Proper Names a Cognitive-Philosophical Study

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Proper Names a Cognitive-Philosophical Study Proper Names A Cognitive-Philosophical Study by Eduardo Garc´ıa-Ram´ırez A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in The University of Michigan 2010 Doctoral Committee: Assistant Professor Eric P. Swanson, Chair Professor Marilyn J. Shatz Professor Richmond H. Thomason Associate Professor Andrew M. Egan Wie seltsam, wenn sich die logic mit einer ‘idealen’ Sprache befaßte und nicht mit unserer. — Ludwig Wittgenstein Philosophische Bemerkungen ... A conspicuous difference between old epistemology and the epistemological enterprise in this new psychological setting is that we can now make free use of empirical psychology. — W.V.O. Quine Epistemology Naturalized c Eduardo Garc´ıa-Ram´ırez All Rights Reserved 2010 To my family — in loving memory ii Acknowledgments This dissertation would not have been possible without the help and support of my commit- tee: Eric Swanson, Marilyn Shatz, Andy Egan, and Rich Thomason. My work has been greatly influenced by their guidance. Each one of them has, in her / his own way, helped me become a much better philosopher. Chapters 2, 3, 4, and 5 have benefited from presentations at different venues. Thanks are owed to audiences at the Proper Names Reading Group (PNRG) at UofM, the graduate seminar on Psycholinguistics at UofM, the Philosophy of Language Seminar at IIF’s-UNAM, the second annual AAMPh conference at CUNY, the faculty seminar of the Logic and Phi- losophy of Science Department at UCM-Madrid, the Vortragsreihe at the Ruhr-Universitat¨ Bochum, the workshop on Cognitive Perspectives on Mind and Language at IIF’s-UNAM, and the first annual EFA conference at UBA-Buenos Aires. Special thanks are owed to Lina Jansson, Sam Liao, Ivan Mayerhoffer, Nate Charlow, Maite Ezcurdia, Mario Gomez-´ Torrente, Axel Barcelo,´ Angeles´ Erana,˜ Agust´ın Rayo, Rasmus Winther, Carla Merino, Carlos Montemayor, Raul´ Saucedo, Ricardo Mena, Luis Fernandez,´ Albert Newen, Ulrike Pompe, Christoph Michel, Isidora Stojanovich, and Edouard Machery. Special thanks are also owed to Lenny Clapp and Francois Recanati for their detailed comments on previous versions of chapter 4, and to Marilyn Shatz with whom I coauthored chapter 2. Thanks are owed as well to Dustin Tucker and Molly Mahony for their editorial help. This dissertation also benefited from two term-long visits to MIT-Philosophy and to IIF’s-UNAM. Thanks to Agust´ın Rayo and Guillermo Hurtado for making them possible. My philosophical development has also benefited enormously from the wisdom of my peers. I feel fortunate for having had the chance to work with the class of 2005. Substantial thanks are owed to Alex Plakias, Lina Jansson, Wendy Tng, Sam Liao, Michael Docherty, Neil Mehta, Ian Flora, and David Plunkett. I am also fortunate for being part of a Department with such an excellent group of graduate students. Thanks are owed to all. My research has improved substantially thanks to the amazing work of our librarian. Thanks are owed to Molly Mahony for keeping me up to date with respect to proper names. Thanks are also owed to Linda Shultes, and to all the philosophy staff, for turning the PhD iii into a less daunting, more liveable, task. Not everything has been nice during the past few years. I want to thank the faculty and staff of the Philosophy Department at UofM for their extraordinary support during the horrible times. Thanks are owed as well to Abraham Arceo, Juan Esp´ındola, Jonathan DeVore, Luciana Meli, Bruno Velazquez, Moises´ Vaca, and Marco Rigau for their unyielding support. Finally, I want to thank Catalina for keeping up with a partner-unfriendly academic lifestyle and, most importantly, for keeping me alive. iv Table of Contents Dedication ....................................... ii Acknowledgments ................................... iii List of Tables ...................................... vi List of Figures ..................................... vii Abstract ......................................... viii Chapter 1 Introduction: Why should we care about proper names? ......1 1.1 Reference . .2 1.2 Belief and Intentionality . .3 1.3 Imagination and the use of language . .6 Chapter 2 On Problems with Descriptivism: Psychological Assumptions and Empirical Evidence ................................ 10 2.1 Background . 10 2.1.1 Mill’s view . 11 2.1.2 Frege’s insight . 11 2.2 Varieties of descriptivism . 13 2.2.1 Expanded descriptivism . 13 2.2.2 Cluster descriptivism . 14 2.2.3 Boethian expanded descriptivism . 14 2.2.4 Basic causal descriptivism . 15 2.2.5 Two-dimensional (expanded) descriptivism . 16 2.2.6 Wide scope expanded descriptivism . 16 2.2.7 Metalinguistic descriptivism . 16 2.3 What descriptivism presupposes . 17 2.3.1 Towards an operative account of descriptivism . 17 2.3.2 A caveat . 21 2.4 The evidence . 22 2.4.1 Early lexical development . 22 2.4.2 Cognitive development . 23 v 2.4.3 Memory for proper names . 25 2.5 Preliminary Conclusions . 28 2.6 Objections and replies . 30 2.6.1 Accounting for natural languages . 30 2.6.2 A descriptivist reply . 31 2.6.3 If not definite descriptions, what then? . 33 2.6.4 Why philosophers should care . 34 2.7 Concluding remarks: Where are we now? . 35 2.7.1 Psychology . 36 2.7.2 Philosophy . 37 2.7.3 Conclusions . 38 Chapter 3 The Puzzle of Names ........................... 47 3.1 The puzzles . 48 3.1.1 Informativeness . 48 3.1.2 Substitution failure . 50 3.2 Case studies . 53 3.2.1 Frege . 53 3.2.2 Recanati on belief reports . 56 3.2.3 Plantinga and the Boethian compromise . 57 3.2.4 Stalnaker on two-dimensionalism . 60 3.3 A historical account . 64 3.4 Why is there substitution failure? . 65 3.5 A working hypothesis . 69 Chapter 4 An Integrated Account of Substitution Failure ............ 75 4.1 How much substitution failure is there? . 76 4.2 The evidence . 78 4.2.1 Memory . 78 4.2.2 Semantic assumptions for proper names . 80 4.2.3 The localization of labels . 85 4.3 The psychological side . 86 4.3.1 The account . 86 4.3.2 How to count names . 89 4.4 The linguistic side . 91 4.4.1 Meaning transfers . 92 4.4.2 Deferred interpretation and belief reports . 94 4.5 Integrating the accounts . 98 4.5.1 Solving Frege’s puzzle . 99 4.5.2 Solving Kripke’s puzzle . 101 4.5.3 Non-linguistic believers? . 102 4.6 Explanatory power . 103 4.6.1 Simple sentences . 103 4.6.2 Demonstratives . 105 4.6.3 Anaphoric reports . 107 vi 4.6.4 Mistaken identities . 109 4.6.5 Embedded reports . 109 4.6.6 Anaphoric and de se reports . 110 4.6.7 Germans . 111 Chapter 5 The Cognitive Theory of Empty Names ................ 118 5.1 A theory and the phenomena . 119 5.1.1 Mental content . 121 5.1.2 Fictional discourse . 122 5.1.3 Pretense and imaginings . 125 5.2 The cognitive theory . 126 5.2.1 The decoupler . 127 5.2.2 Belief, pretense, and EDUs . 130 5.2.3 EDUs and empty names . 133 5.2.4 EDUs and propositions . 135 5.3 Problem solving . 139 5.3.1 Homogeneous semantics . 139 5.3.2 Meaningfulness . 140 5.3.3 Fictional discourse . 140 5.3.4 Psychological adequacy . 141 5.3.5 Non-fictional empty names . 141 5.3.6 Errors and hallucinations . 143 5.3.7 Belief reports . 143 5.4 Advantages . 144 5.4.1 Metaphysics . 145 5.4.2 Problematic assertions . 145 5.4.3 Explaining intentional inexistence . 146 5.4.4 Metanormative theory . 147 5.5 Negative existentials . 148 5.5.1 Positive and negative uses . 148 5.5.2 Metalinguistic interpretation . 151 5.5.3 The mechanisms . 152 5.5.4 Problem solving . 154 5.6 Closing remarks . 158 Chapter 6 Conclusions: Lessons from proper names ............... 164 vii List of Tables Table 2.1 Varieties of Description Theories . 13 2.2 Speakers according to Description Theories . 21 2.3 Actual Memory and Descriptivist Demands for Names . 29 5.1 Kinds of Mental States . 138 viii List of Figures Figure 5.1 Primary and other representations . ..
Recommended publications
  • Reference and Definite Descriptions1
    Philosophical Review !"#"$"%&"'(%)'*"#+%+,"'*"-&$+.,+/%- 01,2/$3-45'6"+,2'78'*/%%"99(% 7/1$&"5':2"';2+9/-/.2+&(9'!"<+"=>'?/98'@A>'B/8'C'3D198>'EFGG4>'..8'HIEJCKL ;1M9+-2")'MN5'*1O"'P%+<"$-+,N';$"--'/%'M"2(9#'/#';2+9/-/.2+&(9'!"<+"= 7,(M9"'P!Q5'http://www.jstor.org/stable/2183143 0&&"--")5'KARKIRHKEK'EA5HC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=duke. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Duke University Press and Philosophical Review are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Review. http://www.jstor.org REFERENCE AND DEFINITE DESCRIPTIONS1 I DEFINITE descriptions, I shall argue, have two possible func- tions.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter Three Classifying, Identifying, and the Function of Substance Concepts §3.1 Orientation Substances, As I Have Described
    Chapter Three Classifying, identifying, and the function of substance concepts §3.1 Orientation Substances, as I have described them, are whatever one can learn from given only one or a few encounters, various skills or information that will apply on other encounters. Further, this possibility must be grounded in some kind of natural necessity. The function of a substance concept is to make possible this sort of learning and use of knowledge for a specific substance. For this, the cognizing organism must be able to recognize the specific substance under a variety of different conditions, as many as possible. It needs to do this, first, to grasp that the substance it is learning about over various encounters is one and the same so that knowledge of it can accumulate and, second, so that the accumulated knowledge can be applied. For substance concepts to be employed in the service of theoretical knowing —employed for knowing that rather than knowing how— the substance must be represented in thought in a univocal way, the same substance always represented as being the same. This makes possible a stable, unequivocal and nonredundant inner representational system. The ability to recognize what is objectively the same substance again as the same despite wide variations in the faces it shows to the senses is necessarily fallible. Although you surely have many ways of identifying each member of your immediate family —similarly for water and for cats— there will always be possible conditions under which you would misidentify them, mistaking them for someone or something else. If a concept is genuinely a substance concept, if its extension is really a substance, this extension is not determined by one's fallible dispositions to recognize it.
    [Show full text]
  • Direct Reference 9/26/11
    24.251#5 Yablo Direct Reference 9/26/11 Epistemically necessary = knowable a priori. Metaphysically necessary = true in every possible world. They come apart! 'This animal is a dog' is metaphysically necessary but epistemically contingent. 'Jack the Ripper, if he exists, is a murderer' is epistemically necessary but metaphysically contingent. Kripke's Objections to Russell's Name Claim. ('n' means 'the F'). If 'n' means 'the F', then (*) 'a thing is n iff it is the F' should be (i) metaphysically necessary, (ii) a priori. 1. (*) is not necessary left to right; F is not metaphysically necessary for being n 'It could have happened that Twain was an illiterate tramp.' True. 'It could have happened that the author of such and such books was an illiterate tramp.' False. 2. (*) is not necessary right to left; F is not metaphysically sufficient for being n 'Necessarily Bertrand Russell descended from Lord John Russell.' True. 'Necessarily the most famous 20th Century British philosopher descended from Lord Russell.' False. 3. (*) is not a priori left to right; F is not epistemically necessary for being n Say 'Gödel' means the man who proved that arithmetic is incomplete 'Gödel was a mathematician' should be a priori. And it's not; we can imagine discovering he was an impostor. 4. (*) is not a priori right to left; F is not epistemically sufficient for being n Suppose it turns out that the man known as Gödel in fact stole the proof from Schmidt. Does that mean 'Gödel' really refers to Schmidt? Replies (?). To 1. The description gets wide scope.
    [Show full text]
  • Gottlob Frege Patricia A
    Gottlob Frege Patricia A. Blanchette This is the penultimate version of the essay whose final version appears in the Oxford Handbook of Nineteenth-Century German Philosophy, M. Forster and K. Gjesdal (eds), Oxford University Press 2015, pp 207-227 Abstract Gottlob Frege (1848-1925) made significant contributions to both pure mathematics and philosophy. His most important technical contribution, of both mathematical and philosophical significance, is the introduction of a formal system of quantified logic. His work of a more purely- philosophical kind includes the articulation and persuasive defense of anti-psychologism in mathematics and logic, the rigorous pursuit of the thesis that arithmetic is reducible to logic, and the introduction of the distinction between sense and reference in the philosophy of language. Frege’s work has gone on to influence contemporary work across a broad spectrum, including the philosophy of mathematics and logic, the philosophy of language, and the philosophy of mind. This essay describes the historical development of Frege’s central views, and the connections between those views. Introduction Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege was born on November 8, 1848 in the Hanseatic town of Wismar. He was educated in mathematics at the University of Jena and at the University of Göttingen, from which latter he received his doctorate in 1873. He defended his Habilitation the next year in Jena, and took up a position immediately at the University of Jena. Here he spent his entire academic career, lecturing in mathematics and logic, retiring in 1918. His death came on July 26, 1925 in the nearby town of Bad Kleinen.1 Frege is best known for three significant contributions to philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Externalism Is a View About the Conditions for Our Thoughts and Words to Refer to Things
    Semantic Internalism and Externalism in the Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Language, ed. by Barry C. Smith and Ernest Lepore. Oxford University Press 2006. pp. 323-40. Katalin Farkas Central European University, Budapest 1. Three claims about meaning In a sense, the meaning of our words obviously depends on circumstances outside us. ‘Elm’ in English is used to talk about elms, and though I could decide – perhaps as a kind of code – to use the word ‘elm’ to talk about beeches, my decision would hardly change the English language. The meaning of ‘elm’ depends on conventions of the language speaking community, and these are certainly beyond my control. In this sense, no-one will disagree that meaning is determined by factors outside the individual. At the same time, it seems that it is up to me what I mean by my words; and in fact, the meaning of a word in the language is simply a result of what most of us mean by it. Another way of putting this point is that even if the meaning of an expression is determined by social agreement, grasping the meaning of the word is an individual psychological act. I may grasp the usual public meaning correctly, or I may – willingly or accidentally – mean something different by the word, but it looks that meaning in this sense depends entirely on me. It is also plausible to assume that in some sense, our physical environment contributes to what our words mean. If I am right in assuming that before Europeans arrived to Australia, English had had no word which meant the same as the word ‘kangaroo‘ does nowadays, this is easily explained by the fact that people at that time hadn’t encountered kangaroos.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Linguistics
    Philosophy of Linguistics Brian Rabern Philosophy DSB 4.04c 0131 651 5178 [email protected] Geoff Pullum Linguistics DSB 2.23 0131 650 3603 [email protected] Meetings The class meetings are from 11:00 to 13:00 each Wednesday from 19th September to 28th November in Old Library 2.19, Geography building, Old Infirmary complex (weeks 1–3 and 6–11) and in 01M.469 Teaching Room 12 (Doorway 3), Medical School building. Class meetings are mandatory. Readings Required reading is to be done before the class meets; background reading to be studied as time and specific interests permit. Assessment (i) short paper (1000-1500 words) to be turned in by 5 p.m. on Monday 15th October (topics will be provided); (ii) final essay examination with choice of questions from the whole of the course. Week 1 (19th September; Old Library 2.19): Introduction What linguistics is. Linguistics as a special science. Syntax and semantics as conceived in logic. Charles Morris’s trichotomy of syntax, semantics, and pragmatics. Philosophy of science applied to linguistics. Required reading • Hunter, Geoffrey (1971) Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic (Berkeley: University of California Press), pp. 4–13. Background reading • Stainton, Robert (2014) ‘Philosophy of linguistics’, Oxford Handbooks Online. Online at https://works.bepress.com/robertstainton/126/ Week 2 (26th September; Old Library 2.19): Language and languages The metaphysics of linguistics. The vexed question of whether language should be regarded as psychological, social, or purely abstract. The descriptive linguistics of the American structuralists and the mentalist/cognitive backlash; ‘God’s truth’ (realism) vs.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Reference 1. the Phenomenon Of
    1 Reference 1. The phenomenon of reference In a paper evaluating animal communication systems, Hockett and Altmann (1968) presented a list of what they found to be the distinctive characteristics which, collectively, define what it is to be a human language. Among the characteristics is the phenomenon of "aboutness", that is, in using a human language we talk about things that are external to ourselves. This not only includes things that we find in our immediate environment, but also things that are displaced in time and space. For example, at this moment I can just as easily talk about Tahiti or the planet Pluto, neither of which are in my immediate environment nor ever have been, as I can about this telephone before me or the computer I am using at this moment. Temporal displacement is similar: it would seem I can as easily talk about Abraham Lincoln or Julius Caesar, neither a contemporary of mine, as I can of former president Bill Clinton, or my good friend John, who are contemporaries of mine. This notion of aboutness is, intuitively, lacking in some contrasting instances. For example, it is easy to think that animal communication systems lack this characteristic—that the mating call of the male cardinal may be caused by a certain biological urge, and may serve as a signal that attracts mates, but the call itself is (putatively) not about either of those things. Or, consider an example from human behavior. I hit my thumb with a hammer while attempting to drive in a nail. I say, "Ouch!" In so doing I am saying this because of the pain, and I am communicating to anyone within earshot that I am in pain, but the word ouch itself is not about the pain I feel.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Relativity Hyp
    THE LINGUISTIC RELATIVITY HYPOTHESIS by Michele Nathan A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the College of Social Science in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts Florida Atlantic University Boca Raton, Florida December 1973 THE LINGUISTIC RELATIVITY HYPOTHESIS by Michele Nathan This thesis was prepared under the direction of the candidate's thesis advisor, Dr. John D. Early, Department of Anthropology, and has been approved by the members of his supervisory committee. It was submitted to the faculty of the College of Social Science and was accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts. SUPERVISORY COMMITTEE: &~ rl7 IC?13 (date) 1 ii ABSTRACT Author: Michele Nathan Title: The Linguistic Relativity Hypothesis Institution: Florida Atlantic University Degree: Master of Arts Year: 1973 Although interest in the linguistic relativity hypothesis seems to have waned in recent years, this thesis attempts to assess the available evidence supporting it in order to show that further investigation of the hypothesis might be most profitable. Special attention is paid to the fact that anthropology has largely failed to substantiate any claims that correlations between culture and the semantics of language do exist. This has been due to the impressionistic nature of the studies in this area. The use of statistics and hypothesis testing to provide mor.e rigorous methodology is discussed in the hope that employing such paradigms would enable anthropology to contribute some sound evidence regarding t~~ hypothesis. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page Introduction • 1 CHAPTER I THE.HISTORY OF THE FORMULATION OF THE HYPOTHESIS.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistic Determinism and Mutability: the Sapir-Whorf "Hypothesis" and Intercultural Communication
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 403 761 FL 024 384 AUTHOR van Troyer, Gene TITLE Linguistic Determinism and Mutability: The Sapir-Whorf "Hypothesis" and Intercultural Communication. PUB DATE Dec 94 NOTE 18p. PUB TYPE Reports Evaluative/Feasibility (142) Journal Articles (080) JOURNAL CIT JALT Journal; v16 n2 p163-78 Dec 1994 EDRS PRICE MFO1 /PCO1 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Foreign Countries; *Intercultural Communication; *Language Research; *Linguistic Theory; Research Methodology; Scientific Methodology IDENTIFIERS *Sapir (Edward); Whorf (Benjamin Lee); *Whorfian Hypothesis ABSTRACT The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis, long considered a factor in intercultural communication, is discussed. Empirical studies that have tended to validate the hypothesis are reviewed, and the hypothesis is then considered from the standpoint of empirical and scientific research requirements. It is shown that the hypothesis has never been formally defined for testing, and therefore does not exist as a scientifically testable thesis. As a result, all studies that have attempted to interpret empirical data accorded to the hypothesis are either flawed or invalid because they have tested something other than the hypothesis. It is concluded that the Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis exists only as a notion, and has no meaningful relation to intercultural communication. Includes an abstract in Japanese. Contains 22 references. (Author/MSE) *********************************************************************** Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be made from the original document. *********************************************************************** U.S. DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION Office of Educational Research and Improvement PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATION AND CENTER (ERIC) DISSEMINATE THIS MATERIAL This document has been reproduced as HAS BE N GRANTEDBY ceived from the person or organization originating it. Minor changes have been made to improve reproduction quality.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig.Wittgenstein.-.Philosophical.Investigations.Pdf
    PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS By LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN Translated by G. E. M. ANSCOMBE BASIL BLACKWELL TRANSLATOR'S NOTE Copyright © Basil Blackwell Ltd 1958 MY acknowledgments are due to the following, who either checked First published 1953 Second edition 1958 the translation or allowed me to consult them about German and Reprint of English text alone 1963 Austrian usage or read the translation through and helped me to Third edition of English and German text with index 1967 improve the English: Mr. R. Rhees, Professor G. H. von Wright, Reprint of English text with index 1968, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1978, Mr. P. Geach, Mr. G. Kreisel, Miss L. Labowsky, Mr. D. Paul, Miss I. 1981, 1986 Murdoch. Basil Blackwell Ltd 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purposes of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be NOTE TO SECOND EDITION reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or THE text has been revised for the new edition. A large number of otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. small changes have been made in the English text. The following passages have been significantly altered: Except in the United States of America, this book is sold to the In Part I: §§ 108, 109, 116, 189, 193, 251, 284, 352, 360, 393,418, condition that it shall not, by way of trade or otherwise, be lent, re- 426, 442, 456, 493, 520, 556, 582, 591, 644, 690, 692.
    [Show full text]
  • The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): Mathematician, Logician, and Philosopher
    Louis deRosset { Spring 2019 Russell: The Theory of Descriptions 1. Bertrand Russell (1872-1970): mathematician, logician, and philosopher. He's one of the founders of analytic philosophy. \On Denoting" is a founding document of analytic philosophy. It is a paradigm of philosophical analysis. An analysis of a concept/phenomenon c: a recipe for eliminating c-vocabulary from our theories which still captures all of the facts the c-vocabulary targets. FOR EXAMPLE: \The Name View Analysis of Identity." 2. Russell's target: Denoting Phrases By a \denoting phrase" I mean a phrase such as any one of the following: a man, some man, any man, every man, all men, the present King of England, the present King of France, the centre of mass of the Solar System at the first instant of the twentieth century, the revolution of the earth round the sun, the revolution of the sun round the earth. (479) Includes: • universals: \all F 's" (\each"/\every") • existentials: \some F " (\at least one") • indefinite descriptions: \an F " • definite descriptions: \the F " Later additions: • negative existentials: \no F 's" (480) • Genitives: \my F " (\your"/\their"/\Joe's"/etc.) (484) • Empty Proper Names: \Apollo", \Hamlet", etc. (491) Russell proposes to analyze denoting phrases. 3. Why Analyze Denoting Phrases? Russell's Project: The distinction between acquaintance and knowledge about is the distinction between the things we have presentation of, and the things we only reach by means of denoting phrases. [. ] In perception we have acquaintance with the objects of perception, and in thought we have acquaintance with objects of a more abstract logical character; but we do not necessarily have acquaintance with the objects denoted by phrases composed of words with whose meanings we are ac- quainted.
    [Show full text]
  • Thoughts in Motion
    ! ! "# $ % & #''# #() (*+,(( - . / 0& /& &1 , ' ,2 &##/ # ,# & 3, ,/4 # 56/'# / & , , & , ' & / & ' , # # # & 7 '& & ' 3#/(((6,0 '# & / # 8 # 8 # & '# , ' & # '& ,% & # / # # & # ,9& / '# #' '# , 3 6, 3 & 6 # ,% / # / /& '# # 3 & '4 56'/ #/ ' # # & ' 34 56, # , ' & ,2 : # 3 6 & # '; # , / # ' &' ; 3,,/ <6,2 / ' & ' / / , ! (* 7== ,',= &< > 7 ' 777&?@* 2$-@*A@*B?@A(* 2$-@*A@*B?@A(AA 2-?((C@ % & #/(B@ Thoughts in Motion The Role of Long-Term L1 and Short-Term L2 Experience when Talking and Thinking of Caused Motion Guillermo Montero-Melis Centre for Research on Bilingualism Department of Swedish Language and Multilingualism Stockholm University Doctoral Dissertation 2017 Centre for Research on Bilingualism Department of Swedish Language and Multilingualism Stockholm University Copyright: Guillermo Montero-Melis Printing: Universitetsservice AB, Stockholm 2017 Correspondence: SE 106 91 Stockholm www.biling.su.se ISBN 978-91-7649-807-1 (print) ISBN 978-91-7649-808-8 (electronic) ISSN 1400-5921 A mi abuelo Manuel Melis, por su amor al saber Acknowledgements Two persons have mainly guided my efforts. I am deeply grateful to my main advisors, Manne
    [Show full text]