Duhemian and Augustinian Science and the Crisis in Non-Empirical Knowledge

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Duhemian and Augustinian Science and the Crisis in Non-Empirical Knowledge Duhemian and Augustinian Science and the Crisis in Non-Empirical Knowledge J. P. Moreland A SALIENT FEATURE of the success of any social, religious, or moral movement is the degree to which its advocates understand, shape, and employ the flow of ideas that forms the intellectual backdrop against which those advocates carry out their work. Setting aside Marxist and other self-refuting materialist forms of social determinism, it seems clear that ideas are among the primary things that impede or facilitate revolutionary movements. Nowhere is this more evident than the pro-life cause. But just exactly what ideas constitute the core components of the milieu in which pro-life advocates live and move and have their being? I am not a sociologist nor the son of one, and I am no expert in the sociology of knowledge. However, I am a philosopher and, as such, I have a take on this question upon which I believe it is important for us to reflect. In 1981 Daniel Callahan, who at that time served as director of The Hastings Center, published an important article entitled “Minimalist Ethics.”i Callahan’s central thesis was that contemporary American culture had come to stress the transcendence of the individual over the community, the importance of tolerating all moral viewpoints, the autonomy of the individual as the highest human good, and the voluntary, informed consent contract as the model of human relationships. These diverse moral positions, argued Callahan, are not part of a list of isolated ideas; rather, they constitute different aspects of a widely accepted moral axiom–minimalist ethics–that can be expressed in a single proposition: One may morally act in any way one chooses so long as one does not do harm to others. Sadly, Callahan provided no analysis of the connection between this 185 1 86 Life and Learning XII axiom and other ideas extant in the culture at that time. Indeed, this lack of analysis blunted the force of Callahan’s own solution to the problem, which essentially amounted to the claim that we need to set aside the assumption of minimalist ethics in favor of richer moral convictions because a minimalist ethic will not sustain us over the long haul. What are those ideas that Callahan failed to weave into his analysis? Among a small handful of worthy candidates, I want to focus on one that I take to be the primary hindrance to persuading people to adopt a richer ethical stance than minimalist ethics and a fortiori to adopting a pro-life perspective. One might think that it is the loss of belief in moral truth to which I refer. This is, indeed, a serious problem and worthy of analysis, but it is not, in my view, the foundational culprit. After all, if pressed, most moral philosophers and theologians would eschew ethical relativism in is various forms. I think the main intellectual factor that is left out of Callahan’s analysis and that hinders the pro-life movement is a loss of belief among cultural elites in particular, and the broader public in general, in the existence of non-empirical, non-scientific knowledge, especially of moral and religious knowledge. Interestingly, Callahan himself seemed to accept the absence of moral knowledge in his article. He makes reference to the fact than when John Stuart Mill first advanced his harm principle in 1859, he could “assume a relatively stable body of moral conviction below the surface.”ii Later, he advises that we bring “all the public and private opinion we can” against a minimalist ethic.iii Note carefully Callahan’s selection of terms: moral conviction and public/private opinion. These are hardly robust cognitive labels. There are several examples in the literature of this ubiquitous denial of ethical knowledge. Here is one, selected almost at random. In a widely used text in ethics, utilitarian Tom L. Beauchamp considers and rejects a pluralistic theory of value because, among other things, it seems to many to be futile and presumptuous to attempt to develop a general theory of value.iv As a replacement, Beauchamp proffers subjective preference utilitarianism, according to which the value of an act lies in its maximization of the satisfaction of desires and wants which express individual preferences. J. P. Moreland 187 He recognizes that, so defined, this theory suffers from some fairly obvious counter-examples, for example, in a possible world where most prefer child molestation, it would justify such an act under certain conditions. So Beauchamp supplements the principle of subject preference such that the justification of an act is spelled out in terms of the maximization of those subjective preferences that it is rational to have. Now just exactly how is “rationality” functioning here? To answer this, let us distinguish prescriptive and descriptive rationality. Prescrip- tive rationality is the ability to have insights into or form justified beliefs with respect to what is intrinsically valuable. This cannot be what Beauchamp means since, if it were, his theory would be circular. Clearly, he means descriptive rationality: the ability to select efficient means to accomplish arbitrarily preferred ends and the formation of only those desires that normal people desire, which in turn would be cashed out statistically or in terms of evolutionary advantage, or in some similar sort of way. My purpose here is not to evaluate Beachamp’s subjective preference theory as a theory of value, though it is clearly deficient on this score. Rather, I want to call attention to the impact on the availabil- ity of moral knowledge that Beachamp’s analysis has. In a way similar to anti-realists in philosophy of science such as Larry Laudan, by defining rationality in the descriptive and instrumental way he does, Beachamp severs the connection between rationality and moral truth and thus implicitly denies the possibility of moral knowledge. The assault on or ignorance of moral knowledge could be illustrated over and over again. Rawls’s decision-makers in the original position are denied access to moral information, Kai Nielsen advances a contructivist form of reflective equilibrium in which moral truth and moral knowledge are simply irrelevant, and J. L. Mackie argues that, given the truth of naturalistic atheism, irreducible moral facts are too queer to quantify over and, thus, Mackie denies moral knowledge.v What is going on here and how can pro-life advocates qua academics change the situation? These are complicated and difficult questions, but in what follows I will try to offer my own insights on them. While far from exhaustive, I trust they 1 88 Life and Learning XII will be helpful to my pro-life colleagues. I shall (1) locate the rejection of moral knowledge against the backdrop of the central world view struggle now dominant on Western university campuses and (2) distinguish Duhemian and Augustinian science and show how the distinction can be useful to restoring confidence in moral knowledge. In this second section, I shall also define and locate the emerging Intelligent Design movement in an overall pro-life strategy. 1. MORAL KNOWLEDGE AND THE THREE-WAY WORLD VIEW STRUGGLE I begin this section with the story of a prominent individual. Harvard philosopher Hilary Putnam is one current intellectual leader who has embodied the broader cultural malaise to which I am referring. Around 1980 Putnam attended a dinner party at which the hostess remarked that science has taught us that the universe was an uncaring, purposeless, valueless machine.vi The statement stuck with Putnam and, in my view, it played a role in the development of his thought, which moved from strict scientific naturalism to a form of creative neo-Kantian constructiv- ism regarding truth, reality, reference, reason, and value.vii To be sure, postmodernism is a variegated movement with many stripes. But if we take postmodernism to include a rejection of (1) a language independent reality, (2) a correspondence theory of truth, (3) the referential use of language, (4) the epistemic objectivity of reason, (5) the self’s ability to exemplify intentionality so as to contact reality directly, unmediated by “conceptual schemes” or their surrogates; then Putnam’s move is postmodern despite its analytic philosophical trimmings. Curiously, truth is a casualty in both scientific naturalism and postmodernism and along with it authority, in this case knowledge, especially the non-empirical sort. The Baconian/Cartesian identification of power over nature as the goal of science is still with us, and the postmodern preoccupation with the power dynamics of language is well known. Putnam’s way out is sad at many levels. At one level it reminds me of the supposed virtues of Buddhist justifications for ecology heralded in the late sixties. The claim was that Buddhism replaces the Judeo-Christ- ian chauvinism of humans vis-à-vis nature and levels the playing field. J. P. Moreland 189 What escaped notice, however, was that the field was no longer worth playing on. Similarly, it is small comfort to those suffering from real evil to be told not to worry about the meaningless of it all because we now know that value, every bit as much as “reality,” is constructed. But what concerns me more is that Putnam could not see a more satisfying third option right in front of him. He should have added a non-naturalist ontology of value and self to scientific realism and pondered what sort of universe has room for them. I think such a move would have led him to theism. In any case, Putnam’s journey is precisely what has happened to the Western intellectual scene. As with Putnam, the emergence of scientific naturalism as the dominant world view in Western culture is the chief reason why there is widespread disregard for non-empirical knowledge.
Recommended publications
  • Atheism? „ Some History „ Culture of Atheism „ Implications of Atheism Part II: Call to Action „ Strategy „ Preparation and Motivation „ Some Pointers
    Sharing Your Faith With An Atheist Edwin Chong August 15, 2004 1 Hebrews 11:6 And without faith it is impossible to please God, because anyone who comes to him must believe that he exists and that he rewards those who earnestly seek him. [NIV] Aug. 15, 2004 2 2 Outline Part I: Setting the Stage What is Atheism? Some History Culture of Atheism Implications of Atheism Part II: Call to Action Strategy Preparation and Motivation Some Pointers Aug. 15, 2004 3 3 Part I Setting the Stage 4 Atheism No God. Strong atheism: Belief that God doesn’t exist. Weak atheism: No belief that God exists. Agnosticism: [T. H. Huxley, 1876] Belief that we do not (empirical) or cannot (strict) know if God exists. Aug. 15, 2004 5 5 Historical Perspective Modernity and The Enlightenment. Postmodernism. Secularization of higher education. Secularization of societies. Aug. 15, 2004 6 6 Modernity René Descartes (1596–1650) Influenced by early developments in science and mathematics. Knowledge based on reason alone. Knowledge of God. The Enlightenment (18th century) Pursuit of knowledge by means of unfettered human reason alone. Aug. 15, 2004 7 7 Seeds of Atheism Although most of the original Enlightenment thinkers were theists, theological knowledge was increasingly viewed with suspicion. Counter-currents to the Enlightenment rationalism (e.g., Romanticism) were no more sympathetic to traditional theism. Aug. 15, 2004 8 8 Postmodernism Postmodernism rejects the all- sufficiency of human reason championed by free thought. A welcome development for Christian believers? Not so: The cure is worse than the disease! Aug. 15, 2004 9 9 More Atheism Postmodernism denies universal standards of logic, rationality, and truth.
    [Show full text]
  • God and the Initial Cosmological Singularity a Reply to Quentin Smith William Lane Craig Used by Permission of Faith and Philosophy 9 (1992): 237-247
    God and the Initial Cosmological Singularity A Reply to Quentin Smith William Lane Craig Used by permission of Faith and Philosophy 9 (1992): 237-247. SUMMARY Q. Smith contends (i) an atheistic interpretation of the Big Bang is better justified than a theistic interpretation because the latter is inconsistent with the standard Big Bang model and (ii) his atheistic interpretation offers a coherent and plausible account of the origin of the universe. But Smith's argument for (i) is multiply flawed, depending on premisses which are false or at least mootable and a key invalid inference. Smith's attempt to demonstrate the plausibility of the atheistic interpretation on the basis of its greater simplicity is based on false parallels between God and the initial cosmological singularity. Smith's effort to prove that the atheist's contention that the universe came into being uncaused out of absolutely nothing is coherent rests upon a confusion between inconceivability and unimaginability and assumes without argument that the causal principle could not be a metaphysically necessary a posteriori truth. In any case, there are good grounds for taking the principle to be a metaphysically necessary, synthetic, a priori truth, in which case the atheistic interpretation is incoherent. GOD AND THE INITIAL COSMOLOGICAL SINGULARITY A REPLY TO QUENTIN SMITH Introduction "The most efficacious way to prove that God exists is on the supposition that the world is eternal," advised Thomas Aquinas. "For, if the world and motion have a first beginning, some cause must clearly be posited to account for this origin of the world and of motion .
    [Show full text]
  • A Normative Yet Coherent Naturalism Steve Petersen
    Vol. 17, No. 1 Spring-Summer 2014 A Normative Yet Coherent Naturalism Steve Petersen Abstract: Naturalism is normally taken to be an ideology, censuring non- naturalistic alternatives. But as many critics have pointed out, this ideological stance looks internally incoherent, since it is not obviously endorsed by naturalistic methods. Naturalists who have addressed this problem universally foreswear the normative component of naturalism by, in effect, giving up science’s exclusive claim to legitimacy. This option makes naturalism into an empty expression of personal preference that can carry no weight in the philosophical or political spheres. In response to this dilemma, I argue that on a popular (but largely unarticulated) construal of naturalism as a commitment to inference to the best explanation, methodological naturalism can be both normative and internally coherent. Philosophical naturalism faces a difficult but often neglected dilemma: take it as a normative position and it risks internal incoherence, since such an ideo- logical stance itself cannot be a deliverance of science. Forgo the evaluative aspect, on the other hand, and naturalism becomes a merely subjective assess- ment, a cry of “yay for science!” that carries no normative weight for those who are not inclined to agree. I first argue that both horns of this dilemma are sharp and that current attempts to negotiate them have failed. I then give a plausible construal of methodological naturalism that is both normative and internally coherent, and so threads this dilemma. Finally, I respond to objections against this for- mulation of naturalism, and consider the dialectical position in which it leaves us.
    [Show full text]
  • Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: in Concept and Critique
    University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2004 Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique James Carlin Watson The University of Montana Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd Let us know how access to this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Watson, James Carlin, "Contemporary philosophical naturalism: In concept and critique" (2004). Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers. 5022. https://scholarworks.umt.edu/etd/5022 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at ScholarWorks at University of Montana. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks at University of Montana. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Maureen and Mike MANSFIELD LIBRARY The University of Montana Permission is granted by the author to reproduce this material in its entirety, provided that this material is used for scholarly purposes and is properly cited in published works and reports. **Please check "Yes” or "No" and provide signature** Yes, I grant permission No, I do not grant permission Author's Signature: Date: Any copying for commercial purposes or financial gain may be undertaken only with the author's explicit consent. 8/98 Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism: In Concept and Critique by James Carlin Watson B. S. Lee University, Cleveland, TN, 2000 presented in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts' The University of Montana December 2004 Approved by: Chairperson Dean, Graduate School l** I'OS Date UMI Number.
    [Show full text]
  • Humanism for Children William Lane Craig
    Humanism for Children William Lane Craig SUMMARY A critical examination of the American Humanist Association's a new advertising campaign and website designed to furnish children with naturalistic or atheistic perspective on science, sexuality, and other topics. HUMANISM FOR CHILDREN The American Humanist Association is currently promoting a new advertising campaign and website that is designed to furnish children with naturalistic or atheistic perspective on science, sexuality, and other topics. The stated goal of the website is laudatory: “to encourage curiosity, critical thinking, and tolerance among young people, as well as to provide accurate information regarding a wide range of issues related to humanism, science, culture, and history.” The problem is that those values have no inherent connection with naturalism, which is a philosophical viewpoint that holds that there is nothing beyond the physical contents of the universe. One does not need to be a naturalist in order to endorse curiosity, critical thinking, tolerance, and the pursuit of accurate information on a wide range of topics. So why taint children’s perspective on these topics with the philosophy of naturalism? Presumably, the AHA would answer that naturalism is true. Therefore there is no problem with presenting children naturalistically tainted answers to life’s most important questions. The irony is that the AHA has been remarkably uncritical in thinking about the truth of naturalism and of humanism in particular. For example, why think that naturalism is true? The
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy Department Handbook
    PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT HANDBOOK Table of Contents ABOUT PHILOSOPHY ............................................................................................ 3 FACULTY ................................................................................................................. 5 Profiles ...................................................................................................................................................... 6 Academic Faith Testimonies ................................................................................................................... 16 Robin Collins ...................................................................................................................................... 16 David Schenk ...................................................................................................................................... 18 Timothy Schoettle ............................................................................................................................... 20 PHILOSOPHY MAJOR REQUIREMENTS ......................................................................................... 22 PHILOSOPHY MINOR REQUIREMENTS .......................................................................................... 22 PHILOSOPHY COURSES FOR QUEST .............................................................................................. 23 PHILOSOPHY COURSE DESCRIPTIONS .......................................................... 24 Upper-Division Philosophy Courses ......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • God and the Initial Cosmological Singularity: a Reply to Quentin Smith
    God and the Initial Cosmological Singularity: A Reply to Quentin Smith Dr. William Lane Craig William Lane Craig is Research Professor of Philosophy at Talbot School of Theology in La Mirada, California. He lives in Atlanta, Georgia, with his wife Jan and their two teenage children Charity and John. At the age of sixteen as a junior in high school, he first heard the message of the Christian gospel and yielded his life to Christ. Dr. Craig pursued his undergraduate studies at Wheaton College (B.A. 1971) and graduate studies at Trinity Evangelical Divinity School (M.A. 1974; M.A. 1975), the University of Birmingham (England) (Ph.D. 1977), and the University of Munich (Germany) (D.Theol. 1984). From 1980-86 he taught Philosophy of Religion at Trinity, during which time he and Jan started their family. In 1987 they moved to Brussels, Belgium, where Dr. Craig pursued research at the University of Louvain until 1994. Q. Smith contends (i) an atheistic interpretation of the Big Bang is better justified than a theistic interpretation because the latter is inconsistent with the standard Big Bang model and (ii) his atheistic interpretation offers a coherent and plausible account of the origin of the universe. But Smith's argument for (i) is multiply flawed, depending on premisses which are false or at least mootable and a key invalid inference. Smith's attempt to demonstrate the plausibility of the atheistic interpretation on the basis of its greater simplicity is based on false parallels between God and the initial cosmological singularity. Smith's effort to prove that the atheist's contention that the universe came into being uncaused out of absolutely nothing is coherent rests upon a confusion between inconceivability and unimaginability and assumes without argument that the causal principle could not be a metaphysically necessary a posteriori truth.
    [Show full text]
  • CURRICULUM VITAE TEDLA G. WOLDEYOHANNES Email
    CURRICULUM VITAE TEDLA G. WOLDEYOHANNES Email: [email protected], [email protected] Phone: (562) 228.3894 Education PhD, Philosophy, Saint Louis University, St. Louis, MO, August 2016. Dissertation: Volition, Doxastic Voluntarism, and Knowledge of God. Committee: John Greco (Director), Eleonore Stump, William Hasker. M.A. Philosophy, Western Michigan University, Kalamazoo, MI, 2008. M.A. Philosophy, Biola University, La Mirada, CA, 2005. B.Th., Theology, Evangelical Theological College, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia, 2000 Specialization and Competences AOS: Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion. AOC: Ethics, Philosophy of Mind, Philosophy of Science, and Metaphysics of Agency. Publications Peer-reviewed Publications 1. “Paul K. Moser and the End of Christian Apologetics as We Know It.” Philosophia Christi (Vol. 17, No. 1 (Summer 2015), pp. 127-149. 2. “How Not to Attack Natural Theology: Rejoinder to Moser”, Philosophia Christi, Vol.17. No. 2, (Winter 2015), pp. 397-409. Books Can We Decide to Believe in God?: In Defense of Doxastic Voluntarism for Religious Beliefs (A manuscript in preparation). Philosophy and Belief in God (A manuscript in preparation). Teaching Experience Harris-Stowe State University: Fall 2018 to present. Introduction to Logic & Introduction to Philosophy. 1 St Louis Community College, Wildwood Campus: Fall 2019 to present. Introduction to Philosophy, World Religions, and Ethics. Chamberlain University, St. Louis: Visiting Professor: Fall 2016 to Spring 2018: Ethics and Critical Reasoning Southwestern Illinois College: Instructor Introduction to Philosophy (Spring 2018) Jefferson College, Hillsboro, MO: Adjunct Faculty Introduction to Philosophy (Spring 2018) Medical Ethics (Spring 2018). Southern Illinois University at Edwardsville: Instructor Reasoning and Argumentation 101 (Fall 2016) St. Louis University: Philosophy of Religion (Upper Division), (Fall 2013, Fall 2014).
    [Show full text]
  • [Draft] Ruth Barcan Marcus and Quantified Modal Logic [Draft]
    [DRAFT] RUTH BARCAN MARCUS AND QUANTIFIED MODAL LOGIC [DRAFT] FREDERIQUE JANSSEN-LAURET Analytic philosophy in the mid-twentieth century didn’t turn out the way it was sup- posed to. Early analytic philosophy had largely spoken with one voice: adhering strongly to descriptivism, the canonical view deriving from Frege and Russell, and equally strongly to extensionalism and anti-modal attitudes. Inspired by the success of extensional, math- ematised systems designed by Russell, Whitehead, Tarski, and early Carnap, Quine in particular argued vociferously that extensional, non-modal, logical form was a hallmark of scientific or mathematical objectivity (Quine 1944: 185). But by the mid-analytic period, the distinctive new movements in logic and the philosophy of language centred on the direct-reference theory of names, the necessity of identity, and the many and varied appli- cations of quantified logics of modality. For all three of these, the first analytic philosopher to defend them in print was a female logician known as Ruth Barcan Marcus. Ruth Barcan published the first quantified modal logic in the Journal of Symbolic Logic (Barcan 1946a, 1946b, 1947). She published subsequent work as Ruth Barcan Marcus, appending her married name (e.g. Barcan Marcus 1961). But this was not by choice. Around the time when Barcan submitted her review of Smullyan to the Journal of Symbolic Logic, she re- called, ‘Church [the editor] informed me testily that he had learned I was married and must heretofore use my “legal” name’ (Barcan Marcus 2010: 82). Out of respect for her preference, I shall call her either ‘Barcan’ or ‘Barcan Marcus’, not ‘Marcus’.
    [Show full text]