Explaining Postmodernism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Explaining Postmodernism Explaining Postmodernism Explaining Postmodernism Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault Expanded Edition Stephen R. C. Hicks Ockham’s Razor Publishing First Edition published in 2004 by Scholargy Publishing Expanded Edition published in 2011 by Ockham’s Razor Publishing © 2004, 2011, 2014 by Stephen R. C. Hicks All rights reserved 14 15 16 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Expanded Edition Second Printing Tenth Anniversary Printing Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data pending Hicks, Stephen R. C., 1960- Explaining postmodernism: skepticism and socialism from Rousseau to Foucault / Stephen Hicks. p. 276 cm. Includes bibliographic references. Includes index. ISBN: 978-0-9832584-0-7 (cloth) ISBN: (paper) 1. Title. 2. Intellectual History—Modern. 3. Socialism—History. 4. United States— Intellectual Life—20th century. 5. Education, Higher—Po- litical aspects. 6. Art—History Printed in China This book is printed on acid-free paper Contents Thesis: The failure of epistemology made postmodernism possible, and the failure of socialism made postmodernism necessary. List of Tables and Charts v Chapter One: What Postmodernism Is The postmodern vanguard 1 Foucault, Lyotard, Derrida, Rorty Modern and postmodern 5 Modernism and the Enlightenment 7 Postmodernism versus the Enlightenment 14 Postmodern academic themes 15 Postmodern cultural themes 18 Why postmodernism? 20 Chapter Two: The Counter-Enlightenment Attack on Reason Enlightenment reason, liberalism, and science 23 The beginnings of the Counter-Enlightenment 24 Kant’s skeptical conclusion 27 Kant’s problematic from empiricism and rationalism 29 Kant’s essential argument 32 Identifying Kant’s key assumptions 36 Why Kant is the turning point 39 After Kant: reality or reason but not both 42 Metaphysical solutions to Kant: from Hegel to Nietzsche 44 Dialectic and saving religion 46 Hegel’s contribution to postmodernism 50 Epistemological solutions to Kant: irrationalism from Kierkegaard 51 to Nietzsche Summary of irrationalist themes 56 ii Chapter Three: The Twentieth-Century Collapse of Reason Heidegger’s synthesis of the Continental tradition 58 Setting aside reason and logic 61 Emotions as revelatory 62 Heidegger and postmodernism 65 Positivism and Analytic philosophy: from Europe to America 67 From Positivism to Analysis 70 Recasting philosophy’s function 72 Perception, concepts, and logic 74 From the collapse of Logical Positivism to Kuhn and Rorty 78 Summary: A vacuum for postmodernism to fill 79 First thesis: Postmodernism as the end result of Kantian 80 epistemology Chapter Four: The Climate of Collectivism From postmodern epistemology to postmodern politics 84 The argument of the next three chapters 86 Responding to socialism’s crisis of theory and evidence 89 Back to Rousseau 91 Rousseau’s Counter-Enlightenment 92 Rousseau’s collectivism and statism 96 Rousseau and the French Revolution 100 Counter-Enlightenment Politics: Right and Left collectivism 104 Kant on collectivism and war 106 Herder on multicultural relativism 109 Fichte on education as socialization 112 Hegel on worshipping the state 120 From Hegel to the twentieth century 124 Right versus Left collectivism in the twentieth century 125 The Rise of National Socialism: Who are the real socialists? 130 Chapter Five: The Crisis of Socialism Marxism and waiting for Godot 135 Three failed predictions 136 Socialism needs an aristocracy: Lenin, Mao, and the lesson of the 138 German Social Democrats Good news for socialism: depression and war 141 Bad news: liberal capitalism rebounds 143 Worse news: Khrushchev’s revelations and Hungary 145 iii Responding to the crisis: change socialism’s ethical standard 150 From need to equality 151 From wealth is good to wealth is bad 153 Responding to the crisis: change socialism’s epistemology 156 Marcuse and the Frankfurt School: Marx plus Freud, or 159 oppression plus repression The rise and fall of Left terrorism 166 From the collapse of the New Left to postmodernism 170 Chapter Six: Postmodern Strategy Connecting epistemology to politics 174 Masks and rhetoric in language 175 When theory clashes with fact 178 Kierkegaardian postmodernism 179 Reversing Thrasymachus 182 Using contradictory discourses as a political strategy 184 Machiavellian postmodernism 186 Machiavellian rhetorical discourses 187 Deconstruction as an educational strategy 188 Ressentiment postmodernism 191 Nietzschean ressentiment 192 Foucault and Derrida on the end of man 195 Ressentiment strategy 198 Post-postmodernism 201 Bibliography 202 Index 212 Acknowledgements 223 Two Additional Essays Free Speech and Postmodernism Sample speech codes 225 Why not rely on the First Amendment? 226 Context: why the Left? 227 Affirmative action as a working example 228 Egalitarianism 231 Inequalities along racial and sexual lines 233 The social construction of minds 234 Speakers and censors 236 iv The heart of the debate 238 The justification of freedom of speech 239 Three special cases 241 Racial and sexual hate speech 242 The university as a special case 243 From Modern to Postmodern Art: Why Art Became Ugly Introduction: the death of modernism 247 Modernism’s themes 248 Postmodernism’s four themes 257 The future of art 263 * * * v List of Tables and Charts Chart 1.1: Defining Pre-modernism and Modernism 8 Chart 1.2: The Enlightenment Vision 13 Chart 1.3: Defining Pre-modernism, Modernism, and 15 Postmodernism Chart 5.1: Marxism on the Logic of Capitalism 138 Chart 5.2: Total Livestock in the Soviet Union 144 Chart 5.3: Gross Physical Output for Selected Food Items 145 Chart 5.4: Deaths from Democide Compared to Deaths from 148 International War, 1900-1987 Chart 5.5: Left Terrorist Groups’ Founding Dates 168 Chart 5.6: The Evolution of Socialist Strategies 173 * * * Chapter One What Postmodernism Is The postmodern vanguard By most accounts we have entered a new intellectual age. We are postmodern now. Leading intellectuals tell us that mod- ernism has died, and that a revolutionary era is upon us—an era liberated from the oppressive strictures of the past, but at the same time disquieted by its expectations for the future. Even postmodernism’s opponents, surveying the intellectual scene and not liking what they see, acknowledge a new cut- ting edge. In the intellectual world, there has been a changing of the guard. The names of the postmodern vanguard are now familiar: Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Jean-François Lyotard, and Richard Rorty. They are its leading strategists. They set the direction of the movement and provide it with its most potent tools. The vanguard is aided by other familiar and often in- famous names: Stanley Fish and Frank Lentricchia in literary and legal criticism, Catharine MacKinnon and Andrea Dwor- kin in feminist legal criticism, Jacques Lacan in psychology, Robert Venturi and Andreas Huyssen in architectural criti- cism, and Luce Irigaray in the criticism of science. Members of this elite group set the direction and tone for the postmodern intellectual world. 2 Explaining Postmodernism Michel Foucault has identified the major targets: “All my analyses are against the idea of universal necessities in hu- man existence.”1 Such necessities must be swept aside as bag- gage from the past: “It is meaningless to speak in the name of—or against—Reason, Truth, or Knowledge.”2 Richard Rorty has elaborated on that theme, explaining that that is not to say that postmodernism is true or that it of- fers knowledge. Such assertions would be self-contradictory, so post-modernists must use language “ironically.” The difficulty faced by a philosopher who, like my- self, is sympathetic to this suggestion [e.g., Fou- cault’s]—one who thinks of himself as auxiliary to the poet rather than to the physicist—is to avoid hint- ing that this suggestion gets something right, that my sort of philosophy corresponds to the way things re- ally are. For this talk of correspondence brings back just the idea my sort of philosopher wants to get rid of, the idea that the world or the self has an intrinsic nature.3 If there is no world or self to understand and get right on their terms, then what is the purpose of thought or ac- tion? Having deconstructed reason, truth, and the idea of the correspondence of thought to reality, and then set them aside—“reason,” writes Foucault, “is the ultimate language of madness”4—there is nothing to guide or constrain our thoughts and feelings. So we can do or say whatever we feel like. Deconstruction, Stanley Fish confesses happily, “relieves me of the obligation to be right … and demands only that I be interesting.”5 1 Foucault 1988, 11. 2 Foucault, in May 1993, 2. 3 Rorty 1989, 7-8. 4 Foucault 1965, 95. 5 Fish 1982, 180. What Postmodernism Is 3 Many postmodernists, though, are less often in the mood for aesthetic play than for political activism. Many decon- struct reason, truth, and reality because they believe that in the name of reason, truth, and reality Western civilization has wrought dominance, oppression, and destruction. “Rea- son and power are one and the same,” Jean-François Lyotard states. Both lead to and are synonymous with “prisons, pro- hibitions, selection process, the public good.”6 Postmodernism then becomes an activist strategy against the coalition of reason and power. Postmodernism, Frank Lentricchia explains, “seeks not to find the foundation and the conditions of truth but to exercise power for the purpose of social change.” The task of postmodern professors is to help students “spot, confront, and work against the political horrors of one’s time”7 Those horrors, according to postmodernism, are most prominent in the West, Western civilization being where rea- son and power have been the most developed. But the pain of those horrors is neither inflicted nor suffered equally. Males, whites, and the rich have their hands on the whip of power, and they use it cruelly at the expense of women, racial minori- ties, and the poor. The conflict between men and women is brutal.
Recommended publications
  • Free Speech and Postmodernism -- Objectivist Center -- Reason, Individu
    Free Speech and Postmodernism -- Objectivist Center -- Reason, Individu... http://www.objectivistcenter.org/navigator/articles/nav+shicks_free-spee... Category: Culture and Politics: General Culture Category: Culture and Politics: Education Source: Navigator, 10/2002 Free Speech and Postmodernism By Stephen Hicks (This article is adapted from the second of a two-lecture address given by Stephen Hicks at TOC's 2002 Summer Seminar.) In the last lecture, we looked at those arguments that won the debate for free speech. Historically, those arguments were nested in different Subscription philosophical contexts, and they were often tailored to audiences hostile Information in varying degrees to free speech. So let me summarize, in contemporary language, the elements of those arguments that are still Free sample with us: (1) Reason is essential for knowing reality. (2) Reason is a function of the individual. (3) What the reasoning individual needs to pursue his knowledge of reality is, above all, freedom—the freedom to think, to criticize, and to debate. (4) The individual's freedom to pursue War for knowledge is of fundamental value to the other members of his society. Civilization Commentaries A corollary of this argument is that when we set up specialized social and links on institutions to seek and advance our knowledge of the truth—scientific 9/11, the wars, societies, research institutes, colleges and universities—we should take the cultural roots special pains to protect, nurture, and encourage the freedom of of terror, and creative minds. It is therefore surprising that the greatest current Western values. threats to free speech come from within our colleges and universities.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of Herbert Spencer
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 CONTROVERSY In Defense of Herbert Spencer ✦ MAX HOCUTT n 1978, Liberty Fund published nineteenth-century intellectual giant Herbert Spencer’s Principles of Ethics in two volumes, with an introduction by Tibor R. IMachan. Spencer’s magnificent tome is full of wisdom and will be read with profit for generations. Machan’s brief introduction is more questionable. Calling it “Herbert Spencer: A Century Later,” Machan begins with some biographical details.
    [Show full text]
  • Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics
    Review Essay: Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist Carrie-Ann Biondi Marymount Manhattan College There has been in academic philosophy a resurgence of naturalistic virtue ethics that renders it a viable competitor with deontology and utilitarianism, making the timing opportune for the appearance of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist.1 Indeed, Smith in part situates her book within this trend, but also contrasts her explication of how Rand’s rational ethical egoism intersects with virtue theories that have at best “danced around the edges of egoism” (p. 1). Thus far, Smith’s book has been generally well received in the few reviews it has gotten,2 especially by scholars and advocates of Rand’s Objectivism. However, some attention from mainstream philosophers, even by those who are sympathetic readers,3 reveals that contemporary moral philosophers struggle to understand the nuanced value theory underlying Objectivism and are slow to embrace full-fledged egoism. This is hardly surprising, given that many (if not most) ethics 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 2 See Stephen Hicks, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophy in Review 27, no. 5 (October 2007), pp. 377-79; Helen Cullyer, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews (November 12, 2006), accessed online at: http://ndpr.nd.edu/review.cfm?id=8123; Robert Mayhew, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophical Books 49, no.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ideas of Ayn Rand
    On Reflection Big Game, Small Gun? By Stephen Hicks The Ideas of Ayn Rand. By Ronald E. Merrill. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court,1991. 191 pp., in- cluding index. $32.95. In his 1987 bestseller on today’s universities, The Closing of the American Mind, Professor Allan Bloom of the University of Chicago offered this comment: ...I began asking my large introductory classes, and any other group of younger students to which I spoke[,] what books really count for them....There is always a girl who men- tions Ayn Rand’s The Fountainhead, a book, though hardly literature, which, with its sub- Nietzschean assertiveness, excites somewhat eccentric youngsters to a new way of life. Professor Bloom’s remark is typical of members of the academic establishment, who almost unanimously agree that Ayn Rand was hardly a serious intellectual and those attracted to her ideas tend to be naive, cultist, and immature. These charges are not news to Objectivists. Nor is it news that they go far to explain the lack of scholarly interest in Rand’s ideas. So it should be exciting news to learn of Ronald Merrill’s The Ideas of Ayn Rand, a systematic investigation of her ideas published by an academic press. Mr. Merrill has been engaged with the fiction and philosophy of Ayn Rand for many years. He is in substantial agreement with her and makes clear where he disagrees. The result is a treatment that is light years better than most by authors claiming to present and critique Rand’s work. Ideas offers many provocative points worthy of discussion and several that are both true and (to my knowledge) original.
    [Show full text]
  • Postmodernism and Censorship
    Free Speech & Postmodernism By Stephen R.C. Hicks, Ph.D. Stephen Hicks is Professor of Philosophy at Rockford College, where he also is Executive Director of the Center for Ethics and Entrepreneurship. He received his B.A. and M.A. degrees from the University of Guelph, Canada, and his Ph.D. from Indiana University. His publications include Explaining Postmodernism (Scholargy, 2004/2011), Nietzsche and the Nazis (Ockham’s Razor, 2010), and essays and reviews in academic and other publications. This essay is adapted from the second of a two-part lecture. In the early modern world, the case for free speech won the battle against traditional authoritarianism. Powerful arguments by Galileo,1 John Locke,2 John Stuart Mill,3 and others won the debate for free speech. Historically, those arguments were nested in different philosophical contexts, and they were often tailored to audiences hostile in varying degrees to free speech. In contemporary language, here are the elements of those arguments that are still with us: (1) Reason is essential for knowing reality (Galileo and Locke). (2) Reason is a function of the individual (Locke, especially). (3) What the reasoning individual needs to pursue knowledge of reality is, above all, freedom—the freedom to think, to criticize, and to debate (Galileo, Locke, and Mill). (4) The individual’s freedom to pursue knowledge is of fundamental value to the other members of his society (Mill, especially). A corollary of this argument is that when we set up specialized social institutions to seek and advance our knowledge of the truth—scientific societies, research institutes, colleges and universities—we should take special pains to protect, nurture, and encourage the freedom of creative minds.
    [Show full text]
  • Carlin Romano on Ayn Rand
    Reason Papers Vol. 34, no. 2 Afterwords America the Philosophical: Carlin Romano on Ayn Rand Stephen Hicks Rockford College Over the years I’ve enjoyed and learned from many of Carlin Romano’s articles in The Chronicle of Higher Education. He can do good philosophical reporting. So I picked up his latest book, America the Philosophical, and I was disappointed.1 Romano’s thesis is that the United States is a nation of vigorous philosophical activity and—contrary to the critics who portray it as an intellectual wasteland of complacency and platitudes—a culture that takes philosophy seriously. It’s a great topic, and I agree with Romano’s thesis. First impressions matter, however, and the first section of America the Philosophical I read was the eight pages on philosopher-novelist Ayn Rand, a case study in how not to write about other philosophers (pp. 359-66). Here’s how to write a book about other philosophers: (1) Present their positions. (2) At least sketch the arguments for the positions they take. (3) Criticize those positions when necessary by making counter- arguments. Here’s how not to write about other philosophers: (4) Ignore the academic literature about the philosopher and use only critical remarks gleaned from amateurs or non-philosopher professionals. (5) Focus more on gossip about the philosopher’s person rather than the person’s philosophy. (6) Identify the philosopher’s views in passing with those of contemporary politicians whom you despise. 1 Carlin Romano, America the Philosophical (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2012). Reason Papers 34, no. 2 (October 2012): 245-247.
    [Show full text]
  • Discussion Notes Tara Smith's Ayn Rand's Normative Ethics: a Positive
    Reason Papers Vol. 35, no. 1 Discussion Notes Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism? Eyal Mozes Bethesda, MD 1. Introduction Reviews of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics,1 written by Objectivists, have been very positive. I believe that this is unfortunate. Smith faithfully paraphrases much of what Rand wrote about normative ethics, but distorts Rand’s philosophy on pretty much any issue on which she goes beyond simple paraphrasing of Rand’s statements. In many cases she directly contradicts Rand’s own statements while pretending to be presenting Rand’s philosophy. In this discussion note I will point out some of the issues on which Smith has seriously distorted Rand’s views that other Objectivist reviewers have either missed or have not discussed adequately. The two reviews of Smith’s book I will specifically address are Stephen Hicks’s 2007 review in Philosophy in Review,2 and Carrie-Ann Biondi’s 2008 review in Reason Papers.3 2. Conflicts of Interests Ayn Rand’s most revolutionary contribution to interpersonal ethics is the principle that there are no conflicts of interests among rational men. This principle is central to the Objectivist concept of selfishness, and is one of the principles that readers of Rand have had the most trouble understanding. For 1 Tara Smith, Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 2 Stephen Hicks, “Review of Tara Smith’s Ayn Rand’s Normative Ethics: The Virtuous Egoist,” Philosophy in Review 27, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining Postmodernism Pdf Download EXPLAINING POSTMODERNISM HICKS PDF
    explaining postmodernism pdf download EXPLAINING POSTMODERNISM HICKS PDF. Explaining Postmodernism by Stephen R.C. Hicks The Righteous Mind by Jonathan Haidt Higher Superstition by Paul R. Gross The Blank Slate by Steven. The UBC Free Speech Club had the absolute honour of hosting Dr. Stephen Hicks earlier in March. We sincerely hope you enjoy this lecture as. PDF | On Jun 1, , Gary Jason and others published Review of: S. Hicks, Explaining Postmodernism: Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault . Author: Mohn Voodoogar Country: Italy Language: English (Spanish) Genre: Finance Published (Last): 6 August 2014 Pages: 85 PDF File Size: 18.81 Mb ePub File Size: 2.73 Mb ISBN: 506-1-64207-327-7 Downloads: 91247 Price: Free* [ *Free Regsitration Required ] Uploader: Gosho. In this book, Mr. This book is mostly polemical in a time where Triumphal liberal capitalism fresh from the end of the cold war could demolish any other point of view towards its end of history as collectivist irrationalism based on appeals grievances of the lower orders. The question that while they were cut from the same cloth of the Enlightenment, as it were, why did they have such different outcomes? View all 12 comments. So maybe its time to take a leaf from the SJW cookbook and repurpose the language to reflect the binary actualite ie. It seems if you are not completely with us, you are against us. I mean, look at the questions that this place has been getting the past day or so. Is there an article about how new atheism Richard Dawkins, Sam Harris, Christopher
    [Show full text]
  • A Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism As an Orientation for Human Life
    Liberty University Journal of Statesmanship & Public Policy Volume 1 Issue 2 Article 2 January 2021 The Failure of Imagination: A Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism as an Orientation for Human Life Maverick Edwards Liberty University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/jspp Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Public Law and Legal Theory Commons Recommended Citation Edwards, Maverick (2021) "The Failure of Imagination: A Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism as an Orientation for Human Life," Liberty University Journal of Statesmanship & Public Policy: Vol. 1 : Iss. 2 , Article 2. Available at: https://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/jspp/vol1/iss2/2 This Research Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholars Crossing. It has been accepted for inclusion in Liberty University Journal of Statesmanship & Public Policy by an authorized editor of Scholars Crossing. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Failure of Imagination: A Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism as an Orientation for Human Life Cover Page Footnote I would like to thank Dr. Mary Prentice for her continued support and encouragement in this project. Her deep knowledge in legal theory and political philosophy has been instrumental and inspiring. I offer my sincerest gratitude to her contribution and insight. This research article is available in Liberty University Journal of Statesmanship & Public Policy: https://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/jspp/vol1/iss2/2 Edwards: The Failure of Imagination: A Theoretical and Pragmatic Analysis of Utopianism Question and Hypothesis The allure of utopia has captivated the minds of philosophers and political theorists from ancient Greece to contemporary Western thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Stephen Hicks's Defence of Individualism
    Do We Know What We Advocate? Stephen Hicks’s Defence of Individualism By Piotr Kostyło Piotr Kostyło is Head of the Department of Philosophy of Education at Casimir the Great University in Bydgoszcz, Poland. The forty-five years of communism in Poland (1944-1989) were marked by the government reminding society of the atrocities committed during World War II by the Nazis. The patriotic attitudes of citizens were formed on the basis of overt hostility to the Germans, who were not only held responsible for Nazi war crimes, but also presented as a source of constant military threat. As Poles, we were told, we had to defend ourselves against this threat, against a new war. And since we were too weak to defend ourselves, we had to ask the great Soviet people for help. In this way, the Communists justified the presence of Soviet troops on Polish territory and, more broadly, the total political and economic subordination of Poland to the interests of the Soviet Union. The Hungarians, Czechs, Slovaks and the Baltic nations heard analogous justifications. The arguments were thoroughly cynical, since democratizing Germany was not a threat to anyone at the time, and no central European nation ever asked the Soviet Union for any help of this kind. Frightening central European societies after 1945 with allegedly resurgent Nazism in Germany was one of the key tools to keep them in a state of bondage and submission to the Soviet Union. The order which was formed after the Second World War in Europe and beyond was also a result of the disaster caused in the 1930s by the Nazis.
    [Show full text]
  • Interview with Stephen Hicks
    Interview with Stephen Hicks by Grégoire Canlorbe Stephen Ronald Craig Hicks (born 1960) is a Canadian-American philosopher who teaches at Rockford University, Illinois, where he also directs the Center for Ethics and Entrepreneurship. Hicks is the author of Explaining Postmodernism: Skepticism and Socialism from Rousseau to Foucault, in which he argues that postmodernism is best understood as a rhetorical strategy of intellectuals and academics on the far- Left of the political spectrum in response to the failure of socialism and communism. His documentary and book Nietzsche and the Nazis is an examination of the ideological roots of National Socialism, particularly how Friedrich Nietzsche’s ideas were used, and in some cases misused, by Adolf Hitler and the Nazis to justify their beliefs and practices. Additionally, Hicks has published articles on free speech in academia, the development of modern art, Ayn Rand’s Objectivism, business ethics, and the philosophy of education, including a series of YouTube lectures. He is also the co-editor, with David Kelley, of a critical thinking textbook, The Art of Reasoning: Readings for Logical Analysis. Grégoire Canlorbe is a French intellectual entrepreneur. He currently resides in Paris. ________________________ Grégoire Canlorbe: According to a popular opinion, left to its own devices, capitalism inevitably tends to a monopoly economy. An economy in which there is no competition. In a monopoly environment, the dominant companies can freeze competition and entrepreneurial initiative. In this regard, any monopoly is problematic, even the monopoly of the local baker or shoemaker. Without competition, the quality of service slips. And innovation becomes an expensive nuisance unless it wildly jacks up profits.
    [Show full text]
  • How Did Friedrich Nietzsche's Ideas Influence the Nazi Regime in The
    How did Friedrich Nietzsche’s ideas influence the Nazi regime in the Third Reich? Adolf Hitler gazing into the bust of Nietzsche, snapshot took in 1934 during one of his visits to the Nietzsche-Archiv in Weimar, Germany. Lucas Carter International School of Toulouse Centre Number: FR042 Candidate Number: Word Count: 4,031 1 Table of Content A. Abstract B. Introduction C. Investigation I. The Will to Power a) Face-value b) Nazi Interpretation c) Nietzsche Explanation II. The Übermensch a) Face-value b) Nazi Interpretation c) Nietzsche Explanation III. Religion a) Face-value b) Nazi Interpretation c) Nietzsche Explanation D. Conclusion E. Bibliography F. Appendices 2 A. Abstract This essay investigates the question “How did Friedrich Nietzsche’s ideas influence the Third Reich?” The investigation makes use of a range of primary and secondary sources. “How to Read Nietzsche” by Keith Ansell Pearson.1 A section from “The Consolations of Philosophy” by Alain de Botton.2 “A Beginner’s Guide to Nietzsche’s Beyond Good and Evil” by Gareth Southwell.3 “Nietzsche: Godfather of Fascism?”4 by James Golomb, “Forgotten Fatherland” by Ben Macintyre5 alongside the BBC2 documentary adaptation of the same name, written and produced by Candida Pyrce-Jones6. All these sources include extracts of Nietzsche’s writings, quotes, letters, as well as extracts from his books. The essay is structured into five main sections, the abstract, introduction, investigation, conclusion and bibliography (in addition with the Appendices). The investigation, the main body of the essay, is divided into three parts; each corresponding to three separate ideas and areas of Nietzsche’s philosophy.
    [Show full text]