Virtues of Man, Woman – Or Human Being?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Virtues of Man, Woman – Or Human Being? Liisa Tuomela VIRTUES OF MAN, WOMAN – OR HUMAN BEING? An Intellectual Historical Study on the Views of the Later Stoics Seneca the Younger, Musonius Rufus, Epictetus, Hierocles and Marcus Aurelius on the Sameness of the Virtues of Man and Woman Academic dissertation to be publicly discussed, by due permission of the Faculty of Arts at the University of Helsinki in auditorium XII, on the 10th of September, 2014 at 12 o’clock. ISBN 978-951-51-0073-3 (paperback) ISBN 978-951-51-0074-0 (PDF) ABSTRACT The aim of this intellectual historical study is (using, modified for the purposes of the study, (con)textual analysis, philological method and approaches of women’s/gender history) to examine the views of the later Stoics Seneca the Younger, Musonius Rufus, Epictetus, Hierocles and Marcus Aurelius on the sameness of the virtues of man and woman, a question which gives a very non-anachronistic perspective on sameness, otherness, equality and inequality in Greek and Roman thinking. The basis of the study consists of two ideas found in Stoicism since its beginning: that the individual virtues are common to all human beings and that virtue as such is natural and possible to all. At the same time, other authors and material discussing women’s virtues are used as an ideological background and context, i.e. views emphasising difference/ inequality (or, in short, “otherness”) and views emphasising sameness/equality at least more than on average. Thus, it is an important aspect of this study to examine the proportion of these kinds of attitudes in the later Stoics, and how consistently they follow the two above-mentioned Stoic ideas in their construction of ‘woman’ in relation to ‘man’ and ‘human being’ It is obvious that the sameness of the virtues of man and woman, discussed most intentionally and consistently by Musonius, who also most unambiguously equates ‘woman’ with ‘human being’, means two things also for the later Stoics: that everyone has at least in principle capacity to acquire virtue and that the virtues of both sexes are the so-called cardinal virtues, i.e. prudence, bravery, self-control and justice. Thus, even bravery is not a masculine but a human virtue, and the sameness of man and woman does not mean that a woman becomes “masculine”, but their sameness is based on their common (rational) humanhood. Equality resulting from sameness is especially in Musonius not only theoretical but also practical in a wider sense and on a larger scale than usual, above all in the division of tasks, whereas Seneca, advocating many traditional ideals, constructs the gender of women mostly very conservatively and even reacts negatively to contemporary changes in women’s social/societal roles and spheres. He also refers to women’s emotional “weakness”, but does not, however, see it as specific only to women and seems to be convinced that women, too, can overcome it and be (at least in principle) equal in virtue - emphasising thus, after all, the fundamental sameness rather than otherness of women. The views of the later Stoics provide a rather exceptional and ungendered perspective on individual virtues, capacity for virtue and philosophical education, as well as on sameness, otherness, equality and inequality, and what is “masculine”, “feminine” or “human”. Thus, their views are also an important contribution to discussions of who a “full” human being is, in an era when a “human being” was in the first place a (free) man. TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 1. INTRODUCTION 1 1.1. The aim of the study 1 1.2. The basis of the study: Two aspects of the sameness of the virtues of man and woman 3 1.2.1. “ὅτι δὲ οὐκ ἄλλαι ἀρεταὶ ἀνδρός, ἄλλαι δὲ γυναικός, ῥᾴδιον μαθεῖν” 3 1.2.2. “σπέρμα ἀρετῆς ἑκάστῳ ἡμῶν” 5 1.3. The most important sources and earlier research 8 2. SOME BASIC STOIC THOUGHTS CONCERNING VIRTUES 11 . 3. IDEOLOGICAL BACKGROUND: A SURVEY OF THE VIEWS ON THE SAMENESS OF MAN'S AND WOMAN'S VIRTUES IN ANTIQUITY 14 3.1. Thinking emphasising sameness/equality 14 3.2. Conservative thinking emphasising difference/inequality 20 4. THE LATER STOICS ON THE SAMENESS OF THE VIRTUES OF MAN AND WOMAN 27 4.1. The individual virtues - “ὅτι δὲ οὐκ ἄλλαι ἀρεταὶ ἀνδρός, ἄλλαι δὲ γυναικός, ῥᾴδιον μαθεῖν” 27 4.1.1. The sameness of the contents of the virtues 27 4.1.1.1. Prudence and bravery 28 4.1.1.2. Self-control and justice 34 4.1.1.3. Masculine women, masculine virtues? 40 4.1.2. Virtues in practical life 52 4.1.2 1. Seneca 54 4.1.2 2. Musonius, Epictetus, and Hierocles 60 1. Conservative ideals? 60 2. Practical equality and division of tasks 67 i Within the household 67 ii Outside the household 81 4.2. The capacity for virtue in man and woman - “σπέρμα ἀρετῆς ἑκάστῳ ἡμῶν” 93 4.2.1.The innate capacity for virtue 94 4.2.1.1. Musonius and Epictetus on the same capacity for virtue in man and woman 94 4.2.1.2. Seneca on the emotional “weakness” of women 102 . 4.2.2. Educating the innate capacity for virtue 113 4.2.2.1. The content of the philosophical education 113 4.2.2.2. The result of the philosophical education 122 5. CONCLUSION 132 COLLECTIONS OF FRAGMENTS AND INSCRIPTIONS 140 BIBLIOGRAPHY ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This study is now finally completed, not in the early 2000’s, as was intended, but after a long pause due to eye disease. We do not live, after 2000 years, in a world without otherness and inequality, and some are still regarded as more “full” human beings than others. I think that views of antiquity can give some historical perspective. I would like to thank the Institutum Classicum of the University of Helsinki, especially Professor Olli Salomies and Professor Heikki Solin for encouragement. This has been a long process. I would like to thank Intellectual Historian Markku Hyrkkänen for his encouragement when I was preparing my first thesis on this subject. I am also grateful to my late supervisor before my obligatory pause, Professor Juha Sihvola. He also encouraged me to focus still more intensively on the practical equality in the views of the later Stoics. And, of course, I would like to thank my pre-examiners, Docent Marja-Leena Hänninen and Academy Research Fellow Miira Tuominen for their valuable comments. I dedicate this study to my loved ones, with gratitude. 1. INTRODUCTION 1.1. The aim of the study The aim of this doctoral dissertation is to examine what the later Stoics Seneca the Younger (c. 5 BC – 65 AD), Musonius Rufus (c. 30 – c. 100), Epictetus (c. 55 – 135), Hierocles (2nd cent.) and Marcus Aurelius (121 – 180) have understood by the sameness of the virtues of man and woman. It had been discussed since Plato (427 – 347 BC) and Aristotle (384 – 322 BC) whether (or to what extent) human virtues are also women’s virtues, but the later Stoics, with their strong emphasis on practical ethics, offer exceptionally rich material both in its extensivity and versatility: Musonius Rufus treats the virtues of women in more detail than any other author in antiquity, and Seneca wrote even two philosophical consolations to women, to a certain Marcia and to his mother Helvia. The basis of this study consists of two fundamental Stoic thoughts set forth in Stoicism since its beginning: that the individual virtues are common to all human beings, both men and women, and that virtue as such is natural and possible to all. At the same time views of other authors, too, are used as an ideological background and context; these include two main types of attitudes, i.e. conservative1 attitudes (emphasising difference/inequality, or, in short, “otherness”) and attitudes emphasising sameness/equality at least more than on average. Thus, it is an important aspect to examine the proportion of such attitudes in the later Stoics - and how consistently they follow (using also strategies of inclusion/exclusion and categories such as ‘we’, ‘human being’, ‘men - women’, or, as in Seneca, ‘men – exceptional women – other women’) the two above-mentioned Stoic ideas in their construction of ‘woman’ in relation to ‘man’ and ‘human being’. The era itself is also rather interesting because in the first and second centuries AD both conservative and more “egalitarian” attitudes and trends appeared side by side and interacted with each other. And it is also interesting that Musonius’ views on women have been interpreted even in opposite ways: some scholars consider him a feminist, whereas more argue that he to a great extent advocates conservative attitudes2 - an interpretation supported by most scholars also regarding Stoicism and __________________ 1 ‘Conservative’ is used to refer to (old, traditional, etc.) attitudes emphasising difference/inequality. 2 For the former view, e.g., Favez 1933 and Klassen 1984, for the latter view below pp. 53 – 54. 2 especially later Stoicism as a whole: despite ideas and ideals of theoretical equality the Stoics are thought to be conservatives who are not interested in the practical equality of women.1 So, it is also one aim of this study to investigate where this interpretation does not seem to be valid - and how conservatively these Stoics, after all, construct ‘woman’ and women’s gender and roles in this respect, i.e. discuss women’s social/societal “sameness” and “otherness” in this respect. This perspective is of crucial importance because if the later Stoics refer to changes in women’s social/societal role(s), they deviate from Stoicism, for the Stoics thought that one can acquire virtue and happiness regardless of one’s external circumstances, including one’s position and role(s).
Recommended publications
  • 166 BOOK REVIEWS Gretchen Reydams-Schils, the Roman Stoics
    166 BOOK REVIEWS Gretchen Reydams-Schils, The Roman Stoics: Self, Responsibility and Affection. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2005. xii + 210 pp. ISBN 0-226-30837-5. In the third book of the Histones Tacitus presents us with the ludicrous picture of a Stoic philosopher mingling with the soldiers of the Flavian army as it prepares to invade the city, and preaching unheeded the blessings of peace and the dangers of war (3.81). The purveyor of this intempestiva sapientia was Musonius Rufus, an eques Romanus, a friend of many Roman senators, a political exile, and the hero of this book. The author sets out to prove that the Roman Stoics adapted originally Greek Stoic doctrine to emphasize the importance of social responsibility and social engagement to the life of virtue. Stoicism, for all its emphasis on self-sufficiency, independence of outer circumstances, and spiritual self-improvement, saw the instinct for sociability as implanted by divine providence in human beings, who were imbedded in a society of rational beings comprising men and gods. What the author thinks was the distinctive contribution of the Roman Stoics was to retrieve for the life of virtue the traditional relationships of parenthood and marriage that Plato and the Cynics had tried to denigrate. It is therefore not the Musonius Rufus of Roman politics that interests her, but the advocate of marriage as a union of body and soul between equals and the opponent of infanticide and child exposure. The structure of the book reflects this emphasis, for it ‘reverses the Stoic progression from self to god and universe’ (5).
    [Show full text]
  • Peitho12.1-2
    Volume 12 Issue 1/2 SPRING/FALL 2010 Peitho www.cwshrc.org a publication of the coalition of women scholars in the history of rhetoric and composition In this issue: Editor’s Letter Holding Hands and Shaking Hands Intentional Mentoring Mentoring, an Incantation Women in Digital Spaces Roundtable Report A Selection of Secondary Texts Concerning Ancient Women Historical Methodology: Past and “Presentism”? Editor’s Letter Peitho fleeing the seduction of Dear all Leda appearing on an Apulian red I am pleased to present to you the combined Spring/Fall 2010 issues of figure vase, ca. 350-340 B.C.E. Peitho. Much of this combined issue focuses on the topic of the Coalition Wednesday night session at the 2010 C’s. Based on feedback from the 2009 J. Paul Getty Museum Used with permission session in San Francisco, the 2010 Louisville session attempted to examine new ways of mentoring and professional development—the remix, revisit, rethink, revise, renew of the conference’s call for papers. We are pleased to present here a number of the presentations from that Coalition Officers session. Marcy Tucker’s “Holding Hands and Shaking Hands: Learning to Profit from the Professional Mentor-Mentee Relationship” argues for looking President Nancy Meyers (Continued on page 5) University of North Carolina at Greensboro Holding Hands and Shaking Hands: Vice-President Elizabeth Tasker Learning to Profit from the Professional Stephen F. Austin State University Mentor-Mentee Relationship Treasurer Lisa Mastrangelo Marcy Tucker College of St. Elizabeth Secretary Scholars and students of feminist movement understand that we should Jenn Fishman never assume that anything is natural to any particular group; however, those University of Tennessee-Knoxville of us who teach rhetoric and composition, and especially those of us who are Member-at-Large female and who support interactive pedagogies, have long contended with Lynée Lewis Gaillet the assumption that we are (or should be) nurturing.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Xerox University Microfilms
    INFORMATION TO USERS This material was produced from a microfilm copy of the original document. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the original submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or patterns which may appear on this reproduction. 1. The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is "Missing Paga(s)". If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting thru an image and duplicating adjacent pages to insure you complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a large round black mark, it is an indication that the photographer suspected that the copy may have moved during exposure and thus causa a blurred image. You will find a good image of the page in the adjacent frame. 3. When a map, drawing or chart, etc., was part of the material being photographed the photographer followed a definite method in "sectioning" the material. It is customary to begin photoing at the upper left hand corner of a large sheet and to continue photoing from left to right in equal sections with a small overlap. If necessary, sectioning is continued again - beginning below the first row and continuing on until complete. 4. The majority of users indicate that the textual content is of greatest value, however, a somewhat higher quality reproduction could be made from "photographs" if essential to the understanding of the dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • De Otio De Brevitate Vitae
    SENECA DE OTIO DE BREVITATE VITAE G. D. WILLIAMS Associate Professor of Classics, Columbia University, New York The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge , United Kingdom The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge, ,UK West th Street, New York, -, USA Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, , Australia Ruiz de Alarc´on , Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town , South Africa http://www.cambridge.org C Cambridge University Press This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published Printed in the United Kingdom at the University Press, Cambridge Typefaces Baskerville / pt and New Hellenic System LATEX ε [] A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library hardback paperback CONTENTS Preface page vii Conventions and abbreviations viii Introduction Author and date: initial problems The Dialogues in context (a) The Stoicbackground (b) The Roman philosophical tradition (c) From Republicto Empire De otio (a) The view from above (b) Date, addressee and related problems De breuitate uitae (a) Preliminaries (b) Date and addressee (c) Theme and interpretation Style and language (a) Senecan style: context and general tendency (b) Senecan mannerism, vocabulary, wordplay The transmission of the text L. ANNAEI SENECAE DE OTIO; DE BREVITATE VITAE Commentary Bibliography Indexes General Latin words Greek words v INTRODUCTION . AUTHOR AND DATE: INITIAL PROBLEMS Born into a provincial equestrian family of Italian extraction at Corduba (modern C´ordoba) in southern Spain, Lucius Annaeus Seneca (c. – ) wasraisedand educated from an early age at Rome.
    [Show full text]
  • Kristeva Paper Submissible Substance Revised
    Lampe, K. W. (2016). Kristeva, Stoicism, and the "True Life of Interpretations". SubStance, 45(1), 22-43. https://doi.org/10.3368/ss.45.1.22 Peer reviewed version Link to published version (if available): 10.3368/ss.45.1.22 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document This is not the final version of record. This can viewed (C) The Board of Regents of the University of Wisconsin System at http://sub.uwpress.org/content/45/1/22.refs University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ ! ! Kristeva, Stoicism, and the “True Life of Interpretations” The repertory of theories, practices, and stories associated with Greek and Roman Stoicism fills a significant compartment in the western philosophical archive, the meaning and value of which are ceaselessly reconfigured by each generation’s archivists. In the recent decades it is not only specialists who have browsed, rearranged, and relabeled these shelves; following Foucault’s Hermeneutics of the Subject as well as a powerful synergy between Anglophone scholars and cognitive-behavioral therapists, there is now a wave of enthusiasm, inquiry, and experimentation.1 Into these vigorous currents I propose that we release yet another stream, namely the numerous commentaries on Stoicism in the psychoanalytic, literary, and broadly
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION Aules Persius Flaccus Was Born Into a Middle
    INTRODUCTION Stoic Satire Aules Persius Flaccus was born into a middle-class family on 4th December, A.D. 34, at Volaterrae in Etruria. At the age of twelve, he moved to Rome to further his education and four years later joined the circle of the Stoic philosopher Lucius Annaeus Cornutus. It was the beginning of a lifelong association for Persius, who acknowledges his debt to Cornutus' teachings in Satire 5. Other Stoics befriended by Persius included the poet Lucan and the leader of the 'Stoic opposition' to Nero in the Senate, Thrasea Paetus. He also met Seneca. Persius shunned a public career, apparently preferring a more sheltered way oflife. He died on 24th November, A.D. 62. 1 In contrast to Lucilius, Horace and Juvenal, who adopt Stoic ethics only occasionally and display a generally lukewarm attitude towards them, Persius is a wholehearted subscriber. Stoicism is most noticeable in Satires 3 and 5, but it runs through all his other poems with the exception of Satire 6. The depth and sincerity of Persius' commitment to Stoicism is indicated by, inter alia, his passionate condemnation of materialism in contemporary religion (2.61-75), the forceful Stoic sermon directed against himself (3.15-62), his flattering tribute to Cornutus (5.21-51) and the relentless and uncompromising diatribe on libertas (5.83-123). The element of positive moral exhortation is far more marked in Persius' poetry than in that of Horace and Juvenal. The latter tend to criticise failings and vices in a negative manner, censuring and ridiculing without specifying an alternative way of life.
    [Show full text]
  • Jakub Pigon, Reviewing Jacqueline M. Carlon, Pliny's Women
    Jacqueline M. Carlon, Pliny’s Women: Constructing Virtue and Creating Identity in the Roman World. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. Pp. x + 270. Cloth, $85. The book under review is yet another proof of the growing interest in Pliny the Younger, an author who, only some twenty years ago, seemed rather neglected by classical scholars. Since the late nineties, a number of book-length treatments of his work have appeared, including monographs by Ludolph (1997), Hoffer (1999), Beutel (2000), Henderson (2002), Méthy (2007), Marchesi (2008) and, most recently, Lefèvre (2009), as well as two conference volumes edited by, respectively, Castagna and Lefèvre (2003) and Morello and Gibson (as a special issue of Arethusa 36 [2003], 2). Here we have a book which, to my knowledge, is the first full-length study on Pliny’s representation of women (another book, by Jo-Ann Shelton, is announced for January 2011 by Routledge). Women play, at least by Roman standards, quite an important role in Pliny’s correspondence. According to Carlon’s own figures (p. 8), out of the 368 letters of the whole corpus (books 1–10) no less than 72 contain some references to women (see the table in Appendix B, pp. 223–226); within this group, women appear as the main or significant subject in 38 letters. In this rewritten version of a Boston University PhD thesis (supervised by Ann Vasaly), Jacqueline Carlon (henceforth, C.) shows how more or less detailed descriptions of, and references to, women in Pliny’s correspondence serve what she identifies as the overriding goal of his literary pursuits, namely the securing of his own aeternitas (this key term is, characteristically, the last word of her book).
    [Show full text]
  • 2 the School in the Roman Imperial Period
    christopher gill 2 The School in the Roman Imperial Period 1. the stereotype According to a stereotypical view, Stoicism in the period of the Roman Empire was philosophically uncreative. The ‘school’ had an ill-defined institutional status and there was a good deal of eclecti- cism and merging of different philosophies. The dominant theme was ethics, and the main surviving works consist of exercises in practical moralising based on ideas mapped out centuries before. Unsurpris- ingly, in the later part of this period, Stoicism was replaced as a living philosophy by a revived Platonism and by a form of Christianity that was increasingly more sophisticated and theoretically aware. Like all stereotypes, this one contains an element of truth; but it obscures important respects in which Stoicism continued as an active philosophical force for at least the first two centuries a.d. Although there was no institutional ‘school’ as there was in the Hellenistic Age, there were numerous Stoic teachers, and the distinc- tive three-part Stoic educational curriculum was maintained, with important work continuing in all three areas (i.e., logic, ethics, and physics). As well as being the dominant philosophical movement in the period, Stoicism was also strongly embedded in Greco-Roman culture and, to some extent, in political life, and the ideal of living a properly Stoic life remained powerful. In the third and fourth cen- turies a.d. and later, Neoplatonic and Christian writers built on key Stoic ideas and absorbed them into their systems. 33 Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006 34 christopher gill 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoic Argument from Oikeiōsis
    Created on 2 December 2015 at 9.14 hours page 143 THESTOICARGUMENT FROM OIKEIŌSIS JACOBKLEIN . Introduction S Stoic accounts of oikeiōsis—appropriation, as I will translate it—are marked by two features: they begin with the ap- parently descriptive claim that the complex, seemingly purposeful behaviour all animals display in relation to their environment depends on a sophisticated capacity for self-perception. They con- clude, on the other hand, with the normative thesis that the human good consists in a life regulated by reason or, as the Stoics some- times describe it, in a life lived according to nature. This account is central to three of the fullest surviving presentations of Stoic ethics, and sources report that the Stoics appealed to it to defend their conception of the human good in general and their account of justice in particular. Since Pohlenz, most commentators have regarded the oikeiōsis doctrine as substantially Stoic in origin and important, one way or another, to Stoic ethical theory. But they © Jacob Klein I am especially grateful to Tad Brennan and Charles Brittain for extensive discus- sion, detailed criticism, and encouragement at crucial points. For insightful written comments I thank Victor Caston, Gail Fine, Brad Inwood, Terry Irwin, Nate Jezzi, Anthony Long, Martha Nussbaum, and an anonymous referee for this journal. I have benefited from (and greatly enjoyed) discussions with Margaret Graver, Lar- kin Philpot, Gretchen Reydams-Schils, Timothy Roche, and Maura Tumulty. Er- rors and shortcomings are my own. On the translation of oikeiōsis and its cognates see nn. and below. Diogenes Laertius (. – = LS A= SVF iii.
    [Show full text]
  • Here an Attempt Was Made to Analyse the Nexus of Familial, Amical and Patronal Ties Wherein Domitius Corbulo Flourished
    DOMITIUS CORBULO AND THE SENATORIAL OPPOSITION TO THE REIGN OF NERO* I. INTRODUCTION Domitius Corbulo enjoyed trust and considerable favour with Gaius and Claudius. In AD 39, he became consul suffectus, no doubt as a conse- quence of his well-attested connections to the domus Augusta and prob- ably as a token of imperial gratitude for the financial profits Gaius made out of the prosecutions of the highway commissioners that Corbulo’s ran- corous (and homonymous) father had pursued ever since the rule of Tiberius. Although in 43, Claudius forced Corbulo Maior to repay a part of the fines to his victims, the star of Corbulo the Younger continued to rise. In 47, he achieved military repute as legatus Augusti pro praetore exercitus Germaniae inferioris, receiving the ornamenta triumphalia for his ruthless campaign against several Germanic tribes. Around AD 52, Corbulo got the prestigious proconsulate of Asia. That Nero also had complete confidence in Corbulo up to and including the eventful year of AD 65, is irrefutable1. In 63, the emperor commanded all legati Augusti pro praetore serving in the Eastern imperial provinces to obey the military orders of Corbulo, whose imperium pro praetore was * This paper may be construed as the complement of A Note on Syme’s Chronology of Vistilia’s Children, AncSoc 30 (2000), p. 95-113, where an attempt was made to analyse the nexus of familial, amical and patronal ties wherein Domitius Corbulo flourished. The results of this analysis may help to explain Corbulo’s unusually successful political and military career. I sincerely wish to thank Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • 99-114 the Suicides of Otho and Nero in Suetonius Mb
    THE SUICIDES OF OTHO AND NERO IN SUETONIUS M B Charles (Southern Cross Business School, Southern Cross University) and E Anagnostou-Laoutides (School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University) Both Otho and Nero are usually regarded as ‘bad’ emperors in the historical record, and their conduct is often assimilated. Yet Suetonius’ treatment of their suicides, while cleverly approximating the two events, nevertheless shows clear differences. While Nero appears weak and without resolve, Otho bravely shrugs off his supposed effeminacy and dies a true Roman emperor, more so since his death was intended to preserve the lives of his fellow citizens. Suetonius deliberately composed Otho’s exitus scene in such a way as to leave the reader with a positive impression of the emperor, simultaneously to the detriment of Nero. It is well known that Suetonius placed a good deal of import on the deaths of his imperial subjects, including the omens presaging them, and the precise context in which the emperors met their ends.1 These death-scenes, it follows, are meant to provide a final illumination of the character of his subjects, something very much in keeping with general attitudes in the ancient world towards death.2 Describing a person’s manner of death, to Suetonius and his contemporaries, effectively constituted providing a person’s literary epitaph, distilling much of what we need to remember about that person’s character, with Arand (2002:230-232) even suggesting that the deaths of ‘bad’ emperors offer more scope for literary effect. Given Suetonius’ general propensity to arrange his material so as to cohere with 1 Translations in this article are taken directly or else are adapted from the relevant Loeb editions.
    [Show full text]