Algebraic Cycles

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Algebraic Cycles Algebraic Cycles Anand Sawant Abstract Algebraic cycles arose in the study of intersection theory for algebraic varieties. This note, based on a a lecture in the Mathematics Students’ Seminar at TIFR on September 7, 2012 is meant to give an intorduction to algebraic cycles and various adequate equivalence relations on them. We then state the Standard Conjecture D and state some of its consequences including the conjectural theory of motives. 1 Intersection theory and algebraic cycles Intersection theory deals with the problem of studying intersection of two closed subschemes of a scheme. Perhaps the first result in intersection theory was Bezout’s theorem, which says that given 2 two plane curves of degree m and n in PC having no component in common, their intersection consists of at most mn points (exactly mn points if counted with multiplicity). A systematic study of intersection theory involves the study of the group of algebraic cycles on a scheme X. In this section, we give a brief account of basic definitions and properties of algebraic cycles; for details, the reader is referred to Fulton’s book [1]. For simplicity, all the schemes considered in this note will be of finite type over a field F. Definition 1.1. An algebraic cycle on a scheme X is an element of the free abelian group on the set of all the closed integral subschemes of X. We shall denote the group of algebraic cycles by Z(X). Since closed integral subschemes of X are determined uniquely by their generic points, we have Z(X) = ⊕ Z: ζ2X We usually grade this group by dimension, by letting Zp(X) denote the algberaic cycles of dimension p. If X(p) denotes the set of points of X of dimension p, then Zp(X):= ⊕ Z. A point x 2 X is x2X(p) said to have codimension p, if the local ring OX;x has Krull dimension p. We may grade Z(X) by codimension as well: writing X(p) for the set of points of X of codimension p, we set Z p(X):= ⊕ Z. If X is equidimensional of dimension n, we have x2X(p) p Zn−p(X) = Z (X): If Z ,! X is a closed integral subscheme, we denote its class in Z(X) by [Z], and call it a prime cycle. 1 Definition 1.2. An algebraic cycle associated to a closed subscheme Y ,! X is defined to be [Y]:= ⊕ `(OY;Yi )[Yi]; i where the sum is taken over all the irreducible components Yi of Y and `(OY;Yi ) denotes the length of OY;Yi as module over itself. Note that the length is finite, OY;Yi being an artinian ring. For a well-working theory of algebraic cycles, we need to have a notion of intersection product of the cycles associated to two subvarieties Y and Z of a scheme X of dimension n, which will closely reflect the geometry of their intersection Y \ Z. Just taking the set-theoretic intersection of subvarieties in question will not work, because subvarieties may occur in bad position - for instance, two parallel lines in a plane or the case of intersecting a subvariety with itself. In case the cycles intersect properly, that is, if dim Y + dim Z − dim Y \ Z = n, we can define [Y] · [Z] = [Y \ Z]: In order to take care of the bad cases, we must have an adequate equivalence relation on Z(X) which is broad enough to ensure that given any two cycles on X we can find equivalent cycles intersecting properly such that their intersection is equivalent to the original intersection. The most important such equivalence relation which is essential for the purposes of intersection theory on smooth varieties is rational equivalence. Definition 1.3 (Rational equivalence). An i-dimensional cycle α on a scheme X is said to be ratio- nally equivalent to zero and we write α ∼rat 0 if there exist (i+1)-dimensional subvarieties V1;::: Vr 1 1 of X × P , such that the projection maps π j : V j ! P are dominant and we have Xr α = [V j(0)] − [V j(1)]; j=1 −1 1 1 where [V j(P)] = p∗[π j (P)] for a point P 2 P . Here p denotes the projection X × P ! X. The group of i-dimensional cycles that are rationally equivalent to zero is denoted by Rati(X). We use the notation Rati(X), if the cycles are graded by codimension. Thus, in other words, an i-dimensional cycle α on a scheme X is rationally equivalent to zero if there is an (i + 1)-dimensional cycle β on X × P1 such that α = [β(0)] − [β(1)]: Definition 1.4. The Chow group of dimension i-cycles on a scheme X is defined to be CHi(X):= Zi(X)=Rati(X): We will henceforth assume that all the schemes considered here are equidimensional and will i write CH (X):= CHn−i(X), where n is the dimension of X. Theorem 1.5. If X is a smooth scheme of dimension n over a field F, then the intersection product n makes CH∗(X) = ⊕ CHi(X) into a commutative ring. i=1 2 This theorem was first proved in the Chevalley seminar for smooth quasiprojective varieties using the moving lemma and was later generalized by Fulton by replacing the moving lemma by using the techniques of reduction to the diagonal and of deformation to the normal cone. We summarize the imporatant properties of Chow groups in the next proposition: Proposition 1.6. (1) If f : Y ! X is proper, there is a pushforward map f∗ : CHp(Y) ! CHp(X); for all p. (2) If g : Y ! X is flat of relative dimension d, then there is a pullback map ∗ g : CHp(Y) ! CHp+d(X); for all p. (3) Let i : Z ,! X be a closed subscheme and let U = X − Z. Let j : U ,! X be the inclusion of U into X. Then the sequence ∗ i∗ j CHp(Z) −! CHp(X) −! CHp(U) ! 0 is exact for all p. (4) If π : E ! X is an affine bundle of rank d, then the flat pullback ∗ π : CHp(X) ! CHp+d(E); is an isomorphism for all p. 2 Examples of adequate equivalence relations We now see examples of some other adequate equivalence relations on algebraic cycles on smooth projective varieties over an algebraically closed field k. We shall denote the category of smooth projectivve varieties by SmProj=k. Definition 2.1 (Algebraic equivalence). We say that α 2 Zi(X) is algebraically equivalent to zero and write α ∼alg 0 if there exists a smooth curve C, points c1; c2 2 C and a cycle β 2 Zi+1(X × C) such that α = [β(c1)] − [β(c2)]: The subgroup of Zi(X) generated by cycles algebraically equivalent to zero is denoted by Algi(X). We use the notation Algi(X), if the cycles are graded by codimension. Clearly, it can be seen that Rati(X) ⊆ Algi(X). The inclusion is proper in general. We next introduce homological equivalence of algebraic cycles. This depends on the notion of a Weil cohomology theory, which we define next. Definition 2.2. A Weil cohomology theory is a contravariant functor H∗ : SmProj=k ! Graded K-algebras; ∗ i for a field K such that if X 2 SmProj=k is of dimension n, then H (X) = ⊕iH (X) satisfies the following properties: 3 1. Hi(X) is a finite dimensional K-vector space for each i. 2. Hi(X) = 0 for i < 0 and for i > 2n. 3. H2n ' K. 4. (Poincare´ duality) There exists a nondegenerate pairing Hi(X) × H2n−i(X) ! H2n(X) ' K; for each i. 5. (Kunneth¨ isomorphism) There is a canonical isomorphism ∼ H∗(X) ⊗ H∗(Y) −! H∗(X × Y); induced by the projection maps. 6. (Cycle map) There exists a group homomorphism ∗ γX : Z(X) ! H (X) that is functorial with proper pushforwards and flat pullbacks, respects products and direct sums and such that it coincides with the canonical map Z ! K in the case X = Spec k. 7. (Weak Lefschetz property) For any smooth hyperplane section j : W ,! X (that is, W = X\H for some hyperplane H), j∗ : Hi(X) ! Hi(W) is an isomorphism for i ≤ n − 2 and a monomorphism for i ≤ n − 1. 8. (Hard Lefschetz property) For any smooth hyperplane section j : W ,! X, let w = γX([W]) 2 H2(X). Let L : Hi(X) ! Hi+2(X) be the Lefschetz operator given by x 7! x [ w. Then Li : Hn−i(X) ! Hn+1(X) is an isomorphism for i = 1;:::; n. The classical examples of Weil cohomology theories include the singular (Betti) cohomology, de Rham cohomology, l-adic cohomology, crystalline cohomology and Hodge cohomology. We are now set ot define the adequate equivalence relation of homological equivalence. Definition 2.3 (Homological equivalence). Fix a Weil cohomology theory H∗ on SmProj=k. A cycle α 2 Zi(X) is said to be homologically equivalent to zero and we write α ∼hom 0 if γX(α) = 0. The subgroup of Zi(X) generated by cycles homologiically equivalent to zero is denoted by Homi(X). We use the notation Homi(X), if the cycles are graded by codimension. It is a fact that Algi(X) ⊆ Homi(X) for each i. The inclusion can be proper, as was shown first by Griffiths and later by Clemens and others. (Griffiths showed that Hom2(X)= Alg2(X) is nonzero 4 and actually has an element of infinite order, if X is a generic hypersurface of degree 5 in PC.) We now define the coarsest of the adequate equivalence relations.
Recommended publications
  • Algebraic Cycles from a Computational Point of View
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Theoretical Computer Science 392 (2008) 128–140 www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs Algebraic cycles from a computational point of view Carlos Simpson CNRS, Laboratoire J. A. Dieudonne´ UMR 6621, Universite´ de Nice-Sophia Antipolis, 06108 Nice, France Abstract The Hodge conjecture implies decidability of the question whether a given topological cycle on a smooth projective variety over the field of algebraic complex numbers can be represented by an algebraic cycle. We discuss some details concerning this observation, and then propose that it suggests going on to actually implement an algorithmic search for algebraic representatives of classes which are known to be Hodge classes. c 2007 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Algebraic cycle; Hodge cycle; Decidability; Computation 1. Introduction Consider the question of representability of a topological cycle by an algebraic cycle on a smooth complex projective variety. In this paper we point out that the Hodge conjecture would imply that this question is decidable for varieties defined over Q. This is intuitively well-known to specialists in algebraic cycles. It is interesting in the context of the present discussion, because on the one hand it shows a relationship between an important question in algebraic geometry and the logic of computation, and on the other hand it leads to the idea of implementing a computer search for algebraic cycles as we discuss in the last section. This kind of consideration is classical in many areas of geometry. For example, the question of deciding whether a curve defined over Z has any Z-valued points was Hilbert’s tenth problem, shown to be undecidable in [10,51, 39].
    [Show full text]
  • What Is the Motivation Behind the Theory of Motives?
    What is the motivation behind the Theory of Motives? Barry Mazur How much of the algebraic topology of a connected simplicial complex X is captured by its one-dimensional cohomology? Specifically, how much do you know about X when you know H1(X, Z) alone? For a (nearly tautological) answer put GX := the compact, connected abelian Lie group (i.e., product of circles) which is the Pontrjagin dual of the free abelian group H1(X, Z). Now H1(GX, Z) is canonically isomorphic to H1(X, Z) = Hom(GX, R/Z) and there is a canonical homotopy class of mappings X −→ GX which induces the identity mapping on H1. The answer: we know whatever information can be read off from GX; and are ignorant of anything that gets lost in the projection X → GX. The theory of Eilenberg-Maclane spaces offers us a somewhat analogous analysis of what we know and don’t know about X, when we equip ourselves with n-dimensional cohomology, for any specific n, with specific coefficients. If we repeat our rhetorical question in the context of algebraic geometry, where the structure is somewhat richer, can we hope for a similar discussion? In algebraic topology, the standard cohomology functor is uniquely characterized by the basic Eilenberg-Steenrod axioms in terms of a simple normalization (the value of the functor on a single point). In contrast, in algebraic geometry we have a more intricate set- up to deal with: for one thing, we don’t even have a cohomology theory with coefficients in Z for varieties over a field k unless we provide a homomorphism k → C, so that we can form the topological space of complex points on our variety, and compute the cohomology groups of that topological space.
    [Show full text]
  • Hodge-Theoretic Invariants for Algebraic Cycles
    HODGE-THEORETIC INVARIANTS FOR ALGEBRAIC CYCLES MARK GREEN∗ AND PHILLIP GRIFFITHS Abstract. In this paper we use Hodge theory to define a filtration on the Chow groups of a smooth, projective algebraic variety. Assuming the gen- eralized Hodge conjecture and a conjecture of Bloch-Beilinson, we show that this filtration terminates at the codimension of the algebraic cycle class, thus providing a complete set of period-type invariants for a rational equivalence class of algebraic cycles. Outline (1) Introduction (2) Spreads; explanation of the idea p (3) Construction of the filtration on CH (X)Q (4) Interpretations and proofs (5) Remarks and examples (6) Appendix: Reformation of the construction 1. Introduction Some years ago, inspired by earlier work of Bloch, Beilinson (cf. [R]) proposed a series of conjectures whose affirmative resolution would have far reaching conse- quences on our understanding of the Chow groups of a smooth projective algebraic variety X. For any abelian group G, denoting by GQ the image of G in G⊗Z Q, these P conjectures would have the following implications for the Chow group CH (X)Q: (I) There is a filtration p 0 p 1 p (1.1) CH (X)Q = F CH (X)Q ⊃ F CH (X)Q p p p+1 p ⊃ · · · ⊃ F CH (X)Q ⊃ F CH (X)Q = 0 whose successive quotients m p m p m+1 p (1.2) Gr CH (X)Q = F CH (X)Q=F CH (X)Q may be described Hodge-theoretically.1 The first two steps in the conjectural filtration (??) are defined classically: If p 2p 0 : CH (X)Q ! H (X; Q) is the cycle class map, then 1 p F CH (X)Q = ker 0 : Setting in general m p p m p F CH (X) = CH (X) \ F CH (X)Q ; ∗Research partially supported by NSF grant DMS 9970307.
    [Show full text]
  • DENINGER COHOMOLOGY THEORIES Readers Who Know What the Standard Conjectures Are Should Skip to Section 0.6. 0.1. Schemes. We
    DENINGER COHOMOLOGY THEORIES TAYLOR DUPUY Abstract. A brief explanation of Denninger's cohomological formalism which gives a conditional proof Riemann Hypothesis. These notes are based on a talk given in the University of New Mexico Geometry Seminar in Spring 2012. The notes are in the same spirit of Osserman and Ile's surveys of the Weil conjectures [Oss08] [Ile04]. Readers who know what the standard conjectures are should skip to section 0.6. 0.1. Schemes. We will use the following notation: CRing = Category of Commutative Rings with Unit; SchZ = Category of Schemes over Z; 2 Recall that there is a contravariant functor which assigns to every ring a space (scheme) CRing Sch A Spec A 2 Where Spec(A) = f primes ideals of A not including A where the closed sets are generated by the sets of the form V (f) = fP 2 Spec(A) : f(P) = 0g; f 2 A: By \f(P ) = 000 we means f ≡ 0 mod P . If X = Spec(A) we let jXj := closed points of X = maximal ideals of A i.e. x 2 jXj if and only if fxg = fxg. The overline here denote the closure of the set in the topology and a singleton in Spec(A) being closed is equivalent to x being a maximal ideal. 1 Another word for a closed point is a geometric point. If a point is not closed it is called generic, and the set of generic points are in one-to-one correspondence with closed subspaces where the associated closed subspace associated to a generic point x is fxg.
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Cycles on Generic Abelian Varieties Compositio Mathematica, Tome 100, No 1 (1996), P
    COMPOSITIO MATHEMATICA NAJMUDDIN FAKHRUDDIN Algebraic cycles on generic abelian varieties Compositio Mathematica, tome 100, no 1 (1996), p. 101-119 <http://www.numdam.org/item?id=CM_1996__100_1_101_0> © Foundation Compositio Mathematica, 1996, tous droits réservés. L’accès aux archives de la revue « Compositio Mathematica » (http: //http://www.compositio.nl/) implique l’accord avec les conditions gé- nérales d’utilisation (http://www.numdam.org/conditions). Toute utilisa- tion commerciale ou impression systématique est constitutive d’une in- fraction pénale. Toute copie ou impression de ce fichier doit conte- nir la présente mention de copyright. Article numérisé dans le cadre du programme Numérisation de documents anciens mathématiques http://www.numdam.org/ Compositio Mathematica 100: 101-119,1996. 101 © 1996 KluwerAcademic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Algebraic cycles on generic Abelian varieties NAJMUDDIN FAKHRUDDIN Department of Mathematics, the University of Chicago, Chicago, Illinois, USA Received 9 September 1994; accepted in final form 2 May 1995 Abstract. We formulate a conjecture about the Chow groups of generic Abelian varieties and prove it in a few cases. 1. Introduction In this paper we study the rational Chow groups of generic abelian varieties. More precisely we try to answer the following question: For which integers d do there exist "interesting" cycles of codimension d on the generic abelian variety of dimension g? By "interesting" cycles we mean cycles which are not in the subring of the Chow ring generated by divisors or cycles which are homologically equivalent to zero but not algebraically equivalent to zero. As background we recall that G. Ceresa [5] has shown that for the generic abelian variety of dimension three there exist codimen- sion two cycles which are homologically equivalent to zero but not algebraically equivalent to zero.
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on Grothendieck's Standard Conjectures of Type C and D
    A NOTE ON GROTHENDIECK’S STANDARD CONJECTURES OF TYPE C+ AND D GONC¸ALO TABUADA Abstract. Grothendieck conjectured in the sixties that the even K¨unneth projector (with respect to a Weil cohomology theory) is algebraic and that the homological equivalence relation on algebraic cycles coincides with the numer- ical equivalence relation. In this note we extend these celebrated conjectures from smooth projective schemes to the broad setting of smooth proper dg cat- egories. As an application, we prove that Grothendieck’s original conjectures are invariant under homological projective duality. This leads to a proof of Grothendieck’s conjectures in the case of intersections of quadrics, linear sec- tions of determinantal varieties, and intersections of bilinear divisors. Along the way, we prove also the case of quadric fibrations. 1. Introduction and statement of results Let k be a base field of characteristic zero. Given a smooth projective k-scheme ∗ i ∗ ∗ th X and a Weil cohomology theory H , let us denote by πX : H (X) → H (X) the i ∗ K¨unneth projector, by Z (X)Q the Q-vector space of algebraic cycles on X, and by ∗ ∗ Z (X)Q/∼hom and Z (X)Q/∼num the quotients with respect to the homological and numerical equivalence relations, respectively. Following Grothendieck [4] (see also Kleiman [6, 7]), the standard conjecture1 of type C+, denote by C+(X), asserts that + 2i the even K¨unneth projector πX := Pi πX is algebraic, and the standard conjecture ∗ ∗ of type D, denoted by D(X), asserts that Z (X)Q/∼hom = Z (X)Q/∼num.
    [Show full text]
  • Weil Conjectures and Betti Numbers of Moduli Spaces
    Weil conjectures and Betti numbers of moduli spaces Christopher Lazda 1 Lecture 1 Let’s start with an object you’ll hopefully all be reasonably familiar with. X s ³(s) n¡ , s C, Re(s) 1. Æ n 1 2 È ¸ Conjecture (RH). If ³(s) 0 and 0 Re(s) 1, then Re(s) 1 . Æ Ç Ç Æ 2 This has an Euler product expansion Y s 1 ³(s) (1 p¡ )¡ Æ p prime ¡ and we note that {prime numbers} {closed points of Spec(Z)} $ so we can write Y s 1 ³(s) (1 #k(x)¡ )¡ Æ x Spec(Z) ¡ 2j j where k(x) is the residue field at x. Definition. For any scheme X of finite type over Z, (i.e. any “arithmetic scheme") we define Y s 1 ³X (s) (1 #k(x)¡ )¡ Æ x X ¡ 2j j the product being taken over all closed points, and k(x) denotes the residue field. Exercise. Show that in this situation k(x) is always a finite field, so the definition makes sense. Example. Suppose that K/Q is finite, with ring of integers OK . Then taking X Spec(OK ) Æ we get Y s 1 ³Spec (s) (1 Np¡ )¡ (OK ) Æ ¡ p OK ½ which is the usual Dedekind zeta function ³K (s) of K. There is also a Riemann hypothesis 1 for ³K , again stating that zeroes of ³K with 0 Re(s) 1 satisfy Re(s) . Ç Ç Æ 2 1 ¡ ¢ Example. X AF Spec Fp t . Æ p Æ J K n 1 o © ª closed points of A irreducible polynomials over Fp Fp $ Y ds Nd ³ 1 (s) (1 p¡ )¡ AF ) p Æ d 1 ¡ ¸ 1 s where Nd # irreducible polynomials of degree d.
    [Show full text]
  • JOINT CNU-USTC-SUST SEMINAR on P-ADIC DEFORMATION of ALGEBRAIC CYCLE CLASSES AFTER BLOCH-ESNAULT-KERZ
    JOINT CNU-USTC-SUST SEMINAR ON p-ADIC DEFORMATION OF ALGEBRAIC CYCLE CLASSES AFTER BLOCH-ESNAULT-KERZ 1. Introduction Our joint seminar program is to understand the paper [4] that study the p-adic variation of Hodge conjecture of Fontaine-Messing ([6], see also [4, Conjecture 1.2]) which states roughly as follows: For simplicity, let X=W be a smooth pro- jective scheme, with W = W (k) the Witt ring of a perfect field k of characteristic 1 p > 0. If the crystalline cycle class of an algebraic cycle Z1 in the special fiber X1 = X × k has the correct Hodge level under the canonical isomorphism of Berthelot-Ogus ∗ ∼ ∗ (1.0.1) Hcris(X1=W ) = HdR(X=W ); then it can be lifted to an algebraic cycle Z of X. This problem is known when the dimension of an cycle is zero dimensional (trivial by smoothness) and codi- mension one case (Betherlot-Ogus [2, Theorem 3.8]). The article [4] proved that, under some technical condition arising from integral p-adic Hodge theory, once the Hodge level is correct, the cycle can be formally lifted to the p-adic formal scheme X = \ lim "X ⊗ W=pn of X, and it remains to be an open problem that · −!n whether there exists some formal lifting which is algebraic. The p-adic variation of Hodge conjecture is a p-adic analogue of the infinites- imal variation of Hodge conjecture ([4, Conjecture 1.1]): in this conjecture the base ring is the formal disk, i.e., the spectrum of k[[t]] where k is a character- istic zero field, and the Berthelot-Ogus isomorphism (1.0.1) is replaced by the trivialization of Gauß-Manin connection over the formal disk ([13, Proposition 8.9]) ∗ ∼ ∗ (1.0.2) (HdR(X1=k) ⊗ k[[t]]; id ⊗ d) = (HdR(X=k[[t]]); rGM): It can be shown that the infinitesimal variation of Hodge conjecture is equivalent to the original version of Grothendieck on variation of Hodge conjecture ([11], page 103 footnote), which is indeed a direct consequence of Hodge conjecture after Deligne's global invariant cycle theorem.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1710.02344V3 [Math.AG] 12 Jun 2019 Mirror Symmetry, Mixed Motives, and Ζ(3)
    Mirror symmetry, mixed motives, and ζ(3) Minhyong Kim1 and Wenzhe Yang2 1Mathematical Institute, University of Oxford 2Stanford Institute for Theoretical Physics June 14, 2019 Abstract In this paper, we present an application of mirror symmetry to arithmetic geometry. The main result is the computation of the period of a mixed Hodge structure, which lends evidence to its expected motivic origin. More precisely, given a mirror pair (M,W ) of Calabi-Yau threefolds, the prepotential of the complexified K¨ahler moduli space of M admits an expansion with a constant term that is frequently of the form −3 χ(M) ζ(3)/(2πi)3 + r, where r ∈ Q and χ(M) is the Euler characteristic of M. We focus on the mirror pairs for which the deformation space of the mirror threefold W forms part of a one-parameter algebraic family Wϕ defined over Q and the large complex structure limit is a rational point. Assuming a version of the mirror conjecture, we compute the limit mixed Hodge 3 structure on H (Wϕ) at the large complex structure limit. It turns out to have a direct summand expressible as an extension of Q(−3) by Q(0) whose isomorphism class can be computed in terms of the prepotential of M, and hence, involves ζ(3). By way arXiv:1710.02344v3 [math.AG] 12 Jun 2019 of Ayoub’s works on the motivic nearby cycle functor, this reveals in precise form a connection between mirror symmetry and a variant of the Hodge conjecture for mixed Tate motives. 0. Introduction Over 50 years of research on motives has continued to enrich virtually all areas of number theory and algebraic geometry with a wide-ranging supply of unifying themes as well as deep formulas.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Motives
    Introduction to motives Sujatha Ramdorai and Jorge Plazas With an appendix by Matilde Marcolli Abstract. This article is based on the lectures of the same tittle given by the first author during the instructional workshop of the program \number theory and physics" at ESI Vienna during March 2009. An account of the topics treated during the lectures can be found in [24] where the categorical aspects of the theory are stressed. Although naturally overlapping, these two independent articles serve as complements to each other. In the present article we focus on the construction of the category of pure motives starting from the category of smooth projective varieties. The necessary preliminary material is discussed. Early accounts of the theory were given in Manin [21] and Kleiman [19], the material presented here reflects to some extent their treatment of the main aspects of the theory. We also survey the theory of endomotives developed in [5], this provides a link between the theory of motives and tools from quantum statistical mechanics which play an important role in results connecting number theory and noncommutative geometry. An extended appendix (by Matilde Marcolli) further elaborates these ideas and reviews the role of motives in noncommutative geometry. Introduction Various cohomology theories play a central role in algebraic geometry, these co- homology theories share common properties and can in some cases be related by specific comparison morphisms. A cohomology theory with coefficients in a ring R is given by a contra-variant functor H from the category of algebraic varieties over a field k to the category of graded R-algebras (or more generally to a R-linear tensor category).
    [Show full text]
  • Algebraic Cycles and Topology of Real Enriques Surfaces
    Compositio Mathematica 110: 215±237, 1998. 215 c 1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Algebraic cycles and topology of real Enriques surfaces ?? FRED ERIC MANGOLTE1 ? and JOOST VAN HAMEL2 1Laboratoire de Mathematiques, Universite de Savoie, 73376 Le Bourget du Lac Cedex, France; e-mail: [email protected] 2Institute of Mathematics, University of Utrecht, Budapestlaan 6, 3584 CD Utrecht, The Netherlands; e-mail: [email protected] Received:14 May 1996; accepted in ®nal form 22 October 1996 H Y R; Z= Abstract. For a real Enriques surface Y we prove that every homology class in 1 2 can be R represented by a real algebraic curve if and only if all connected components of Y are orientable. Furthermore, we give a characterization of real Enriques surfaces which are Galois-Maximal and/or Y Z-Galois-Maximal and we determine the Brauer group of any real Enriques surface . Mathematics Subject Classi®cations (1991): 14C25 14P25 14J28 13A20. Key words: Algebraic cycles, real algebraic surfaces, Enriques surfaces, Galois-Maximality, Brauer group. 1. Introduction Y C Let Y be a complex algebraic surface. Let us denote by the set of closed points alg H Y C ; Z of Y endowed with the Euclidean topology and let 2 be the subgroup Y C ; Z of the homology group H2 generated by the fundamental classes of Y algebraic curves on Y .If is an Enriques surface, we have alg Y C ; Z=H YC;Z: H2 2 One of the goals of the present paper is to prove a similar property for real Enriques surfaces with orientable real part.
    [Show full text]
  • G Aperf–Modules and De Rham Cohomology
    perf Ga –modules and de Rham Cohomology Shubhodip Mondal Abstract We prove that algebraic de Rham cohomology as a functor defined on smooth Fp–algebras is formally perf ´etale in a precise sense. To prove this, we define and study the notion of a pointed Ga –module and its perf refinement which we call a quasi-ideal in Ga following Drinfeld. Our results show that given de Rham cohomology, one obtains the theory of crystalline cohomology as its unique functorial deformation. Contents 1 Introduction 2 1.1 Overviewoftheresults............................... ......... 2 1.2 Motivationsandrelatedwork . ......... 5 1.3 Acknowledgements .................................. ........ 6 2 Modules over ring schemes 7 2.1 Ga–modules............................................ .. 7 Gperf 2.2 a –modules............................................ 8 2.3 TheHodgemap...................................... ...... 11 2.4 Cartierduality ...................................... ...... 12 G Gperf 2.5 Deformations of some a and a –modules ........................... 14 G Gperf 3 Construction of functors using a and a –modules 18 3.1 Tensoring a module with a module scheme. ......... 18 3.2 Unwinding pointed Ga–modules. .................................. 19 Gperf 3.3 Unwinding pointed a –modulesI. ................................ 23 Gperf 3.4 Unwinding pointed a –modulesII................................. 26 3.5 Hodgefiltration..................................... ....... 31 4 Review of de Rham and Crystalline cohomology 33 5 Formal ´etaleness of de Rham cohomology 35 arXiv:2101.03146v1 [math.AG] 8 Jan 2021 5.1 First proof using deformation theory of u∗W [F ]. ......................... 35 5.2 Second proof using deformation theory of W [F ]. ......................... 36 1 1 Introduction 1.1 Overview of the results Let X be a scheme over a field k. Grothendieck defined the algebraic de Rham cohomology of X to be the ∗ hypercohomology of the algebraic de Rham complex ΩX [Gro66].
    [Show full text]