Book Review [Republicanism: a Theory of Freedom and Government] Santa Clara Law Review

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Book Review [Republicanism: a Theory of Freedom and Government] Santa Clara Law Review Santa Clara Law Review Volume 39 | Number 1 Article 9 1-1-1998 Book Review [Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government] Santa Clara Law Review Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.scu.edu/lawreview Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Santa Clara Law Review, Book Review, Book Review [Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government], 39 Santa Clara L. Rev. 355 (1998). Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.scu.edu/lawreview/vol39/iss1/9 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Santa Clara Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Santa Clara Law Review by an authorized administrator of Santa Clara Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW THE REPUBLICAN MANIFESTO Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government. By Philip Pettit. New York, Oxford University Press, 1997. Pp. 304. Hard Cover. $29.95 Reviewed by Mortimer Sellers* The United States Constitution provides that the federa- tion shall guarantee a "[r]epublican [florm of [g]overnment" to every state in the Union.1 This makes republicanism one of the guiding principles of American law, to be imposed, by force if necessary, whenever states depart from their republi- can foundations. Yet despite its central position in American constitutional law, the republican guarantee has become an ideological cipher, used to mean anything or nothing and generally ignored by judges and lawyers, or misapplied by le- gal academics.2 Now at last Philip Pettit's new book on Re- publicanism examines republican government from a sound historical perspective, illuminating the republican guarantee in the light of contemporary philosophical insights, and sug- gesting what republican ideals require, applied to modern problems. Pettit does not waste much space on history, because his purpose is normative, but his short first historical chapter * A.B. 1980, J.D. 1988, Harvard University. B.C.L. 1988, D.Phil. 1986, Oxford University. M.N.S. Sellers is a Professor of Law and Director of the Center for International and Comparative Law at the University of Baltimore School of Law. 1. U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 4. 2. See G. Edward White, Reflections of the "Republican Revival": Inter- disciplinary Scholarship in the Legal Academy, 6 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 1 (1994); Daniel T. Rodgers, Republicanism: The Careerof a Concept, 79 J. AM. HIST. 11 (1992) (critizing the use of republican terminology by law school academics). 355 356 SANTA CLARA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39 justifies the rest of the book by explaining clearly and suc- cinctly what republicanism is and has been through the ages.! Recent American academic and law school discussions have sometimes implied that Aristotle,4 Sparta,5 or Athenian democracy' were in some sense models of republican govern- ment in the United States and elsewhere.' Pettit correctly insists that republican allusions always evoked the primor- dial conception of liberty, or libertas, of the world's first res publica in Rome.8 Republican liberty requires that governments must never intervene in private lives, except to serve the common good (res publica) of the people.! Pettit demonstrates that republics secure liberty for their citizens as "non- domination," protecting all equally against arbitrary interfer- ence by self-interested groups, individuals or the state." He usefully distinguishes more recent Hobbesian conceptions of liberty as license, or the absence of restraint, from the older republican tradition of liberty through law." This differs from simple democracy or tyranny of the majority in not be- ing populist, homogenous, or even necessarily communitar- ian." The state is not the servant of the people, but their trustee, acting faithfully in the interests of all." Pettit's Project Pettit's argument begins (chapter 1) with a history of the republican conception of liberty, culminating in its greatest 3. Cf. M.N.S. SELLERS, Republican Liberty, THE JURISPRUDENCE OF LIBERTY (Moens and Ratnapala, eds., 1996). 4. Frank I. Michelman, The Supreme Court 1985 Term, Foreword: Traces of Self-Government, 100 HARV. L. REV. 4 (1986). 5. PAUL A. RAHE, REPUBLICS ANCIENT AND MODERN: CLASSICAL RE- PUBLICANISM AND THE AMERICAN REVOLUTION (1992). 6. MICHAEL J. SANDEL, DEMOCRACY'S DISCONTENT: AMERICA IN SEARCH OF A PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY (1996). 7. These views probably derive from misreadings of J.G.A. POCOCK, THE MACHIAVELLIAN MOMENT: FLORENTINE POLITICAL THOUGHT AND THE ATLANTIC REPUBLICAN TRADITION (1975). 8. M.N.S. SELLERS, AMERICAN REPUBLICANISM: ROMAN IDEOLOGY IN THE UNITED STATES CONSTITUTION (1994). 9. PHILIP PETTIT, REPUBLICANISM: A THEORY OF FREEDOM AND GOVERNMENT, at vii (1997). 10. Id. at vii. 11. Id. at 5. 12. Id. at 8. 13. Id. at 9. 1998] REPUBLICANISM 357 triumph in the American Revolution. He goes on (chapter 2) to develop a philosophy of freedom as non-domination, distin- guishing republican liberty from later Hobbesian construc- tions of freedom as non-interference. This lays the ground- work for a broader application of liberty (chapter 3) to the project of designing a state. Pettit sets out to explain (chapter 4) the egalitarian and communitarian appeal of re- publican political and legal institutions. Such institutions will act (chapter 5) to restrain private power, which Pettit calls "dominium," as well as public power (chapter 6), which Pettit calls "imperium." This requires certain regulating checks and balances (chapter 7) to keep the system stable, al- though Pettit concludes (chapter 8), that republican institu- tions will not be enough in themselves. To succeed they also need the support of virtue, which is to say, of embedded re- publican attitudes in society at large. The project as a whole falls into two parts. First (Part I), Pettit must identify what republican freedom is. Then (Part II), having done so, he explores the political and legal institu- tions that secure republican government in a just and stable commonwealth, or free state. Applied to United States con- stitutional discourse, Part I corresponds to the Preamble and XIVth Amendment: what it is to "secure the blessings of lib- erty to ourselves and our posterity" 4 or "deprive any person of... liberty." 5 Part II corresponds to the body of the Consti- tution, guaranteeing a "republican form of government" to every state in the Union. 6 Neither makes sense without the other. Republican governments secure liberty. Liberty de- fines republican government. This is why, as George Wash- ington observed when he inaugurated republican government under the United States Constitution, "the sacred fire of lib- erty and the destiny of the republican model of government, are justly considered as deeply, perhaps as finally, staked on the experiment entrusted to the hands of the American Peo- ple." 7 14. U.S. CONST. preamble. 15. U.S. CONST. amend. XIV. 16. U.S. CONST. art. IV, § 4. 17. George Washington, The First Inaugural Speech (April 30, 1789), in GEORGE WASHINGTON: A COLLECTION, at 462 (W.B. Allen ed.,1988). 358 SANTA CLARA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 39 Republican Liberty Defined Republican liberty, as Pettit (correctly) defines it, re- quires immunity from arbitrary power.18 Pettit repeats Tom Paine's definition of arbitrary state power as the power in public officials to act with themselves, "and not the res- publica," as their object."9 So "[e]very government that does not make the res-publica its whole and sole object, is not good government" and "republican government is no other than government established and conducted for the interest of the public.""° Pettit considers governments arbitrary that have the power to impose their will contrary to the public good, whether or not they exercise this power. It is the lack of con- straint that makes power arbitrary.2 Republics must be "empire[s] of laws, and not of men."2 Law professors, judges and lawyers have tended to lose sight of the purposes of America's constitutional experiment. They casually adopt a new vocabulary of "negative" liberty first advanced (as Pettit shows) by opponents of the Ameri- can Revolution.23 This replaced the original republican con- ception of liberty as non-domination with a new conception of liberty as non-interference." Such profound changes in meaning entailed corresponding changes in the law, or rather in academic and judicial perceptions of the relationship be- tween liberty and the law. 5 The original sense of liberty re- quired law for its existence, since laws create the freedoms that citizens share. As John Locke observed against Sir Rob- ert Filmer: "the end of law is not to abolish or restrain, but to preserve and enlarge freedom," by protecting citizens against the violent impositions of their fellow human beings.26 Recent liberal philosophers, rejecting Locke's viewpoint, 18. PETTIT, supra note 9, at 51. 19. Id. at 56, (quoting THOMAS PAINE, "THE RIGHTS OF MAN: PART II," re- printed in POLITICAL WRITINGS 168 (Bruce Kuklick ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1989)). 20. Id. at 29-30 (cited and partially quoted in Pettit). 21. Id. at 55. 22. Id. at 39 (quoting JAMES HARRINGTON, THE COMMON WEALTH OF OCEANA AND A SYSTEM OF POLITICS 8 (J.G.A. Pocock ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1992). 23. PETTIT, supra note 9, at 35-41. 24. Cf. M.N.S. SELLERS, THE SACRED FIRE OF LIBERTY: REPUBLICANISM, LIBERALISM, AND THE LAW (1998). 25. PETTIT, supra note 9, at 35-41. 26. JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT, at II.57 (1690). 1998] REPUBLICANISM 359 have embraced the doctrine of Hobbes and Filmer, to view
Recommended publications
  • Mill and Pettit on Freedom, Domination, and Freedom-As-Domination
    Prolegomena 18 (1) 2019: 27–50 doi: 10 .26362/20190102 Mill and Pettit on Freedom, Domination, and Freedom-as-Domination Tim Beaumont School of Foreign Languages, Shenzhen University, Guangdong, P .R . China beaumonttim@hotmail .com ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC ARTICLE – RECEIVED: 29/11/18 ACCEPTED: 11/04/19 abstract: Pettit endorses a ‘republican’ conception of social freedom of the person as consisting of a state of non-domination, and takes this to refute Mill’s ‘liberal’ claim that non-domineering but coercive interference can compromise social freedom of choice . This paper argues that Pettit’s interpretation is true to the extent that Mill believes that the legitimate, non-arbitrary and just coercion of would-be dominators, for the sake of preventing them from dominating others, can render them unfree to choose to do so without rendering them socially unfree (qua dominated) persons in their own right . However, contra Pettit, Mill is correct to reject the ‘republican’ view for at least two reasons . Firstly, it enables him to avoid commitment to the implausi- ble implication that would-be dominators who sincerely deny any interest in a shared system of basic liberties are automatically rendered unfree persons by the coercion necessary to uphold such a system . Secondly, it enables him to avoid begging the question against ‘immoralists’ like Nietzsche, whose opposition to systems of recip- rocal non-domination is at least partly motivated by the losses of social freedom of choice they entail for those they deem to be worthy of dominating others . key words: Domination, freedom, liberalism, liberty, John Stuart Mill, Friedrich Nietzsche, Philip Pettit, republicanism .
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Republicanism Across Cultures Philip Pettit Introduction Every
    1 Republicanism Across Cultures Philip Pettit Introduction Every philosophy of the good society starts with an account of the central complaint that the state should help to put right: the evil that the society should drive out by means of political organization and initiative. If the philosophy is to be persuasive, then the complaint should attract widespread sympathy and support, being recognized as something that everyone will want to have remedied. And, of course, it should be a complaint that the state has the ability in principle to rectify, reducing or even eradicating the ill indicted. Republican philosophy identifies a complaint that is meant to be at once popularly motivating and politically implementable. It indicts the evil of subjection to another’s will — particularly in important areas of personal choice — as an ill that we all recognize and recoil from and at the same time as an ill that the state is well placed to deal with. Such subjection can be effectively corralled and reduced, if not wholly eliminated, by means of political initiative. And yet it takes only a little imagination to realize just how repellent it can be. Think, by way of exercising such imagination, of how you would feel as a student if you depended for not failing a course on the whim of an instructor. Or as a wife if you had to rely on the mood of your husband for whether you could enjoy an unmolested day. Or as a worker if you hung on the favor of a manager for whether you retained your job.
    [Show full text]
  • Brief of International Law Scholars and Nongovernmental Organizations As Amici Curiae in Support of Appellees
    Case: 17-15589, 04/20/2017, ID: 10403831, DktEntry: 96, Page 1 of 40 No. 17-15589 IN THE United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit STATE OF HAWAII, et al., Plaintiffs-Appellees, v. DONALD J. TRUMP, et al., Defendants-Appellants. On Appeal from the United States District Court for the District of Hawaii, No. 1:17-cv-00050-DKW-KSC District Judge Derrick K. Watson BRIEF OF INTERNATIONAL LAW SCHOLARS AND NONGOVERNMENTAL ORGANIZATIONS AS AMICI CURIAE IN SUPPORT OF APPELLEES By: s/ Aaron X. Fellmeth By: s/ Joseph M. McMillan Aaron X. Fellmeth By: s/ Michelle L. Maley Arizona State University Joseph M. McMillan, WSBA No. 26527 Sandra Day O’Connor College of Law Michelle L. Maley, WSBA No. 51318 Mail Code 9520 Perkins Coie LLP 111 E. Taylor St. 1201 Third Avenue, Suite 4900 Phoenix, AZ 85004-4467 Seattle, WA 98101-3099 Telephone: 480.241.8414 Telephone: 206.359.8000 [email protected] Facsimile: 206.359.9000 By: s/ Jonathan Hafetz [email protected] Jonathan Hafetz [email protected] Seton Hall University School of Law One Newark Center Newark, NJ 07102 Telephone: 917.355.6896 [email protected] LEGAL135011644.5 Case: 17-15589, 04/20/2017, ID: 10403831, DktEntry: 96, Page 2 of 40 CORPORATE DISCLOSURE STATEMENT Pursuant to Federal Rules of Appellate Procedure 26.1 and 29(a)(4)(A), amici curiae certify that they have no parent corporations or any publicly held corporations owning 10% or more of their stock. DATED this 20th day of April, 2017. By: s/ Aaron X. Fellmeth By: s/ Joseph M.
    [Show full text]
  • Two-Dimensional Democracy and the International Domain Philip Pettit
    Draft for conference presentation, NYU Law School, 4 Oct, 02. Two-dimensional Democracy and the International Domain Philip Pettit Drawing on a background in republican thought, I have argued elsewhere that democracy should be two-dimensional in character, allowing for an electoral and a contestatory aspect.1 I argued in a normative spirit that the two- dimensional ideal is more defensible and more commanding than the more common, purely electoral alternative. This usage of the word ‘democracy’ also picks up some aspects of common talk. Few of us would happily apply the word to regimes, no matter how electorally unimpeachable, that failed to provide for certain forms of contestation, say through the presence of a viable opposition or an independent judiciary. My aim in this paper is to recast the two-dimensional way of thinking about democracy, with the aim of preparing the ground for a consideration of what democracy should require in the international domain: in the context of international organizations and, more generally, cooperation among national governments. In section 1 I look at the two-dimensional ideal from an abstract perspective; in section 2 I consider how it might be implemented in a national context; and in section 3 I consider how far the ideal can be approximated in the international domain. I should emphasise that I am no expert on the institutions of the international domain. My hope is, at best, to sketch a line that those who have a professional knowledge of the domain may find useful in considering the common complaint that international institutions inevitably erode democracy.
    [Show full text]
  • Default Document
    ASCL Sponsor Members Minutes – 2011 Annual Meeting of the Society on October 21, 2011 MINUTES of the Annual Meeting of the Sponsor Members of the American Society of Comparative Law, Inc. Held on Friday, October 21, 2011 at 4:45 p.m. at McGeorge School of Law, University of the Pacific, 3200 Fifth Avenue, Sacramento, CA 95817 The annual meeting of the Sponsor Members of the American Society of Comparative Law, Inc. was called to order by President John C. Reitz at 4:45 p.m. 1. Secretary’s Roll Call A sheet for silent roll call was distributed. The following 47 Sponsor Members were present at the meeting and were represented by the individuals listed below: 1. University of Alabama School of Law: Kenneth M. Rosen 2. American University, Washington College of Law: Padideh Ala`i 3. University of Arkansas at Little Rock Bowen School of Law: Kenneth S. Gallant 4. University of Baltimore School of Law: James Maxeiner, Mortimer Sellers 5. Boston College Law School: Richard Albert 6. University of California at Berkeley School of Law: Richard M. Buxbaum 7. University of California at Davis School of Law: Afra Afsharipour 8. Chicago-Kent College of Law, IIT: David J. Gerber 9. Cleveland-Marshall College of Law: Brian Ray 10. University of Connecticut School of Law: Richard S. Kay 11. Duke University School of Law: Donald L. Horowitz, Ralf Michaels 12. Emory University School of Law: Johan van der Vyver 13. University of Florida College of Law: Pedro Malavet 14. George Washington University, National Law Center: Francesca Bignami 15.
    [Show full text]
  • Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict and Human Rights Edited by Jens David Ohlin Frontmatter More Information
    Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-13793-6 — Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict and Human Rights Edited by Jens David Ohlin Frontmatter More Information THEORETICAL BOUNDARIES OF ARMED CONFLICT AND HUMAN RIGHTS In the last two decades, human rights law has played an expanding role in the legal regulation of wartime conduct. In the process, human rights law and international humanitarian law have developed a complicated sibling relationship. For some, this relationship is viewed as a mutually reinforcing effort between like-minded regimes designed to civilize human behavior. For others, the relationship is a more complicated sibling rivalry. In this book, an unparalleled collection of legal theorists examine the relationship between these two bodies of law. Each chapter skilfully maps the possibil- ities of harmonization while, at the same time, raising cautionary flags about the limits of that project. The authors not only chart the existing state of the law, but also debate the normative implications of the continu- ing influence of human rights norms on current practices including torture, targeted killings, the conduct of non-international armed conflicts, and post-war state building. Jens David Ohlin is Professor of Law and Associate Dean for Academic Affairs at Cornell Law School. He specializes in international law and all aspects of criminal law, including domestic, comparative, and inter- national criminal law. © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-1-107-13793-6 — Theoretical Boundaries of Armed Conflict and Human Rights Edited by Jens David Ohlin Frontmatter More Information asil studies in international legal theory Series Editors Mortimer N.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy
    A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key fi gures, terms, topics, and problems of the fi eld. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, representing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series: 20. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa 1. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy, 21. A Companion to Genethics Second edition Edited by Justine Burley and John Harris Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric Tsui-James 22. A Companion to Philosophical Logic 2. A Companion to Ethics Edited by Dale Jacquette Edited by Peter Singer 23. A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy 3. A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by Steven Nadler Edited by David Cooper 24. A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle 4. A Companion to Epistemology Ages Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa Edited by Jorge J. E. Gracia and Timothy B. Noone 5. A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (2-volume set), Second edition 25. A Companion to African-American Edited by Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit and Philosophy Thomas Pogge Edited by Tommy L. Lott and John P. Pittman 6. A Companion to Philosophy of Mind 26. A Companion to Applied Ethics Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Edited by R. G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman 7. A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa 27.
    [Show full text]
  • Civil Liberty and Fundamental Rights: a Neo-Roman Approach
    1 Civil liberty and fundamental rights: a Neo-Roman approach Quentin Skinner Queen Mary, University of London I This paper is part of a project, or rather two linked projects, on which I have recently begun to work, so I am particularly grateful for the chance to gain some comments on this preliminary draft. Both my projects are centred on what I call the neo-Roman understanding of civil liberty. This has been widely discussed in recent Anglophone political philosophy, but has generally been described as a ‘republican’ rather than a ‘neo-Roman’ line of argument. This preference is almost entirely due to the work of Philip Pettit, who has done more than anyone to clarify the concept at issue.1 I still prefer to speak of neo-Romanism, if only because many of the leading exponents of the theory in its early-modern heyday – John Locke, for example – would have been horrified to find themselves described as republican in their political allegiances. But I hasten to add that nothing much hangs on these differences of terminology. My main project is to write a history of the rise and fall of the neo-Roman understanding of rights and liberty in Anglophone political thought. This story is largely an early-modern one. The ideological uses of neo-Roman ideas reached their climax with the English revolution in the 1640s, and their nemesis with the loss of the American colonies in the 1770s. I have already written about the first half of this story in my book, Liberty before liberalism, so my new study will mainly focus on the Imperial crisis of the mid eighteenth century.
    [Show full text]
  • Amicus Curiae Brief of International Law Scholars and Nongovernmental Organizations in Support of Respondents
    NOS. 16-1436, 16-1540 In the Supreme Court of the United States DONALD J. TRUMP, PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES, et al., Petitioners, v. INTERNATIONAL REFUGEE ASSISTANCE PROJECT, et al., Respondents. DONALD J. TRUMP, PRESIDENT OF THE UNITED STATES, et al., Petitioners, v. HAWAII, et al., Respondents. On Writs of Certiorari to the United States Court of Appeals for the Fourth and Ninth Circuits AMICUS CURIAE BRIEF OF INTERNATIONAL LAW SCHOLARS AND NONGOVERNMENTAL ORGANIZATIONS IN SUPPORT OF RESPONDENTS Elisabeth C. Frost Aaron X. Fellmeth Amanda R. Callais Counsel of Record PERKINS COIE LLP Sandra Day O’Connor 700 13th Street, NW College of Law Suite 600 Mail Code 9520 Washington, D.C. 20005-3960 Arizona State University 111 E. Taylor St. Phoenix, AZ 85004-4467 480.727.8575 [email protected] Counsel for Amici Curiae International Law Scholars and Non-Governmental Organizations Becker Gallagher · Cincinnati, OH · Washington, D.C. · 800.890.5001 i TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF AUTHORITIES................... ii RULE 29 STATEMENT OF INTEREST OF AMICI CURIAE ............. 1 I. SUMMARY OF THE ARGUMENT........ 2 II. ARGUMENT.......................... 4 A. International Law Is Relevant to Assessing the Legality of the Executive Order............................. 4 B. International Law Regarding Discrimination on the Basis of Religion and National Origin ................. 9 1. The International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights............... 9 2. The International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination.................. 14 C. Relevant Provisions of the Executive Order............................ 16 III. CONCLUSION ....................... 18 APPENDIX Appendix A ............................App. 1 ii TABLE OF AUTHORITIES Federal Cases F. Hoffmann-La Roche Ltd. v.
    [Show full text]
  • Beyond Liberalism? Political Theories of Republicanism and Democracy
    SPS Seminar 1st term 2017-2018 Beyond Liberalism? Political Theories of Republicanism and Democracy Organized by Rainer Bauböck and Matthew Hoye Tuesday 11:00 – 13:00, Seminar room 3, Badia Fiesolana Register online Contact: [email protected] Today, when we think of citizenship, we think about individualism, rights, freedom as non-interference, and the state as the neutral protector of individual autonomy. That is, we think about citizenship through the prism of contemporary liberalism. These ideas were not always so widely accepted. Liberalism was once the language of radicals fighting for emancipation against entrenched power and deep-rooted philosophical and ideological systems. The genealogy of liberalism tracks a series of intellectual disputes, political crises, internal criticism, conceptual appropriations, rhetorical intensifications, problem solving, and institutional innovations. It was these battles—philosophical and political—that motivated liberalism. Classical liberalism—say, from 1651 to 1848—did not only fight against political and religious absolutism but also against the much older republican and democratic traditions. Those latter battles were rather less pitched, and primarily about ethical priorities, the nature of freedom, social and political institutions, traditions, and ideologies. That history was one of productive mutual appropriation, inspired criticism, and ultimately of revolution and counter-revolution. The modern history of liberalism—say, from 1848 to 1989—was an existential battle between liberalism, communism, and fascism. In the contemporary period—say, from 1989 onwards—liberalism is hegemonic. Proof of the hegemony of liberalism is evident in our seemingly acrimonious debates. These debates appear to be fought between advocates of deeply antithetical positions, but on closer analysis they often seem to be about rather small philosophical differences.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom in the Market
    politics,philosophy & economics article © SAGE Publications Ltd London Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi 1470-594X 200606 5(2) 131–149 Freedom in the market Philip Pettit Princeton University, USA abstract The market is traditionally hailed as the very exemplar of a system under which people enjoy freedom, in particular the negative sort of freedom associated with liberal and libertarian thought: freedom as noninterference. But how does the market appear from the perspective of a rival conception of freedom (freedom as non-domination) that is linked with the Roman and neo- Roman tradition of republicanism? The republican conception of freedom argues for important normative constraints on property, exchange, and regulation, without supporting extremes to the effect that ‘property is theft’ or ‘taxation is theft’ or anything of that kind. It does not cast a cold eye on commerce; it merely provides an alternative view of the attractions. keywords liberty, market, liberalism, libertarianism, republicanism, domination, property, exchange, regulation The market is traditionally hailed as the very exemplar of a system under which people enjoy freedom, in particular the negative sort of freedom associated with liberal and libertarian thought: freedom as noninterference. The appeal of the market from within that viewpoint is that it represents a regime of unobstructed consumer choice and, as a bonus, a regime in which consumer options may be expected to increase and diversify under the pressure of competition. In this article, I want to look at how the market appears from the perspective of a rival conception of freedom (freedom as non-domination) that is linked with the Roman and neo-Roman tradition of republicanism — so, at any rate, a number of recent authors claim, myself included among them.1 In pursuing this task, I do not say that the appeal of the market as a forum of unobstructed choice among ever-improving options is in any way bogus or suspect.
    [Show full text]
  • Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma
    PI 11-11 Philosophical Issues, 11 11 Social, Political, and Legal Philosophy, 2001 Deliberative Democracy and the Discursive Dilemma Philip Pettit Taken as a model for how groups should make collective judg- ments and decisions, the ideal of deliberative democracy is inher- ently ambiguous. Consider the idealised case where it is agreed on all sides that a certain conclusion should be endorsed if and only if certain premises are admitted. Does deliberative democ- racy recommend that members of the group debate the premises and then individually vote, in the light of that debate, on whether or not to support the conclusion? Or does it recommend that members individually vote on the premises, and then let their commitment to the conclusion be settled by whether or not the group endorses the required premises? Is deliberative democracy to enforce the discipline of reason at the individual level, as in the first possibility, or at the collective level, as in the second? Deliberative-democratic theory has not addressed this issue, per- haps because of an implicit assumption that it does not matter whether the discipline of reason is imposed at the individual or at the collective level. But that assumption is false and there is no excuse for neglecting the issue raised. The discursive dilemma of my title—a generalisation of the doctrinal paradox that has re- 11. Deliberative Democracy and Discursive Dilemma 269 cently received attention in analytical jurisprudence—shows that the procedures distinguished can come apart. Thus deliberative democrats must make up their minds on where they stand in re- lation to the issue; they cannot sit on the fence.
    [Show full text]