An Account of Contributive Justice by Kimberly Wen-Chun Chuang A

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Account of Contributive Justice by Kimberly Wen-Chun Chuang A An Account of Contributive Justice by Kimberly Wen-Chun Chuang A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2018 Doctoral Committee: Professor Elizabeth S. Anderson, Co-chair Professor Peter A. Railton, Co-chair Professor Allan F. Gibbard Professor Daniel E. Little Associate Professor Ishani Maitra Kimberly W. Chuang [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-7364-6457 © Kimberly W. Chuang 2018 i For my mother. And in memory of my father (“well you go up we follow you but you go up we follow you but you go up we are following you but you are gone last” - Frank O’Hara, “For David Schubert”). And for family. ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I've been the fortuitous beneficiary of a lot of luck. And while it was luck that consistently positioned me as a beneficiary, over and over again the benefits in question were entirely deliberate and voluntary expenditures of time, effort, and compassion on the part of others. I've got a lot of people to thank. I'll try to not do it too effusively. What follows will be characterized by some measure of organization and grouping, though perhaps not very much of it. I owe much to the members of my committee, without whom there wouldn’t be much of a dissertation: to Liz, whose incisive feedback helped to mould me in the image of a more competent philosopher. The feedback in question was always turned around with impossible speed. To Peter, to whom I owe the initial germ of this very dissertation. If there’s even a sapling’s worth of work here—to needlessly press the plant analogy—I owe it to Peter. Peter’s abundant generosity with ideas helped me through corners into which I’d written myself more times than I could count. To Dan, who has believed firmly in what projects I’ve brought to him—this firm belief has, in turn, buoyed me through those projects—and who is unfailingly generous with his time and encouragement. Thank you for your incredibly many kindnesses. To Ishani, for consistently perspicuous dissertation feedback. To Allan, for remarkable and kind encouragement over the years. Thanks are owed for departmental support: to Laura Ruetsche, who gently shepherded me through the entirety of my time here. I’m not sure how I had the good fortune to warrant your guidance from my first year onward—guidance that was unfailingly patient, humorous, and sometimes conveyed from exceptionally remote locales—but it’s no exaggeration to say that it iii got me through the degree. To Jude, who has allowed me to pester her for the better part of a decade now: thank you for warm conversation, supportiveness, and your willingness to navigate steep driveways for sake of my occasional lapses in bipedalism (more on that later). To Molly: thank you emphatically, for everything—for less solitary Thanksgivings, for Californian solidarity, for warmth and support of the familial stripe. Thanks are also owed to Annette Bryson, who is an absolute paragon of strength and fortitude. And thanks are owed to Johann Hariman for meaningful conversations. And thanks are owed for institutional support: to Ida Faye Webster and Jean McKee, without whom my (literal) degree completion would’ve been impossible. Thank you both for your compassionate intervention. To Charlotte O’Connor, who helped me figure out more effective ways to work: thank you for your warmth and willingness to be troubled on weekends. To Mika Handelman, for all of her work. I also wouldn’t be anywhere without my earliest mentors at the California State University of Los Angeles, which I attended through the auspices of the Early Entrance Program. David Pitt was the professor with whom I took my very first philosophy course as an undergraduate. He continued to advise and support me through two subsequent undergraduate institutional moves, and I couldn’t have asked for a more affable introduction to philosophy. His course is the only reason why I have any grasp of Lockean substratum at all. Henry Mendell was the professor who first cued me into the realization, at age fourteen or fifteen, that something had to change dramatically about my writing if it was to be up to (philosophical) snuff (“Kimberly, this [style of writing] is self-indulgent.”). He was also responsible, in large part, for my eventual move to Tufts—I owe him much for this. And thanks are owed to my professorial mentors at Tufts University. Stephen L. White for devoting inordinate amounts of time to the facilitation of at least one independent study, the design of an Analytical Marxism course, and an entire graduate school admissions cycle. Thank you for your patient mentoring. I certainly wouldn’t have ended up at Michigan without it. And many thanks are owed to George E. Smith as well, who contributed considerably to the iv sharpening of my philosophical wits. And to Jody Azzouni, with whom long conversations helped to unravel philosophy of language for me. Thanks are also owed to Paul Gowder, who influenced the decision to re-ally myself with political philosophy, even after I’d spent some time thinking of myself as a potential meta- ethicist. Much gratitude is owed to James Molnar, Anthony DiClaudio, and Kabir Soorya—to friends. And to Jack Rohman, who I still think about often. Thanks are owed to climbing friends. I suspect that what may have happened here were the inadvertent effects of climbing itself as a selection factor: talented climbers, belayers and spotters—which all of you unequivocally are—have to be people who appreciate the gravity of being positioned to maim or kill one’s climbing partners. One possible consequence of such selection is that you’ve all been, individually and collectively, an extraordinary community. Thank you, Ken Garber, for always inquiring and extending earnest help and support. Thanks are owed to Hugh Garton for kindly shepherding me to the hospital when I folded my foot into my shin and temporarily found myself peering at the bottom of my own sole. To Billy, Matt, and Emory for warm company and solemn concern that evening as my ankle ballooned and reached the proportions and color of a cantaloupe. To Matthew Schiffert, for contending, patiently and compassionately, with the stir-crazed outcomes of my being unable to walk for nearly two months. To Carson Schultz, Chari Cortez, and Timothy NeCamp for remarkable friendship and climbing company. And my inordinate gratitude for family. For my mother, who traded in her own prospects entirely for the possibility of advancing mine. I wouldn't really be anything—or be anywhere, for that matter—without her. For Damian Wassel, who, for years and years was an absolutely indefatigable source of support, and who is, unequivocally and genuinely, family. Whenever I’m working, I’m always—in the back of my mind—trying to hold myself to emulating the sort of clarity that you evince in your own work. v For Jeffrey Yang, Phoebe Lee, Uncle Vigor Yang, Aunt Dorothy Chuang, and (presently, though soon-to-no-longer-be) wee Claire: Jeff, I remember clearly meeting you and your mother over dinner in Boston, very much aware that you were the extent of extended family that I had Stateside. The same uncertainty applies here too: I’m not sure how, exactly, I struck you then as someone in whom to invest time in the form of careful, and sometimes boisterous, mentoring. The good results of your influence are too many to list, and so I’ll only mention a couple: (a) that earnest, well-motivated ambition isn’t hubris, and (b) that I’m at least a bit more capable than I think myself to be. Phoebe, thank you for compassionately fielding the various kerfuffles into which I’ve gotten myself, and for your indefatigable good cheer. Uncle Vigor and Aunt Dorothy Chuang: thank you, thank you for being so good to me. For Jonathan Bye, who I had the exceptionally good fortune to meet in this past year. Our shared inventory of rites that we’ve endured individually includes: one, a Californian bar exam (to which I cannot claim to have contributed to in any way), and, two, the possible completion of a doctorate. In my case, I’m not sure that I would’ve gotten through these last few months without your help. The outcomes, in any case, would’ve been questionable. I hope sincerely that you do not perish on a mountainous peak. Pursuant to that hope, I hope also that my saying that doesn’t constitute some horrifyingly prescient omen. And to anyone I inadvertently omitted: please forgive me, the final submission deadline for this dissertation is nearing. vi TABLE OF CONTENTS DEDICATION ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS iii LIST OF TABLES x ABSTRACT xi CHAPTER ONE: MAKING CONCEPTUAL SPACE FOR PRINCIPLES OF CONTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE 1 I. Introduction 1 II. Public goods 3 II.i How do the first and second accounts of public goods interact? How can they be reconciled? 17 III. Reconstructing the Murphy and Nagel argument 19 III.i Rejecting efficiency as the sole criterion for determining public provision: the procedural objection 22 III.ii Rejecting efficiency as the sole criterion for determining public expenditure: proposing at least three different types of public good, two of which resist determination by efficiency 24 IV. Civic cultural goods 30 IV.i Arguments against efficient determinations of the financing and delivery of civic cultural goods 32 IV.ii Ways that culture itself, as a good, militates in favor of public financing and delivery 35 V.
Recommended publications
  • Conclusion to the Work THINKING ABOUT and ACTING TO
    Conclusion to the Work THINKING ABOUT AND ACTING TO ADVANCE SOCIAL JUSTICE: A DILEMMA Paul Gomberg Even many who are not philosophers know John Rawls’s name, as his renowned A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1999) gave new life to political philosophy and sparked dis- cussion across the world. Rawls gave theoretical foundations for both the basic liber- ties and equality of opportunity and argued that the only allowable economic inequali- ties should be those that benefit the least advantaged members of society (assuming that inequalities might create incentives that sparked such big gains in production that even those with least had more than anyone would have if there was complete equali- ty). Ronald Dworkin (2000) and others also challenge current social inequalities. Dworkin was vexed that some people are harmed by pure bad luck and argues that egalitarians should be concerned to mitigate such harms; others (see the essays col- lected in Clayton and Williams 2002) debate whether egalitarians should strive for equality or for maximum benefit to those who are worst off. All these theories emphas- ize distributive justice, particularly how the material benefits of social cooperation are spread among people. Robert Nozick’s Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974) challenged these egali- tarian views of distributive justice from the right; he argued that any distribution, no matter how unequal, is just if it came about from actions that were just. Distributive justice also was challenged from the left: in How to Make Opportunity Equal (2007) I proposed that the focus on who gets what is misguided because it sets up contests for limited resources; a just society would make it possible for all to develop complex abilities, to contribute those abilities back to society, and to earn esteem from others for those contributions (I called this contributive justice).
    [Show full text]
  • Applications of Principles of Contributive and Distributive Justice to the Climate Refugee Crisis
    Shoa Moosavi Prof. Bishop Climate Change & Global Justice 19 March 2021 Applications of Principles of Contributive and Distributive Justice to the Climate Refugee Crisis Climate change has and will continue to increase the number of displaced persons around the globe, including both international refugees and internally displaced migrants. Most estimates of the number of climate refugees number in the hundreds of millions (Lustgarten), while more concerning estimates say that up to two billion people could become refugees or migrants by the end of this century (McCarthy). From financial assistance to legal protection, addressing the issue of climate-related displacement introduces many complicated questions about justice and responsibility. The climate refugee problem needs a solution that uses deontological principles to engage parties that have the duty to help as well as consequentialist ethics that closely consider the best outcomes to secure their health, livelihood, and ability to thrive. Managing the logistical considerations of finding safe, dignified living situations for climate refugees and migrants will require extensive planning and funding, so it is critical to decide who will provide what resources to facilitate this process and how those resources will be allocated. The argument for how we ought to approach the crisis of climate refugees will be put forward in three parts. First, this paper will investigate the differences in how refugees, migrants, and climate refugees are defined. The next two sections will discuss the broader ethical implications of who qualifies for receiving what kind of aid and when. This will include an analysis of contributive and distributive justice approaches that address who provides funding and resources and who is eligible to receive those items, respectively.
    [Show full text]
  • Choosing a Tax Rate Structure in the Face of Disagreement
    CHOOSING A TAX RATE STRUCTURE IN THE FACE OF DISAGREEMENT Marjorie E. Komhauser In this Article Professor Kornhauser proposes an Integrity Principle that Congress should use when legislating in the face of inevitable disagreement and conflict among principles. This Principle, loosely based on Ronald Dworkin's principle of integrity, requires Congress to promote coherence from both a practi- cal and theoretical perspective. The practical aspect insists that Congress enact laws that best comport with reality; the theoretical aspect demands that Congress first interpret conflicting principles in a manner that best reconciles them and then enact laws that maximize this harmonization. Professor Kornhauser then applies the Integrity Principle to the question of a tax rate structure, a situation in which fundamental American principles of equality and liberty collide. The practical prong of the Integrity Principle undercuts the assumption that a progressive rate structure is redistributive. This is a crucial assumption because the strongest objections to progressivity are based not on economics but on claims of justice. Thus, to the extent that progressivity is not redistributive, conflicts between equality and liberty disappear. The theoretical prong of the Integrity Principle demonstrates that even if a progressive tax rate were redistributive, progressivity best reconciles two fundamental, but often conflicting, sets of principles: fairness and justice, and equality and liberty. The Integrity Principle, and its concomitant choice of progressivity, will increase the agreement between state action and individual belief and thereby enhance the legitimacy of the state. Since progressivity is a "better fit" with American principles, it boosts legal, moral, and popular support of the state; helps restrain concentrations of wealth and power-an historic threat to the legitimacy in America, and encourages national (or even international)unity.
    [Show full text]
  • Global Contributive Justice
    1 Global contributive justice: An exploration on 2 how to defend a wider provision of meaningful 3 work 4 5 6 7 Cristian Timmermann 8 Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM 9 10 ([email protected]) 11 12 13 (first full draft version – to be presented February 4, 2015) 14 15 16 Abstract: Extreme inequality of opportunity leads to a number of social tensions, 17 inefficiencies and injustices. A raising issue of concern is the effect inequality is 18 having on people’s fair chances in attaining meaningful work, thus limiting 19 opportunities to make a distinguishable positive contribution to society and 20 reducing the chances to live a flourishing life and develop capabilities. Globalization 21 has led to an increasingly uneven distribution of meaningful work in a globalized 22 knowledge economy, the aspects thereof seldom theorized. Aim of the paper is to 23 explore a normative framework to justify a fairer distribution and provision of 24 meaningful work across national boundaries. 25 26 Keywords: labour conditions; capabilities; de-skilling; human flourishing; global 27 justice; knowledge economy; poverty. 28 29 30 31 32 Introduction 33 34 Everyday human well-being can be considerably improved by distributing 35 meaningful work more evenly and by offering additional opportunities to contribute 36 positively to society. The relative recently introduced concept “contributive justice” 37 is a valuable tool to argue for a fairer distribution of meaningful and tedious tasks 38 and to advocate capacity-building. Aim of this paper is to examine what contributive 39 justice demands and how this request can be justified.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Distributive Justice Is Impossible but Contributive Justice Would Work
    Science & Society, Vol. 80, No. 1, January 2016, 31–55 • Why Distributive Justice Is Impossible but Contributive Justice Would Work PAUL GOMBERG* ABSTRACT: Distributive justice, defined as justice in distribution of income and wealth, is impossible. Income and wealth are dis- tributed either unequally or equally. If unequally, then those with less are unjustly subject to social contempt. But equal distribution is impossible because it is inconsistent with bargaining to advance our own good. Hence justice in distribution of income and wealth is impossible. More generally, societies where social relations are mediated by money are necessarily unjust, and Marx was wrong to think a socialist society which retained money would lead to communism. Contributive justice proposes that each flourishes by advancing the flourishing of others. To achieve this goal all labor, both simple and complex, must be shared among all capable of doing it. The good of contributing our abilities to benefit others is then available to all non-competitively. 1. Introduction ISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE, CONCEIVED AS just distribution of income and wealth, is impossible — for reasons to be Dexplained. Social justice concerns how institutions affect people’s lives for better or worse. When the quality of a person’s life depends on access to money — on income and wealth — this * Ancestor drafts of this paper benefitted from criticism from David Schmidtz, David Copp, and Serena Olsaretti. It was the subject of a colloquium at Indiana University/South Bend, where Mahesh Ananth acted as gracious host and made a decisive criticism; a colloquium of the American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, in 2010, where Alastair Norcross was a helpful commentator; and a colloquium at the 2010 meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association, where Frank Lovett made several useful criticisms.
    [Show full text]
  • American Marketing Association Code of Ethics: Instructions for Marketers
    AMERICAN MARKETING ASSOCIATION CODE OF ETHICS: INSTRUCTIONS FOR MARKETERS by Edward J. O’Boyle, PhD Senior Research Associate Mayo Research Institute Lyndon E. Dawson, Jr. Professor of Marketing Louisiana Tech University This paper was published in different form in Journal of Business Ethics Volume 11, Issue 12, December 1992 For more information about this article appearing in the Journal of Business Ethics, go to http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/BF00871958 Questions and comments should be directed to: Edward J. O’Boyle, PhD 1217 Dean Chapel Road, West Monroe, LA 71291 USA [email protected] 1 In marketing no less than in any other specialized area of business, two main obstacles block the pathway to ethically proper conduct: ignorance and conflict. Ignorance raises the question "What is the ethically proper path to follow"? Conflict asks "What price am I willing to pay to follow that path"? These two questions differentiate knowing the moral good from doing it and demonstrate that ethical decision-making resides both in the human intellect and in the human will. This article addresses ignorance by means of the American Marketing Association (AMA) code of ethics which is linked in turn to three principles of economic justice. Conflict is examined in terms of four other ethical principles that are applied to two especially instructive (limiting) cases. Our purpose is to demonstrate that the AMA code of ethics is firmly anchored in certain moral absolutes that can be traced to fundamental ideas of justice in the economic order. MORAL AGENCY AND THE HISTORICAL ROOTS OF ETHICS Concern about ignorance and conflict as obstacles to ethically proper conduct can be traced to the two central historical roots of ethics: the Greco-Roman humanistic tradition and the Judeo-Christian religious tradition.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributive Justice: an Exploration of a Wider Provision of Meaningful Work
    Soc Just Res (2018) 31:85–111 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-017-0293-2 Contributive Justice: An Exploration of a Wider Provision of Meaningful Work Cristian Timmermann1,2 Published online: 9 October 2017 Ó Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2017 Abstract Extreme inequality of opportunity leads to a number of social tensions, inefficiencies and injustices. One issue of increasing concern is the effect inequality is having on people’s fair chances of attaining meaningful work, thus limiting opportunities to make a significant positive contribution to society and reducing the chances of living a flourishing life and developing their potential. On a global scale, we can observe an increasingly uneven provision of meaningful work, raising a series of ethical concerns that need detailed examination. The aim of this article is to explore the potential of a normative framework based upon the idea of contributive justice to defend a fairer provision of meaningful work. Keywords Labour conditions Á Capabilities Á Deskilling Á Human flourishing Á Social justice Á Knowledge economy Á Poverty Introduction Everyday human well-being can be considerably improved by making meaningful work more widely available and by offering additional opportunities to contribute positively to society. The recent revival and expansion of the concept of ‘‘contributive justice’’ is a valuable tool when arguing for a fairer provision of meaningful tasks, doing one’s share of tedious tasks, a fairer competition of ideas and capacity building. The first aim of this article is to explore the demands proposed by this concept. The second aim is to show that the concept of contributive & Cristian Timmermann [email protected] 1 Centro Interdisciplinario de Estudios en Bioe´tica, Universidad de Chile, Diagonal Paraguay 265 - Of.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Distributive Justice Is Impossible but Contributive Justice Would Work
    Science & Society, Vol. 80, No. 1, January 2016, 31–55 View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers • Why Distributive Justice Is Impossible but Contributive Justice Would Work PAUL GOMBERG* ABSTRACT: Distributive justice, defined as justice in distribution of income and wealth, is impossible. Income and wealth are dis- tributed either unequally or equally. If unequally, then those with less are unjustly subject to social contempt. But equal distribution is impossible because it is inconsistent with bargaining to advance our own good. Hence justice in distribution of income and wealth is impossible. More generally, societies where social relations are mediated by money are necessarily unjust, and Marx was wrong to think a socialist society which retained money would lead to communism. Contributive justice proposes that each flourishes by advancing the flourishing of others. To achieve this goal all labor, both simple and complex, must be shared among all capable of doing it. The good of contributing our abilities to benefit others is then available to all non-competitively. 1. Introduction ISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE, CONCEIVED AS just distribution of income and wealth, is impossible — for reasons to be Dexplained. Social justice concerns how institutions affect people’s lives for better or worse. When the quality of a person’s life depends on access to money — on income and wealth — this * Ancestor drafts of this paper benefitted from criticism from David Schmidtz, David Copp, and Serena Olsaretti. It was the subject of a colloquium at Indiana University/South Bend, where Mahesh Ananth acted as gracious host and made a decisive criticism; a colloquium of the American Philosophical Association, Pacific Division, in 2010, where Alastair Norcross was a helpful commentator; and a colloquium at the 2010 meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association, where Frank Lovett made several useful criticisms.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributive Justice: an Exploration of a Wider Provision of Meaningful Work
    Contributive Justice: An exploration of a wider provision of meaningful work Cristian Timmermann [email protected] This is an author accepted version of a manuscript which has been published in: “Social Justice Research” This version is distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 Netherlands License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction, in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Please cite this publication as follows: Timmermann, Cristian. 2018. "Contributive Justice: An Exploration of a Wider Provision of Meaningful Work." Social Justice Research 31 (1):85-111 The final publication is available at Springer via: http://doi.org/10.1007/s11211-017-0293-2 1 Contributive Justice: An exploration of a wider provision of meaningful work Abstract: Extreme inequality of opportunity leads to a number of social tensions, inefficiencies and injustices. One issue of increasing concern is the effect inequality is having on people’s fair chances of attaining meaningful work, thus limiting opportunities to make a significant positive contribution to society and reducing the chances of living a flourishing life and developing their potential. On a global scale we can observe an increasingly uneven provision of meaningful work, raising a series of ethical concerns that need detailed examination. The aim of this article is to explore the potential of a normative framework based upon the idea of contributive justice to defend a fairer provision of meaningful work. Keywords: labour conditions; capabilities; de-skilling; human flourishing; social justice; knowledge economy; poverty. Introduction Everyday human well-being can be considerably improved by making meaningful work more widely available and by offering additional opportunities to contribute positively to society.
    [Show full text]
  • Preservation Is Political: Enacting Contributive Justice and Decolonizing Transnational Archival Collaborations
    Sangwand, T-Kay. 2018. Preservation is Political: Enacting Contributive Justice and Decolonizing Transnational Archival Collaborations. KULA: knowledge creation, dissemination, and preservation studies 2(1): 10. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/kula.36 RESEARCH ARTICLE Preservation is Political: Enacting Contributive Justice and Decolonizing Transnational Archival Collaborations T-Kay Sangwand UCLA Library, US [email protected] This article contributes to critical archival studies discourse and builds upon the theoretical and practical work accomplished under the postcustodial rubric in order to propose an archival framework that is explicitly oriented in the service of justice. Global north/south postcustodial collaborations highlight the ethical and practical obligation of adopting an archival framework that accounts for expanded notions of stewardship and narrative agency. As an archivist based in US academic libraries who works primarily on transnational archival collaborations in the global south, I want to introduce the concept of contributive justice to these postcustodial transnational collaborations because it reframes the role of the partner organization in the global south and acknowledges the agency of all partners (Gomberg 2007). By drawing upon my experiences facilitating transnational archival partnerships between US academic libraries and institutions in Cuba, El Salvador, and Rwanda, I build upon Michelle Caswell’s (2017) suggested actions for dismantling white supremacy within US archives by offering concrete ways archivists can utilize a contributive justice framework to decolonize archival practices (i.e., appraisal, description, access) within transnational partnerships. By offering these examples, we can begin to both imagine and enact a more just and liberatory archival praxis. As Caswell states, ‘through the lens of liberatory archival imaginaries, our work … does not end with the limits of our collection policies, but rather, it is an ongoing process of conceptualizing what we want the future to look like’ (2014a: 51).
    [Show full text]
  • A Loyola University Chicago On-Line Social Justice Reader
    Just Readings A Loyola University Chicago On-Line Social Justice Reader Edited By Michael J. Maher Daniel Hartnett, S.J. University Ministry, Loyola University Chicago This reader is the property of Loyola University Chicago and is protected under its copyright. No portion of this reader may be reproduced in any way without the written permission of Loyola University Chicago. Selections from other publications that are included here are reprinted with permission of their publishers. No portion of these may be reproduced in any way without the permission of their publishers. For permission, please contact the publishers directly rather than Loyola University Chicago. This reader is made possible through a Buehler Grant for Ethics and Social Justice from the Center for Ethics and Social Justice, Loyola University Chicago. 2 Contents I. Introduction (page 4) Michael J. Maher and Daniel Hartnett, S.J. II. Teaching Social Justice (page 6) Introduction by Michael J. Maher a. Social Justice and Jesuit Education (page 7) Jack O’Callaghan, S.J. on the Kolvenbach Santa Clara Address b. A Pedagogy of Justice (page 24) Daniel Hartnett, S.J. c. A Learning Model for Values and Experience (page 28) Michael J. Maher d. Education And Liberation (page 31) John Falcone on Paulo Friere e. Selection from Holland and Henriot, Social Analysis (page 42) f. Using the Internet to Teach Social Justice (page 59) Scott Kelley III. Contemporary Theories of Justice (page 63) Introduction by Daniel Hartnett, S.J. a. The Libertarian Alternative to Social Justice (page 65) Alexei M. Marcoux b. Social Justice from the Liberal Reformist Perspective (page 69) David Ingram on Rawls c.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributive Justice and Meaningful Work
    On-Line Papers – Copyright This online paper may be cited or briefly quoted in line with the usual academic conventions. You may also download them for your own personal use. This paper must not be published elsewhere (e.g. to mailing lists, bulletin boards etc.) without the author's explicit permission. Please note that if you copy this paper you must: include this copyright note not use the paper for commercial purposes or gain in any way you should observe the conventions of academic citation in a version of the following form: Andrew Sayer, Contributive justice and meaningful work, published by the Department of Sociology, Lancaster University, Lancaster, LA1 4YT, UK at http://www.lancs.ac.uk/fass/sociology/papers/sayer-contributive-justice.pdf Publication Details This web page was last revised on 18th February 2009. Contributive justice and meaningful work Andrew Sayer, Department of Sociology, Lancaster University, Lancaster, UK April 2008 To be published in Res Publica Abstract The dominant focus of thinking about economic justice is overwhelmingly distributive, that is, concerned with what people get in terms of resources and opportunities. It views work mainly negatively, as a burden or cost, or else is neutral about it, rather than seeing it as a source of meaning and fulfilment – a good in its own right. However, what we do in life has at least as much, if not more, influence on who we become, as does what we get. Thus we have good reason also to be concerned with what Paul Gomberg has termed contributive justice, that is, justice as regards what people are expected and able to contribute in terms of work.
    [Show full text]