the way we manipulate symbols. Mathematical Platonism, on the other hand, holds that mathematical statements are made true by abstract objects that exist outside of space and time. What would a synthesis of these positions look like? Marks on paper are one thing, Platonic forms an­ other. Compromise may be a good idea in politics, but it looks like a bad one in philosophy. With some trepidation, I propose in this paper to go against this sound advice. Realism and empiricism have always been contradictory tendencies in the philos­ ophy of science. The view I will sketch is a synthesis, which I call Contrastive Empiricism. Realism and empiricism are incompatible, so a synthesis that merely conjoined them would be a contradiction. Rather, I propose to isolate important elements in each and show that they combine harmoniously. I will leave behind what I regard as confusions and excesses. The result, I hope, will be neither con­ tradiction nor mishmash. II Empiricism is fundamentally a thesis about experience. It has two parts. First, there is the idea that experience is necessary. Second, there is the thesis that ex­ perience suffices. Necessary and sufficient for what? Usually this blank is filled in with something like: knowledge of the world outside the mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Omnipotence in Descartes' Philosophy
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 6-2014 Divine Omnipotence In Descartes' Philosophy Alfredo Rodriguez Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/274 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] DIVINE OMNIPOTENCE IN DESCARTES’ PHILOSOPHY BY ALFREDO RODRIGUEZ A master's thesis submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Liberal Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, The City University of New York 2014 © 2014 Alfredo Rodriguez All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Liberal Studies in satisfaction of the requirement for the degree of Master of Arts. Professor Douglas Lackey Date Thesis Adviser Professor Matthew K. Gold Date Executive Officer THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract Divine Omnipotence in Descartes’ Philosophy by Alfredo Rodriguez Adviser: Professor Douglas Lackey The present thesis explores various aspects of Rene Descartes’ doctrine of divine omnipotence within the context of his overall philosophy and with reference to his medieval heritage. This thesis shows that, contrary to his multiple and explicit statements that God’s power cannot be limited in any way, Descartes took a more nuanced position on divine omnipotence that incorporated aspects of the widely accepted medieval position that God’s goodness is a constraint on his power.
    [Show full text]
  • Knowledge and Its Place in Nature by Hilary Kornblith
    Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 1b Knowledge According to A.C. Grayling, if “cogito ergo sum” is an argument, it is missing a premise. This premise is: A. Everything that exists thinks. B. Everything that thinks exists. C. Everything both exists and thinks. D. Everything either thinks or exists. Descartes’ ultimate aim was to prove that we can only know ourselves as thinking things and nothing else. A. True B. False Reminder of what Descartes was trying to do. Descartes was trying to put human knowledge on a firm foundation. Ultimately he hoped to be able to prove that the majority of things that we believe at a common sense can be proven correct. Problems with the cogito argument itself The cogito argument is actually very simple to troubleshoot. Put formally, the argument is this. 1. I think. 2. Therefore, I exist. It is true that if I think (e.g., by doubting my own existence) then I must actually exist. But the real question at issue is whether there really is an I, a particular, stable entity, that thinks. Reformulation We could reformulate Descartes’ argument along these lines: 1. Thinking is occurring. 2. Therefore, a thinking thing exists. Now the premise is clearly true, but, as we just showed, the conclusion may still be doubted. Recap So Descartes famous cogito argument: I think, therefore I am. is actually not a proof of his own existence as a thinking thing. What Descartes has plausibly shown us that we can not doubt that thinking is occurring while we are actually thinking.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of Cognition in the Later Middle Ages
    Theories of cognition in the later Middle Ages ROBERT PASNAU St. Joseph's University q;.::.~ CAMBRIDGE - ::: UNIVERSITY PRESS PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge CB2 1RP, United Kingdom CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge CB2 2RU, United Kingdom 40 West 20th Street, New York, NY 10011-4211, USA 10 Samford Road, Oakleigh, Melbourne 3166, Australia © Robert Pasnau 1997 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 1997 Typeset in Palatino Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Pasnau, Robert. Theories of cognition in the later Middle Ages / Robert Pasnau. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-521-58368-3 1. Knowledge, Theory of - History. 2. Cognition - History. 3. Philosophy, Medieval. 4. Thomas, Aquinas, Saint, 1225?-1274. 5. Olivi, Pierre Jean, 1248 or 9-1298. 6. William, of Ockham, ca. 1285-ca. 1349. 1. Title. B161.P37 1997 128'.2'0902 - dC20 96-36249 C1P A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library Transferred to digital printing 2003 Contents Preface page vii List of abbreviations x Introduction 1 1 The philosophical-historical context 4 2 Thomas Aquinas and the theory of species 11 3 Challenges to the theory 18 PART r: FUNDAMENTALS 1 Immateriality and intentionality 31 1 Cognition
    [Show full text]
  • 1 PHILOSOPHY, Lecture December 13 Contents: Rene Descartes` (1596
    PHILOSOPHY, lecture December 13 Contents: Rene Descartes` (1596-1650) metaphysical dualism (mind and body) Key words: Dualism, Methodical scepticism Rationalism Methods od doubt Cogito ergo sum Alter ego issue Subjectivism Mind-body problem Methodical scepticism – doubt in order to find certainty Classic scepticism – certainty is unavailable for man “The Method of Doubt The Method of Doubt involves treating all your former beliefs as if they were false. You should only believe something if you are absolutely certain that it is true: the slightest doubt about its truth should be sufficient to reject it. The fact that you can doubt it doesn’t prove that it is false; it may well turn out to be true. However, the merest suspicion that it might be false is enough to render it unsuitable as a foundation for the edifice of knowledge. That has to be built on indubitable knowledge. […] The point of this method was that it might allow Descartes to discover some beliefs which were immune from doubt and which would thus serve as foundations for his reconstruction of knowledge on sound principles. At worst it would show him that everything could be doubted; that nothing was certain. The Evidence of the Senses In the First Meditation Descartes introduces this Method of Doubt and applies it rigorously to his former beliefs, beginning with those he has acquired through the five senses. His senses have sometimes deceived him. For instance, he has made mistakes about what he could see in the distance. On the principle that it is wise never to trust what has once deceived you, he resolves not to trust the evidence of his senses.
    [Show full text]
  • Impure Infinitism and the Evil Demon Argument
    E-LOGOS – Electronic Journal for Philosophy 2016, Vol. 23(1) 13–24 ISSN 1211-0442 (DOI: 10.18267/j.e-logos.428),Peer-reviewed article Journal homepage: e-logos.vse.cz Impure Infinitism and the Evil Demon Argument Husein Inusah1 Abstract: The central thesis of this paper is that the modus ponens reductio argument does not clearly favour impure versions of infinitism. The nub of the modus ponens reductio argument is as follows: an infinite series of justified reasons by itself is vulnerable to the modus ponens reductio in the sense that one can construct an infinite chain of reasons supporting both an affirmative and denial of proposition, say p. The problem here is that, as Aikin urges, pure versions of infinitism do not possess the requisite resource to eliminate one of these chains of infinite reasons. The upshot is that pure versions of infinitism are not able to differentiate between an infinite series that is truth conducive and the ones that are not. Accordingly, Aikin promotes an impure infinitism over pure infinitism because, as he opines, impure infinitism has the requisite resources to eliminate one of the infinite chains of justified reasons and rids itself of the threat of the modus ponens reductio. In the following discussion, I submit that although Aikin seems quite successful in this venture, his version of impure infinitism faces a similar setback, in the form of the new evil demon problem, which is equally fatal to it as that which the modus ponens reductio wrecks on pure versions of infinitism. Keywords: Impure infinitism, justification, evil demon, foundationalism, coherentism.
    [Show full text]
  • Module 3: Foundationalism & Descartes's
    Module 3: Foundationalism Contents Module 3: Foundationalism ............................................................................................................ 1 1. Introduction ............................................................................................................................. 1 2. Basic and Derived Beliefs ....................................................................................................... 2 3. The Core of Foundationalism ................................................................................................. 2 3.1 The Regress Argument ..................................................................................................... 3 4. Classical Foundationalism ...................................................................................................... 4 5. Descartes’ Meditations on First Philosophy ........................................................................... 5 5.0 Summary of Meditations 1–6............................................................................................ 5 5.1 Meditation 1 ...................................................................................................................... 5 5.2 Meditation 2 ...................................................................................................................... 6 5.3 Meditation 3 ...................................................................................................................... 8 5.4 Meditation 4 ...................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Three Attempts to Refute Skepticism and Why They Fail Richard Foley
    Three Attempts to Refute Skepticism and Why They Fail Richard Foley One of the advantages of classical foundationalism was that it was thought to provide a refutation of skeptical worries, which raise the specter that our beliefs might be extensively mistaken. The most extreme versions of these worries are expressed in familiar thought experiments such as the brain-in-a-vat hypothesis, which imagines a world in which, unbeknownst to you, your brain is in a vat hooked up to equipment programmed to provide it with precisely the same visual, auditory, tactile, and other sensory inputs that you have in this world. As a result, your opinions about your immediate environment are the same as they are in this world. You have the same beliefs about your recent activities, your current physical appearance, your present job, and so on, but in fact you are a brain in a vat tucked away in a corner of a laboratory. Thus, in the brain-in-a-vat world, your beliefs about these everyday matters are mistaken, and mistaken not just in detail, but deeply mistaken. 1 Classical foundationalists from Descartes to its great twentieth century exemplars (Russell, the early Wittgenstein, Ayer, Carnap, and C.I. Lewis) sought to provide a response to such skeptical worries. Even if Cartesian certainty was not to be obtained, we could at least be assured that if we were careful enough, our beliefs would be justified, and if our beliefs were justified, we could be assured that they were mostly accurate. Classical foundationalists had their disputes with one another, but they gave similar answers to the core questions of epistemology, and the answers they gave were said to be sufficient to banish radical skeptical worries: some beliefs are basic and as such their truth is assured; other beliefs are justified by virtue of being deductively entailed or inductively supported by these basic beliefs; we can determine with careful enough introspection whether our beliefs are justified, and if they are, we can be assured that they are for the most part true.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes' Rationalism
    © Michael Lacewing Descartes’ rationalism Descartes’ Meditations provide an extended study in establishing knowledge through rational intuition and deduction. We focus in this handout on three central claims: his arguments for the existence of the self, of God, and of physical objects. We will also consider his elaboration on the idea of rational intuition through his concept of ‘clear and distinct’ ideas. DESCARTES ON THE EXISTENCE (AND NATURE) OF SELF (MEDITATION II, PP. 3-6) At the end of Meditation I, Descartes supposes that he was being deceived by an evil demon. At the start of Meditation II, he argues that, even if the evil demon is deceiving him, ‘he will never bring it about that I am nothing while I think I am something’ (p. 4). Why not? He cannot doubt that he exists: if he were to doubt that he exists, that would prove he does exist – as something that thinks. So he knows that he exists. He can’t know that he exists as a body – his sense perception of his body, and of bodies in general, could be no more than a dream. But he cannot doubt that he thinks. The cogito, ‘I think’, is Descartes’ first stepping stone to knowledge. Could he nevertheless be a body, without knowing it? Descartes can’t say, but at least his knowledge of what he is can’t depend on his being a body, since he knows he exists but not whether he has a body. What he is is a thinking thing, ‘a thing that doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wants, refuses, and also imagines and senses’ (p.
    [Show full text]
  • Descartes, Plato and the Cave
    Descartes, Plato and the Cave STEPHEN BUCKLE It has been a commonplace, embodied in philosophy curricula the world over, to think of Descartes’ philosophy as he seems to present it: as a radical break with the past, as inaugurating a new philosophical problematic centred on epistemology and on a radical dualism of mind and body.1 In several ways, however, recent scholarship has undermined the simplicity of this picture. It has, for example, shown the considerable degree of literary artifice in Descartes’ central works, and thereby brought out the deceptive character of his self-presentation there. In particular, it has revealed the extent of his debts to the Neoplatonist tradition, particularly to Augustine, and of his engagement with the Scholastic commentators of his day.2 My aim in this paper is to push this interpretative tendency a step further, by bringing out Descartes’ indebtedness to Plato. I begin by offering some reminders of the broadly Platonic nature of Cartesian dualism.3 I then argue that he provides clues sufficient for—and designed to encourage—reading the Meditations on First Philosophy in the light of distinctively Platonic doctrines, and in particular, as a rewriting 1 See, for example, Marleen Rozemond, ‘The Nature of the Mind’, in Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Descartes’ Meditations (Oxford: Blackwell, 2006), 48, for the statement (but not advocacy) of these connections. Amongst the boldest of advocates for Descartes’ novelty along these lines, particularly concerning his account of the mind, is Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1980). Some of his views will be scrutinized below.
    [Show full text]