Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity Ringmar, Erik 2015 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Ringmar, E. (2015). Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity. Paper presented at Heidegger and the Global Age: An International Conference, University of Sussex, Brighton, United Kingdom. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Quote as Ringmar, Erik, “Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity.” Paper presented at Heidegger and the Global Age: An International Workshop, University of Sussex, Brighton, October 29-30, 2015. Heeding the Call of Being: Heidegger on Attention and Authenticity Erik Ringmar, Dept of Political Science, Lund University The thought of Martin Heidegger has little relevance for international politics. Heidegger did not write about international politics and his Being-in-the-world cannot be mapped onto any of the beings in the world which scholars of international relations study. And yet, as we will argue below, Heidegger's philosophy developed in close interaction with themes discussed by social thinkers of his day — a proximity which often is concealed by the technical vocabulary he uses — and his Dasein is for that reason never only a timeless abstraction but also a historical construction. Heidegger writes about life in modern society, about a modern predicament, and as such he too is a social thinker of sorts. Indeed, some of his main themes — the discussion of moods such as boredom and anxiety, the problem of mass society, and the challenge of how to live an authentic life — were very much discussed by his contemporaries too. However, Heidegger's conclusions differ radically in crucial respects, and this, we will argue, is precisely why he should be of interest to us. It is because his thought tells us nothing about international politics that he is relevant to international politics.1 In order to unpack this rather gnomic statement, we need first to consider the historical background. In the decades prior to Heidegger's Being and Time, 1927, Europe had gone through a quick process of modernization, not least in the case of Germany. In the short span of a few decades, rural, agricultural, society had been transformed into an urban, industrial, society. In the new cities people often felt lost and lonely, yet 1 A kindred argument is Thiele, “Heidegger on Freedom.” 1 / 24 everywhere they found themselves the members of crowds. As one face among many in a mass society, contemporary observers argued, people were quite indistinguishable from each other and most of them passively conformed to social norms and received opinions. People were like sleepwalkers, it was often noticed; they were passive and suggestible and they lived perfectly inauthentic lives. The solution most commonly advocated — indeed the remedy universally prescribed — was to tell people to “strengthen their will” and to “assert themselves.” The themes of will-power and self-assertion were discussed as matters of individual psychology, not least in a slew of self-help books and manuals on “physical culture” and calisthenics. But they were also discussed as matters of political action. A passive and weak-willed person could assert himself by means of physical force; he could strengthen his will by engaging in heroic actions — by going to war, for example, or by going off to fight the natives in some far-flung colony. This is how the rhetoric of self-assertion through military action came to permeate European societies in the first decades of the twentieth-century, creating an affective environment in which wars were more likely and the rhetoric of bellicose dictatorships more persuasive. Self- assertion led to genocide. Heidegger, however, drew completely different conclusions. Although his themes — when recast as sociology — were much the same as those of his contemporaries, “the will” was not an important category for him, and “self-assertion” could never be a matter of asserting a self which existed primordially and in opposition to society. In contrast to Nietzsche, Heidegger described no Übermensch and no “will to power.” Although he diagnosed the social malaise in much the same manner as his contemporaries, that is, his remedies were entirely different. Heidegger is irrelevant to international politics since his philosophy has no bellicose or aggressive implications, but this is precisely why he should be of interest to us. Heidegger provided an alternative solution to the problem of life in modern society, and thereby another solution to the problem of how human beings can learn to live with each other and with the earth they inhabit. As we will argue in what follows, instead of self-assertion, Heidegger emphasized 2 / 24 the importance of attention. Attention too was a topic much discussed during the first decades of the twentieth-century and it was treated at great length by the leading psychologists of the day, not least in Germany. In modern society, in contrast to life in traditional society, you were constantly forced to pay attention — to the fast pace of city life; to the machine which you worked at; to instructions from school teachers and government officials, and so on. It is consequently not surprising that attention features prominently in Heidegger's thought too. Indeed, it is more than anything by studying how attention flags, is distracted or overwhelmed, that we can find Dasein stripped of all its psychological and sociological characteristics. The challenge concerning how to construct an authentic life can from this point of view be understood as a question of how to pay attention to Being. Attention understood as heeding, we will argue, is a solicitous looking out for; it is to attentively keep one's eyes on the horizon. As human beings we have the remarkable opportunity to be present when Being presents itself. Paying heed to this event is to live an authentic life. Moods and the search for Being A discussion of moods is the best place to start. In our everyday vocabulary of affect, references to moods are often freely mixed with references to emotions and to feelings. We “feel” a certain way, we say, meaning that we have certain “emotions” or that we are in a certain “mood.” However, a more careful use of these terms distinguishes between different uses.2 Basically, emotions have cognitive content whereas moods do not. Emotions are about something or someone whereas moods concern a more general attitude or stance. Moods are not affective states which we have as much as affective states which we go through and experience. This gives moods a curiously impersonal and objective quality. We find ourselves in a certain mood, we say. Thus understood, moods are features of the situation in which we are placed rather than of our mental 2 See, for example, Carroll, “Art and Mood”; Ratcliffe, “Heidegger’s Attunement and the Neuropsychology of Emotion”; Ratcliffe, “The Feeling of Being.” 3 / 24 make-up, or perhaps rather, they are features of the interaction between a person and a situation. The mood is a question of whether, and how, we fit into a certain situation; it is a question of how we are attuned to the world.3 When somebody asks us how we feel, we tell them — “I feel rootless,” we say, “worried,” “hopeful,” “pensive” or “over the moon.” Answers such as these provide a report on the mood we are in. In works published in the 1920s, Heidegger discusses two examples of moods at some considerable length — anxiety, Angst, in Being and Time, 1927, and boredom in The Fundamental Concepts of Metaphysics, 1930.4 What he engaged in here is not a psychological investigation but a phenomenological. He is not interested in people, how they react or how they feel, but in what their reactions and their feelings can tell us about the human condition, about the world and our selves. Take boredom. In Fundamental Concepts, Heidegger discusses three examples of boredom, going from the most mundane case to the most profound. He finds himself sitting in a train station, he begins by telling us; he has missed his train and he has nothing to do while waiting for the next train to show up.5 He tries to read a book, but the story does not interest him; he draws circles in the sand outside the station; he looks at his watch; counts the trees along the road; looks at his watch again. He is suffering from Langeweile, “long while,” indicating the way time itself seems to have been lengthened and started to drag. Boredom here is an emotion; he is bored by the situation. Heidegger provides a second example.6 He has been working successfully all day, he tells us, when a friend invites him to a dinner party.
Recommended publications
  • Virulence and Digital Culture
    Virulence and Digital Culture Ryan E. Artrip Dissertation submitted to the faculty of the Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy In ASPECT: Alliance for Social, Political, Ethical, and Cultural Thought François Debrix, Chair Timothy W. Luke Brian Britt Patricia Nickel April 18, 2016 Blacksburg, VA Keywords: Technology; Digitality; Digital Culture; Production; Information; Representation; Referentiality; Virtuality; Viral Media; Virulence; Sexuality; Linguistic Theory; Baudrillard; Hyperreality; Virtual Reality; Implosion; Critical Theory; Political Theory; Cultural Theory; Critical Media Studies; Poststructuralism; Epistemology; Ontology; Metaphysics Copyright 2016 Virulence and Digital Culture Ryan E. Artrip ABSTRACT (academic) This dissertation is a theoretical study of the role of virality/virulence as a predominant technological term in the reproduction of social and cultural information in the digital age. I argue that viral media are not new phenomena, only the name is new. Media have always behaved as viruses; it is only when they become hyper-intensified in digital technology that their virulent function surfaces in language and culture. The project examines processes of self-replication and evolution undergone by various new media phenomena as they relate back to the global profusion of social networks, data centers, and cybernetic practices. Drawing from several contributions in media theory, political and social theory, and critical media studies, I argue that digital media have a hyper-intensifying effect on whatever objects, subjects, or realities they mediate or represent; thus networked societies are virulently swarmed by their own signs and images in information. Through an examination of three primary categories of digital proliferation—language, visuality, and sexuality—I situate digital culture in a framework of virulence, arguing that the digital may be best understood as an effect of cultural hyper-saturation and implosion.
    [Show full text]
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • 52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich
    52 Philosophy in a Dark Time: Martin Heidegger and the Third Reich TIMOTHY O’HAGAN Like Oscar Wilde I can resist everything except temptation. So when I re- ceived Anne Meylan’s tempting invitation to contribute to this Festschrift for Pascal Engel I accepted without hesitation, before I had time to think whether I had anything for the occasion. Finally I suggested to Anne the text of a pub- lic lecture which I delivered in 2008 and which I had shown to Pascal, who responded to it with his customary enthusiasm and barrage of papers of his own on similar topics. But when I re-read it, I realized that it had been written for the general public rather than the professional philosophers who would be likely to read this collection of essays. So what was I to do with it? I’ve decided to present it in two parts. In Part One I reproduce the original lecture, unchanged except for a few minor corrections. In Part Two I engage with a tiny fraction of the vast secondary literature which has built up over the years and which shows no sign of abating. 1. Part One: The 2008 Lecture Curtain-Raiser Let us start with two dates, 1927 and 1933. In 1927 Adolf Hitler’s Mein Kampf (volume II) was published. So too was Martin Heidegger’s magnum opus Being and Time. In 1933 two appointments were made: Hitler as Chancellor of the German Reich and Heidegger as Rector of Freiburg University. In 1927 it was a case of sheer coincidence; in 1933 the two events were closely linked.
    [Show full text]
  • Situating Martin Heidegger's Claim to a “Productive Dialogue” with Marxism
    South African Journal of Philosophy ISSN: 0258-0136 (Print) 2073-4867 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rsph20 Situating Martin Heidegger's claim to a “productive dialogue” with Marxism Dominic Griffiths To cite this article: Dominic Griffiths (2017) Situating Martin Heidegger's claim to a “productive dialogue” with Marxism, South African Journal of Philosophy, 36:4, 483-494, DOI: 10.1080/02580136.2017.1342464 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/02580136.2017.1342464 Published online: 26 Nov 2017. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rsph20 Download by: [169.0.16.25] Date: 26 November 2017, At: 22:35 South African Journal of Philosophy 2017, 36(4): 483–494 Copyright © South African Journal of Philosophy Printed in South Africa — All rights reserved SOUTH AFRICAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY ISSN 0258-0136 EISSN 2073-4867 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02580136.2017.1342464 Situating Martin Heidegger’s claim to a “productive dialogue” with Marxism Dominic Griffiths Department of Philosophy, University of Johannesburg, South Africa Division of Studies in Education, University of the Witwatersrand, South Africa [email protected] This critical review aims to more fully situate the claim Martin Heidegger makes in “Letter on Humanism” that a “productive dialogue” between his work and that of Karl Marx is possible. The prompt for this is Paul Laurence Hemming’s recently published Heidegger and Marx: A Productive Dialogue over the Language of Humanism which omits to fully account for the historical situation which motivated Heidegger’s seemingly positive endorsement of Marxism.
    [Show full text]
  • Trialogue Between Heidegger, Nietzsche, and Nāgārjuna In
    Trialogue between Heidegger, Nietzsche, and Nāgārjuna in Todtnauberg By Daniel Fidel Ferrer You can take these as ipsissima verba of Daniel Fidel Ferrer August 2011 Motto and muse: As the sun arises every morning is both new and old, so it is with pondering the nature of philosophy and thinking. In a cottage in the mountains of the Black Forest in southern Germany this imaginary story unfolds. Not too far from here the famous physicist Albert Einstein (1879-1955) conducted thought experiments which undeniably lead to his theory of relativity. Example of this theory was that time was no longer absolute or uniform. The following philosophical dialogue between three philosophers is a thought experiment like Einstein’s. Martin Heidegger (1889-1976) is the most written about 20th century philosopher. Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) is a critical thinker of the highest order, who proclaimed the death of God and is considered the last western metaphysician. He found Platonism everywhere. The Acharya Nāgārjuna (2-3d century AD) is perhaps the greatest single Indian philosopher; he is considered the greatest Buddhist thinker after the Buddha himself. Nāgārjuna although less famous than the other two philosopher, his audacious and unique eastern way of thinking may provide some fundamental solutions to Heidegger’s and Nietzsche’s stickler dilemmas; and their morass and entanglement in their western philosophical predicaments and knots. Should we say, Nāgārjuna will act as cutting the Gordian Knot? Philosophical conundrums and quandaries are based on the wrong assumptions and presuppositions. Heidegger in the 1925 lectures does an intricacy and stimulating analysis of different types of ambiguity.
    [Show full text]
  • “Only a God Can Save Us” by Jeffrey Van Davis
    You are invited to a showing of the Film “Only A God Can Save Us” by Jeffrey Van Davis. The film concerns relations between Heidegger’s Philosophy and Nazi ideology. The film will be shown at 7pm in the Teleconference Lecture Hall, Alexander Library, College Avenue Campus. The film will be introduced by its creator Jefrey Van Davis and will be followed by a discussion panel consisting of Richard Wolin (CUNY Grad Center), Andreas Kalyvas (The New School), and Jason Stanley (Rutgers) and discussion from the audience. Sponsored by the Rutgers departments of Philosophy, History, German, the Center for Cultural Analysis, and the Dean of Humanitities. For more information contact: Barry Loewer, Chair of Philosophy, [email protected] Brief Description of “Only A God Can Save Us” Martin Heidegger is considered by many to be the most profound thinker of the 20th Century. His magnum opus, Being and Time, was published in 1927 and had the equivalent impact on philosophy that Einstein’s theory of relativity, published in 1906, had on physics; and Freud’s theories of personality, published in 1902 had in the field of psychology. What Heidegger did was to overturn the whole history of philosophical thought that went back 2,500 years to the Greeks and re-examine the question of being and to challenge the whole of Western Metaphysics that prevailed up to his time. He went back to the Pre- socratics , specifically Heraclites, to begin to redirect the path of thinking, to redirect the years of philosophical inquiry in order to put us back “on the right track.” A student of Edmund Husserl, the founder of phenomenology, at the University of Freiburg Germany, Heidegger would break with his great mentor and charge forth into a new direction, building on phenomenology, but going his own quite original way.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth in an Interpretative Age
    ‘To catch a voice from an unknown source’ Truth in an interpretative age Thesis Research Master Theology School of Humanities/School of Catholic Theology Tilburg University Supervisors Prof. Dr. E. P. N. M. Borgman Dr. P. A. Bax Tilburg, 30 January 2012 Eveline van der Ham 552708 Preface During my studies in theology and culture. I decided to devote my bachelor’s thesis to that topic and to investigate what could be said about the meaning of a text objectively. I discerned levels of objectivity and subjectivity in interpretations and learned that what might be regarded as the deepest meaning of a text cannot be pinned down objectively. As a theologian, I had difficulties accepting that, as I wasn’t sure what it meant for our notions of revelation and truth. When I started exploring possible topics for my master’s thesis, I kept coming back to this matter and I decided that there was no other way to finish my academic ‘career’ but addressing this topic once again. And so I went on an adventure, not sure of where to go and what to expect. Writing this thesis has been the most difficult and frustrating exercise I have done during my studies, but I suppose it was done the way it had to be done. It has been a long and uncertain quest and it was only during the final weeks that I began to understand what I was trying to say. The results may cause more questions than answers, but at least I feel they give a direction.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger and the Politics of the University 515
    HEIDEGGER AND THE POLITICS OF THE UNIVERSITY 515 Heidegger and the Politics of the University IAIN THOMSON* An ancient proverb ran, “He who learns but does not think is lost.” Confucius added, “He who thinks but does not learn is in great danger.”1 IF THIS PROVERB’S EXHORTATION TO THINKING sounds paradigmatically Heideggerian, Confucius’s wise rejoinder helps raise that haunting political question: What, if anything, did Heidegger learn from his appalling misadventure with Nazism? Heidegger told Der Spiegel that he reached this infamous political decision “by way of the university.” If, as I believe, Heidegger’s philosophical views on higher edu- cation were largely responsible for his decision to become the first Nazi Rector of Freiburg University in 1933, then one of our Confucian questions becomes: Did Heidegger learn from what he later called his “life’s greatest stupidity” and transform the underlying philosophical views that helped motivate this “political mistake”?2 The only scholars to address this question, Otto Pöggeler and Jacques Derrida, both think so.3 We will examine their interpretations once we are in a better posi- tion to evaluate them. Obviously, we need first to understand Heidegger’s early views on university education before we can decide whether or not he changed these views after the war. This task is complicated, however, by the fact that Heidegger’s early work on the university turns out to be less philosophically ho- 1 Confucius, The Analects of Confucius, Arthur Waley, trans. (New York: Vintage Books, 1989), II.11, 91 (translation emended). 2 Heidegger, “Only A God Can Save Us,” Maria P.
    [Show full text]
  • The Tragic Double Bind of Heidegger's Techne
    The Tragic Double Bind of Heidegger’s Techne DAVID EDWARD TABACHNICK I. Despite the fact that “the tragic” is an important theme in Heidegger, there are few specific discussions of tragedy in his work. While he often refers to tragic poets and playwrights, he nowhere explicitly analyzes the concept of the tragic or provides a theory of tragedy (Gelvin 555). Nonetheless, some scholars have had success locating the larger significance of tragedy in Heidegger (e.g., see Gelvin; Schürmann; McNeill; Schmidt). Schürmann, for one, understands Heidegger’s description of human existence as indicative of a tragic “double bind,” suggesting an irreconcilable denial and embrace of fate. In this paper, I further explore this “double bind” in Heidegger’s discussion of techne, technical knowledge, as it relates to the revealing of technology.1 On the one hand, Heidegger identifies Plato’s articulation of techne as the foundation upon which contemporary technology builds. And, according to Heidegger, technology is “the extreme danger” that “threatens man with the possibility that it could be denied to him to enter into a more original revealing and hence to experience the call of a more primal truth” (“The Question” 333). Yet, on the other hand, technology also holds within it a “saving power” that may push us to recapture the “original Greek essence of science” which, I will argue, is akin to a pre-Platonic techne that may allow us to return to a more authentic way of being, free of the aforementioned danger of technology. “Thus,” Heidegger decides, “the essential unfolding of technology harbors in itself what we least suspect, the possible rise of the saving power” (“The Question” 337).
    [Show full text]
  • “Why the Yale Chaplain Rode” William Sloane Coffin Jr
    The Yale Historical Review January 20, 2010 An Undergraduate Publication Lebkc[??iik[' Editorial Board Editor-in-Chief Christopher Magoon, BK ‘11 Editor-at-Large Layne Johnson, SM ‘12 Development & Communications Editor Josh Tannen, SY ‘11 Outside Editor Joe Geylin, SM ‘11 Senior Essay Editor Josh Silverstein, JE ‘10 Senior Essay Editor Ryan Lowe, MC ‘10 Junior Seminar Editor Jessica Moldovan, SY ‘11 Freshman Seminar Editor The Yale Historical Review is published by Yale Michael Bisceglia, PC ‘12 College students. Yale University is not responsible for Directed Studies Editor its contents. Thomas Meyerson, BK ‘11 Design Editor For information regarding submissions, advertise- Chantal Fernandez, TD ‘12 ments, subscriptions, and contributions, or to provide Web Editor feedback, please contact us at Anthony Hsu, ES ‘12 [email protected] or write to us at Yale Historical Review Advisory Board Yale University PO 207137 David Blight Norma Thompson New Haven, CT 06520 Class of 1954 Professor of Director of American History Undergraduate Studies, or visit our website at www.yalehistoricalreview.org Humanities John Gaddis Robert A. Lovett Professor Charles Edel The Yale Historical Review: An of History Graduate Student in Undergraduate Publication exists to give History undergraduates an opportunity to have their Beverly Gage exceptional work highlighted. It also aims to Associate Professor of Stephen Prince encourage the diffusion of original historical History Graduate Student in History ideas on campus by providing a forum for Glenda Gilmore outstanding undergraduate history papers Peter V. and C. Vann Ranin Kazemi covering any historical topic. Woodward Professor of Graduate Student in History History Donald Kagan, Katherine Mooney Sterling Professor of Classics Graduate Student in and History History Contents Junior Seminar “Why the Yale Chaplain Rode: William Sloane Coffin Jr.
    [Show full text]
  • Only Agamben Can Save Us? Against the Messianic Turn Recently Adopted in Critical Theory
    ARTICLES ONLY AGAMBEN CAN SAVE US? AGAINST THE MESSIANIC TURN RECENTLY ADOPTED IN CRITICAL THEORY Matthew Sharpe Matthew Sharpe is author of Slavoj Žižek: A Little Piece of the Real (Ashgate 2004), coed- itor of Traversing the Fantasy (Ashgate 2005), and the author of numerous pieces on polit- ical theory, psychoanalysis, and critical theory. He currently teaches philosophy and psycho- analytic studies at Deakin University. Correspondence to Matthew Sharpe: [email protected] In this paper, I offer a strong criticism of Giorgio Agamben’s recent political texts. I argue that these texts bring to fruition a larger, contentious trend in the theoretical academy coupling one-dimensional, pessim- istic accounts of modernity with strands of messianism. Since the political prospects of messianism, as Agamben’s analyses show, are very thin indeed, I reflectively question the presuppositions that lead him to this prescriptive juncture. In Part I, recurring to Scholem’s classic analyses of Jewish messianism, I show how Agamben’s messianism borrows more or less directly (in The Open) from kabalistic, antinomian, utopian messianism. Having established this exegetical point, I argue two theses in parts II and III. The first, specifically theoretical thesis is that Agamben is driven into his political messianism by the transcend- ental logic of his analyses of ‘the political’, one which by its nature occludes meaningfully political distinc- tions by instead seeking out their ontological grounds. The second, specifically political thesis is that the widespread embrace of ontological messianism by thinkers in the post-Marxian academy is a symptom of, rather than a cure for, the wider malaise of the political left in the first world.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger and Theology Philosophy and Theology Series
    Heidegger and Theology PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY SERIES Other titles in the Philosophy and Theology series include: Adorno and Theology, Christopher Craig Brittain Badiou and Theology, Frederiek Depoortere Derrida and Theology, Steven Shakespeare Foucault and Theology, Jonathan Tran Girard and Theology, Michael Kirwan Habermas and Theology, Maureen Junker-Kenny Hegel and Theology, Martin J. De Nys Kant and Theology, Pamela Sue Anderson and Jordan Bell Kierkegaard and Theology, Murray Rae Levinas and Theology, Nigel Zimmerman Merleau-Ponty and Theology, Christopher Ben Simpson Nietzsche and Theology, Craig Hovey Simone Weil and Theology, A. Rebecca Rozelle-Stone Vattimo and Theology, Thomas G. Guarino Wittgenstein and Theology, Tim Labron Žižek and Theology, Adam Kotsko Heidegger and Theology Judith Wolfe LONDON • NEW DELHI • NEW YORK • SYDNEY Bloomsbury T&T Clark An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com Bloomsbury is a registered trade mark of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2014 © Judith Wolfe, 2014 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. Judith Wolfe has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author.
    [Show full text]