The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1977 The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic Gerasimos X. Santas University of California, Irvine, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Santas, Gerasimos X., "The Form of the Good in Plato's Republic" (1977). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 85. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/85 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. S. PT.M:.R, i977 G.RA SIXOS S AT AS UAIV.RSITY OF C LIFO AIA, IRVIA. ThJ Frr a r: :hJ Grrd pn Pl a:r ia RJm ubl pc l "Lrrnpng pn:r :hJ rrb r: lpgh: hJ [Pla:r] aJJa nr:hpn g, bu: hJ pa waraJd and JlJva:Jd." 55 JrwJ:: Ar wrp:Jr haa aadJ :rr :hJ crncJm: r: grrdnJ aa lr::pJr clapaa :han Pla:r aanJa :rr :hJ Frra r: :hJ Grrd pn :hJ apddlJ brrna r: :hJ RJmublpc. WJ arJ :rld :ha: wp:hru: nnrwlJdgJ r: :hJ Frra r: :h J Grrd wJ cannr: nnrw :ha: any:hpng JlaJ pa grrd, and :ha: wp:hru: nnrwlJdgJ r: :hpa Frra all r:hJr nnrw­ lJdgJ wruld bJ r: nr bJnJ:p: :r ua i505A5506:). Fur hJr, :hJ Frra r: :hJ ., Grrd pa ":hJ cauaJ" r: :ru:h and nnrw,ldgJ. Fur:hJr yJ:, :hJ rbjJc:a r: nnrw­ lJdgJ rJcJpvJ ":hJpr bJpng and JaaJncJ" :rra :hJ Frra r: :hJ Grrd :hrugh p: pa nr: Ja aJncJ "bu: a:pll :ranacJnda JaaJncJ pn dpgnp:y and aurmaaapng mrwJr.ii i509A:) Aa p: :hpa pn:rpgupng vpJwa wJrJ nr: maradrxpcal Jnrugh, Pla:r haa Srcra:Ja auggJa: :ha: JvJn :hJ :runda:prna r: aa:hJaa:pca arJ pnaJcurJ unlJaa wJ havJ nnrwlJdgJ r: :hJ Grrdy :hJ bJgpnnpnga r: gJraJ:ry and arp:haJ:pc arJ hym0:hJaJa, nr: nnrwn un:pl :hJ arul can "aacJn:" :rra :hJa :r :hJ Frra r: :hJ Grrd and "dJacJn: " bacn :rra p: :r :hJa. i509:55iiC) ThJaJ darn aaypnga arJ nr: pncpdJ ii :al :r Pla:ria mhplrarmhy. On :hJ crn:rary :hJy arJ :hJ cJn:JrmpJcJ r: canrnpcal Pla:rnpaa, Pla:ria J:hpca, Jmpa:Jarlrgy, and aJ:amhyapca r: :hJ apddlJ mJrprd. ThJ Frra r: :hJ Grrd pa gpvJn :hJ mrpvplJgJd mrap:prny p: pa mrprr, J:hpcally, Jmpa:Jarlrgpcally , and rn:rlrgpcally, :r JvJry:hpng JlaJ pn Pla:ria unpvJraJ. Arr pa :hpa vpJw crn­ :pnJd :r :hJ RJmublpc. I bJlpJvJ :ha: an JxcJllJn: caaJ can bJ aadJ ru: :ha: :hJ :JlJrlrgpcal Jxmlana:prn r: :hJ PhaJdr i mm 97599) and :hJ "crJa:prn" r: :hJ mhyapcal unpvJraJ pn :hJ TpaaJua imm. 28535) mrJaummraJ :hpa mrprrp:y r: :hJ Frra r: :hJiGrrd. Why dpd Pla:r aaapgn auch a aumrJaJ mrap:prn :r :hJ Frra r: :hJ Grrd? Wha: crncJm:prn r: grrdnJaa dpd hJ havJ whpch allrwJd hpa :r :hpnn r: :hJ Frra r : : h J G r r d n r : r n l y a a : h J : p n a l c a u a J r : JvJry: h p ng w J d r b u. :a l a r " : h J cauaJ" r : : h J nnrwabplp:ya n d J v J n r : : h J v J r y b J p n g r : h p a :avrrp:J Jn:p:pJa, :hJ F r r a a? A n d w h a : crnnJc:prnd p d h J a J J bJ:wJJn: h J F r r a r : : h J G r r d a n d aa:hJ­ aa:pca? Aa apgh: wJll bJ JxmJc:Jd, a crnapdJrablJ brdy r: lp:Jra:urJ haa bJJn bupl: arrund :hJ rJlJvan: maaaagJa. I: wruld :anJ a lrng brrn :r dpacuaa adJ­ qua:Jly :hJ pn:JrmrJ:a:prna mu: :rrward pn :hpa cJn:ury alrnJ. YJ: pa pa nr hymJrbrlJ :r aay :ha: wJ havJ nr aa:pa:ac:rry rr wpdJly accJm:Jd anawJra :r rur quJa:prna. A grrum r: JarlpJr wrp:Jra, vJry auba:an:pal Pla:rnpc achrlara pndJJd, dpacuaaJd :hJ rJlJvJn: :Jx:a a: lJng:h, bu: un:rr:una:Jly :hJy dpd nr: havJ :hJ bJnJ:p: r: :hJ JxcJllJn: dpacuaaprna r: Pla:ria aJ:amhaypca :ha: havJ :anJn mlacJ pn :hJ laa: quar:Jr cJn:ury.2 A aJcrnd grrum r: vJry rJcJn: wrp:Jra :ha: havJ dpacuaaJd rur :Jx:a, acu:J mhplrarmhJra pndJJd, dr nr: aJJa ., J �- ... -2- to me to have paid close enough attention to Plato's texts, and, probably as a result, their discussions do not illuminate a great deal what Plato says.3 In this paper I propose to re-examine closely what Plato actually says with the hope of making some progress: I think it can be shown that what Plato says about the Form of the Good is coherent and coheres well with what is now known of his metaphysics, epistemology, and ethics. I am heavily indebted to a third group of writers who, so far as I know, have not written directly on our passages but who have thrown a flood of light on Plato's thought and have made distinctions of direct relevance to the privileged position of the Form of the Good.4 I divide Plato's discussion into three rounds, or, as they may well b� called, three waves of paradox, and discuss each in turn. I The First Round: Ethics, Politics, and the Form of the Good Plato's discussion of the Form of the Good occurs in a section of Book VI which is concerned with the education of the rulers (SOOff). We are told that it is not sufficient for the rulers to learn what justice, temper­ ance, courage, and wisdom are, according to the definitions established in Book IV. These definitions do not provide a sufficient and exact understanding of these virtues. There is something greater than these virtues, and there is a "longer way".to understanding these things, a way that culminates in "the greatest study": Gl The greatest study is the study of the Form of the Good, by participation in which just things and all the rest become useful and beneficial. (SOSA) G2 If we do not know the·Form of the Good, then even if without such knowledge we know everything else, it (the knowledge of everything else) would be of no benefit to us, just as no possession would be (of benefit) without possession of the Good. (SOSAB) GJ If we know all things without knowing the Good, (this would be of no benefit because) we would not know (thap anything (is) beautiful and good. (SOSB) Next Plato rejects two hypotheses concerning the nature of the Good: (a) The good is knowledge, and (b) the Good is pleasure. The first hypothesis is rejected on the ground that those who hold it are unable to answer the question "Knowledge of what?" except by saying "Knowledge of the Good", thus ending up with the circular and uninformative definition that the Good is knowledge of the Good. The second hypothesis is rejected on the ground that those who hold it admit that there are bad pleasures, and are thus compelled I� ,. - 3 - to admit that the same things (bad pleasures) are both good and bad (presu­ mably a contradiction). Thus: G4 The Good is not (identical with) knowledge or pleasure. (505BCD) Plato concludes this round by asserting two propositions about good things and the Good and by emphasizing the importance of knowledge of the Good for the rulers: GS Many people prefer what appears to be just and honorable but is not, but no one prefers to pursue or possess what appears good but is not. (505DE)5 G6 The Good every soul .pursues and does everything for its sake divining what it is and yet baffled and not having an adequate apprehension of its nature nor a stable opinion about it as it has about other things, and because of this failing to have any benefit from other things. (505E) G7 Our constitution will not be perfectly ordered unless the 1 rulers know how just and honorable things are good and they will not know this unless they know the Good. (506AB) This round is the least paradoxical of the three and the easiest to understand in the general setting of Plato's theory of Forms and his ethics. The main metaphysical and epistemological assertions that Plato makes here about the Form of the Good are simply instances of his general metaphysics and epistemology. Thus the second part of G1 is simply an instance of a general proposition that Plato holds, namely: Fl It is by virtue of participation in the Form F-ness or the F that anything which is F is F .6 And G3 is an instance of the general epistemological proposition that goes together with the theory of Forms, namely: F2 If we do not know F-ness or the F, we do not know that any­ thing is F.7 Thus G3 and the second part of Gl do not assign to the Form of the Good any privileged position over other Forms.
Recommended publications
  • Bad Is Stronger Than Good
    Review of General Psychology Copyright 2001 by the Educational Publishing Foundation 2001. Vol. 5. No. 4. 323-370 1089-2680/O1/S5.O0 DOI: 10.1037//1089-2680.5.4.323 Bad Is Stronger Than Good Roy F. Baumeister and Ellen Bratslavsky Catrin Finkenauer Case Western Reserve University Free University of Amsterdam Kathleen D. Vohs Case Western Reserve University The greater power of bad events over good ones is found in everyday events, major life events (e.g., trauma), close relationship outcomes, social network patterns, interper- sonal interactions, and learning processes. Bad emotions, bad parents, and bad feedback have more impact than good ones, and bad information is processed more thoroughly than good. The self is more motivated to avoid bad self-definitions than to pursue good ones. Bad impressions and bad stereotypes are quicker to form and more resistant to disconfirmation than good ones. Various explanations such as diagnosticity and sa- lience help explain some findings, but the greater power of bad events is still found when such variables are controlled. Hardly any exceptions (indicating greater power of good) can be found. Taken together, these findings suggest that bad is stronger than good, as a general principle across a broad range of psychological phenomena. Centuries of literary efforts and religious pothesis that bad is stronger than good (see also thought have depicted human life in terms of a Rozin & Royzman, in press). That is, events struggle between good and bad forces. At the that are negatively valenced (e.g., losing metaphysical level, evil gods or devils are the money, being abandoned by friends, and receiv- opponents of the divine forces of creation and ing criticism) will have a greater impact on the harmony.
    [Show full text]
  • Evil in the Personal Experience of St. Augustine
    RUCH FILOZOFICZNY LXXVI 2020 2 Agnieszka Biegalska University of Warmia and Mazury, Olsztyn, Poland ORCID: 0000-0002-5653-9684 e-mail: [email protected] DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/RF.2020.024 Our heart is restless until it rests in you. St. Augustine, Confessions* Evil in the Personal Experience of St. Augustine The most disturbing issue that permeates all of St. Augustine’s work is the question of the existence of evil, experiencing it and inflicting it. Giovanni Papini claims that Augustine, “before he found himself in finding God, […] had to exhaust the experience of evil to the very depths”.1 This remark redirects our thinking about Augustine’s under- standing of evil from the field of theoretical considerations to the realm of his personal experience of evil, where his philosophical and theologi- cal thought seems to be rooted. For many years, Augustine experienced evil and inflicted it himself. In the Confessions we read: “our life was one of being seduced and seducing, being deceived and deceiving, in a vari- ety of desires. Publicly I was a teacher of the arts which they call liberal; privately I professed a false religion – in the former role arrogant, in the latter superstitious, in everything vain”.2 A sense of persistence in false- hood and iniquity, noticed by Augustine quite late, a few years before his death in 430 (if one can consider his Confessions as a testimony to this important moment) and his desire to know the truth about himself, * Saint Augustine, Confessions, transl. with an introduction and notes by Henry Chadwick (USA: Oxford University Press, 1991), 1, i (1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Appeal of a Good Conscience 21Baptism, Which Corresponds To
    The Appeal of a Good Conscience 21Baptism, which corresponds to this, now saves you, not as a removal of dirt from the body but as an appeal to God for a good conscience, through the resurrection of Jesus Christ, 22who has gone into heaven and is at the right hand of God, with angels, authorities, and powers having been subjected to him. 1 Peter 3:21-22. Peter says that the physical act of baptism does not save a person, but like eight souls were saved through water in the ark, baptism saves in the same way. If it is not the act what is it? I believe verse 22 tells us the secret. Jesus is at the right hand of the Father in heaven with angels and authorities and powers in subjection to him obeying what He says. He’s the one who commanded baptism for the remission of sins in Mark 16:15-16. Therefore, baptism is the appeal commanded by Jesus who is now Lord of lords and King of kings. When a person obeys Jesus in his baptism. God responds with salvation for that person’s good conscience in his or her obedience. Ananias said to Saul who was to become Paul, “Why do you wait? Rise and be baptized and wash away your sins, calling on His name” (Acts 22:16). Ananias was speaking of Jesus who commanded that men be baptized as an appeal for salvation. It is calling on Jesus to save us because He said do it and a Christian has become subject to the Lordship of Jesus.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • The Highest Good for Plato Goodness Is an Abstract Concept That Is Very
    The Highest Good for Plato Goodness is an abstract concept that is very difficult to define, and saying what counts as the highest good is perhaps even more so. In Republic, Plato attempts to say something about what makes things good, but his answer is very vague in the end. Still, we can get some clarity on what he would have answered if asked what the highest good is, from what he says in this text. What counts as the highest good for Plato can be said to be knowledge of the Form of the Good, because it is necessary for knowing and using the other Forms well. The nature of the Forms is not clear in Republic; Plato writes about them as if his audience already knows what they are. Still, we can get some sense of what forms are like from the text. In several places he says that when two or more things share the same name, then they share a form. For example, in Book IV Socrates and Glaucon talk about the form of justice: “…are things called by the same name, whether they are bigger or smaller than one another, like or unlike with respect to that to which the name applies? Alike. Then a just man won’t differ at all from a just city in respect to the form of justice; rather he’ll be like the city” (435 a-b). But what is a Form, exactly? We can start to get a sense of what Plato means by a Form by looking back at Euthyphro.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms
    Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms Plato's theory of Forms or theory of Ideas[1] [2] [3] asserts that non-material abstract (but substantial) forms (or ideas), and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[4] When used in this sense, the word form is often capitalized.[5] Plato speaks of these entities only through the characters (primarily Socrates) of his dialogues who sometimes suggest that these Forms are the only true objects of study that can provide us with genuine knowledge; thus even apart from the very controversial status of the theory, Plato's own views are much in doubt.[6] Plato spoke of Forms in formulating a possible solution to the problem of universals. Forms Terminology: the Forms and the forms The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts that concerned Plato—the outward "form" or appearance of something, and "Form" in a new, technical nature, that never ...assumes a form like that of any of the things which enter into her; ... But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses of real existences modelled after their patterns in a wonderful and inexplicable manner.... The objects that are seen, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the allegory of the cave expressed in Republic, the things that are ordinarily perceived in the world are characterized as shadows of the real things, which are not perceived directly. That which the observer understands when he views the world mimics the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things observed.
    [Show full text]
  • Rosalind Hursthouse, on Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999
    Rosalind Hursthouse, On Virtue Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. x, 275. Reviewed by Gilbert Harman, Department of Philosophy, Princeton Univer- sity Virtue ethics is atype of ethicaltheory in which the notion of virtue or good character plays a central role. This splendid new book describes a “program” for the development of a particular (“Aristotelian”) form of virtue ethics. The book is intended to be used as a textbook, but should be read by anyone interested in moral philosophy. Hursthouse has been a major contributor to the development of virtue ethics and the program she describes, while making use of the many contributions of others, is very much her program, with numerous new ideas and insights. The book has three parts. The first dispels common misunderstandings and explains how virtue ethics applies to complex moral issues. The sec- ond discusses moral motivation, especially the motivation involved in doing something because it is right. The third explains how questions about the objectivity of ethics are to be approached within virtue ethics. Structure Hursthouse’s virtue ethics takes as central the conception of a human be- ing who possesses all ethical virtues of character and no vices or defects of character—”human being” rather than “person” because the relevant char- acter traits are “natural” to the species. To a first approximation, virtue ethics says that a right action is an action among those available that a perfectly virtuous human being would charac- teristically do under the circumstances. This is only a first approximation because of complications required in order accurately to describe certain moral dilemmas.
    [Show full text]
  • Violent Evil and the General Aggression Model
    THE SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY OF Anderson, C.A., & Carnagey, N.L. (2004). Violent evil and the general aggression model. Chapter in A. Miller (Ed.) The Social Psychology of Good and Evil (pp. 168-192). New York: Guilford Publications. GOOD AND EVIL Edited by Arthur G. Miller THE GUILFORD PRESS New York London Violent Evil and the General Aggression Model 169 11, 2001 terrorist attacks, the subsequent "war on terrorism" in Afganistan, the escalating conflict between the Israelis and Palestinians, the ethnic/religious massacres in India, and the recent (and continuing) war in CHAPTER 8 Iraq. Of course, human violence is not new. Archeological and historical evidence makes it dear that violence was prevalent among our hunter/ gatherer ancestors 25,000 years. ago, among the Greek, Egyptian, and Roman societies 2,000-3,000 years ago, among most societies in the VIOLENT EVIL AND THE GENERAL last two centuries, and in almost every society today. Although technological advances have made mass violence easier to accomplish, "people" today are not more violence-prone than they were AGGRESSION MODEL thousands of years ago. Nonetheless, the prevalence of violence in contemporary society, the efficiency of modern weapons, and differences in violence rates between societies have collectively inspired a resurgence of interest in understanding such behavior at CRAIG A. ANDERSON individual, group, and societal levels. The hope, of course, is that such understanding will lead to significant reductions in future rates of violence at NICHOLAS L. CARNAGEY each level of analysis. Note: This pdf was created from scanned book pages that were then run As is apparent throughout the chapters in this book on good and evil, the through OCR software.
    [Show full text]
  • Can God's Goodness Save the Divine Command Theory
    CAN GOD’S GOODNESS SAVE THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY FROM EUTHYPHRO? JEREMY KOONS Georgetown University School of Foreign Service in Qatar Abstract. Recent defenders of the divine command theory like Adams and Alston have confronted the Euthyphro dilemma by arguing that although God’s commands make right actions right, God is morally perfect and hence would never issue unjust or immoral commandments. On their view, God’s nature is the standard of moral goodness, and God’s commands are the source of all obligation. I argue that this view of divine goodness fails because it strips God’s nature of any features that would make His goodness intelligible. An adequate solution to the Euthyphro dilemma may require that God be constrained by a standard of goodness that is external to Himself – itself a problematic proposal for many theists. The Euthyphro dilemma is often thought to present a fatal problem for the divine command theory (aka theological voluntarism). Are right acts commanded by God because they are right, or are they right because they are commanded by God? If the former, then there is a standard of right and wrong independent of God’s commands; God’s commands are not relevant in determining the content of morality. This option seems to compromise God’s sovereignty in an important way. But the second horn of the dilemma presents seemingly insurmountable problems, as well. First, if God’s commands make right actions right, and there is no standard of morality independent of God’s commands, then that seems to make morality arbitrary. Thus, murder is not wrong because it harms someone unjustly, but merely because God forbids it; there is (it seems) no good connection between reason and the wrongness of murder.
    [Show full text]
  • The Form of Soul in the Phaedo »
    PRINCE, Brian D., « The Form of Soul in the Phaedo » THE FORM OF SOUL IN THE PHAEDO Brian D. PRINCE The Phaedo’s two most prominent philosophical topics are the theory of Forms and the immortality of souls.1 So the intersection of these should also be of central importance, and in particular, the question whether there is a Form of Soul in which individual souls participate. This question is salient for two reasons: first, souls receive specially focused attention in Plato’s texts, and second, if the fact that a thing is a soul were not to be explained by participation in a Form, this would make souls highly unusual among the non-Form items in Plato’s universe.2 That is, the Form of Soul occupies — or fails to occupy — a special slot in the metaphysics of the Phaedo: either it exists, and therefore souls have the same metaphysical explanation as visible items, or the Form of Soul does not exist, and therefore there is some quite different explanation of why something is a soul. As I shall argue, there is a Form of Soul, and it plays a central role in the Phaedo’s final argument for immortality. If this is correct, this Form will have other consequences for the relations between individual souls and Forms, and between individual souls and visible items. For example, if there is a Form of Soul, it seems clear that individual souls will follow the same pattern as visible items in their participation in eponymous Forms. The Form of Soul would raise other questions, including why it is never mentioned directly by Plato.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata
    Plato’s Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata At Meno 86e2–4 Socrates proposes to Meno that they should consider the question whether virtue is teachable on a hypothesis. Partly because its concrete procedure is illustrated by a baffling geometrical example, there has still been wide disagreement among scholars as to how he actually carries out this hypothetical inquiry into virtue. The basic structure of the argument at 87b2–89a5 appears very simple: Socrates converts the original question whether virtue is teachable to the question whether it is knowledge, and then examines the latter on the basis of his agreement with Meno that virtue is good. Apart however from that agreement being, as it is explicitly called, a ‘hypothesis’, opinion is divided on what other hypothesis Socrates posited. Some think of it as the conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable’ or as ‘knowledge is teachable’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Wolfsdorf 2008, 44–6 and 58–60),1 and others as the bi-conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable, but if not, not’ or as ‘knowledge alone is teachable’ (Grgić 1999, 34–6; Weiss 2001, 131; Zyskind and Sternfeld 1976, 132). 2 But most scholars, in contrast, identify it with the simple proposition ‘virtue is knowledge’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Benson 2003, 107–25; Bluck 1961, 17–19 and 85–91; Bostock 1986, 165–6; Canto-Sperber 1991, 98–102; Cherniss 1947, 140; Hackforth 1955, 140–1; Kahn 1996, 310; Robinson 1953, 116–18; Rose 1970, 3–7; Sayre 1969, 29 n. 40; Scott 2006, 137–40 and 221–4; Sharples 1985, 167).3 It is also suggested that Socrates’ new philosophical tool does not involve any process of positing a hypothesis but only aims to establish the equivalence between teachability and knowledge (Ebrey 2013, 76 and 83–4).
    [Show full text]
  • The Form of the Good in Plato's Timaeus
    THANASSIS GKATZARAS | 71 One of the many philosophical problems The Form of the Good in that we face in the Timaeus is raised by the Plato’s Timaeus claim that the God who created the world (from now on we shall call him ‘Demiurge’)1 is good (Tim. 29d7-30a2). A satisfying explanation of Demiurge’s goodness is far from easy, and dif- ferent approaches have been proposed. How- ever, in this paper I’ll try to show that a clear, sufficient and relatively simple interpretation is possible, if we are based on the hypothesis that Timaeus follows the theory of causation in the Phaedo (including the distinction between ‘safe’ and ‘elegant’ cause) and the concept of the Thanassis Gkatzaras Form of the Good in the Republic.2 University of Ioannina [email protected] To be more specific, I’ll try to show that the Form of the Good of the Republic is also presupposed in the Timaeus and it plays the same role, and we should consider it as a first principle of platonic cosmology, independ- ent from the existence of Demiurge or even the Divine Paradigm (i.e. the model accord- ing to which the Demiurge creates the world). On first impression, this interpretation looks barely possible, since there is no direct refer- ence in the text to this particular Form, with the possible exception of what is said at Tim. 46c7-d1.3 In my opinion, this absence has to do ABSTRACT with specific purposes Timaeus serves, and not with the abandonment of the Good as a cause.
    [Show full text]