How Beliefs Are Like Colors

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

How Beliefs Are Like Colors University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations 2018 How Beliefs Are Like Colors Devin Sanchez Curry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Curry, Devin Sanchez, "How Beliefs Are Like Colors" (2018). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 2991. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2991 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2991 For more information, please contact [email protected]. How Beliefs Are Like Colors Abstract Teresa believes in God. Maggie’s wife believes that the Earth is flat, and also that Maggie should be home from work by now. Anouk—a cat—believes it is dinner time. This dissertation is about what believing is: it concerns what, exactly, ordinary people are attributing to Teresa, Maggie’s wife, and Anouk when affirming that they are believers. Part I distinguishes the attitudes of belief that people attribute to each other (and other animals) in ordinary life from the cognitive states of belief theoretically posited by (some) cognitive scientists. Part II defends the view that to have an attitude of belief is to live—to be disposed to act, react, think, and feel—in a pattern that an actual belief attributor identifies with taking the world ot be some way. Drawing on scientific, scholarly, and literary sources of evidence, How Beliefs are like Colors provides a framework for research on belief across the humanities and sciences of the mind. Degree Type Dissertation Degree Name Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) Graduate Group Philosophy First Advisor Gary Hatfield Subject Categories Philosophy This dissertation is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/2991 HOW BELIEFS ARE LIKE COLORS Devin Sanchez Curry A DISSERTATION in Philosophy Presented to the Faculties of the University of Pennsylvania in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy 2018 Supervisor of Dissertation ________________________ Gary Hatfield Adam Seybert Professor in Moral and Intellectual Philosophy University of Pennsylvania Graduate Group Chairperson ________________________ Samuel Freeman, Avalon Professor of the Humanities, University of Pennsylvania Dissertation Committee Elisabeth Camp, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Rutgers University Zoltan Domotor, Professor of Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania Michael Weisberg, Professor and Chair of Philosophy, University of Pennsylvania HOW BELIEFS ARE LIKE COLORS COPYRIGHT 2018 Devin Sanchez Curry This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-ShareAlike 3.0 License To view a copy of this license, visit https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/us/ Chapter 3 of this dissertation is derived, in part, from “Beliefs as inner causes: the (lack of) evidence”, published in Philosophical Psychology on March 28th 2018, available at https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2018.1452197 iii For Denise Roca Curry and David Cook Kemper Curry iv Acknowledgements Philosophers struggle to live good lives in worlds they find intelligible. For my mom—who thinks very highly of my writing while professing not to understand a word of it—these Socratic tasks are a breeze. She has no need for hoary metaphysics. My dad, in contrast, suggested I read Descartes’s Meditations for a class project in 9th grade. I thought he was introducing me, his bookish kid, to the bookish thing he did for a living. I now know (fifteen years of formal schooling later) that my siblings and I had been talking philosophy and reading philosophical literature—Simak’s City, Watterson’s Calvin and Hobbes — with our dad throughout our childhood. This dissertation is dedicated to Denise and David Curry, for showing me how to live right. Thanks also to Galen and Tess, for being my constant companions in ethical education. Nearly every good, bad, and weird idea I have had over the last seven years— including those that made it into this dissertation—has been tested in conversation with Amelia Brockman Curry. I am unspeakably lucky to look forward to a future centering on more conversations with Amelia. Thanks to her, and our cats Hobbes, Anouk, and Matisse, for always being there. Gary Hatfield has been an ideal supervisor. He models passionate and careful scholarship, pursuing the questions that fascinate him across disciplinary borders. I cannot thank him enough for investing the same passion and care in me. Professor Hatfield takes his vocational roles admirably seriously. If I have been a good apprentice, it is because he took the time and thought to be a superb mentor. v I owe similarly deep thanks to my committee. I leave every meeting with Liz Camp charged up about talking philosophy, newly equipped with (exquisitely helpful) doubts about my habits of thinking. Despite his ability to classify every tree, Michael Weisberg never lets me miss the forest. I am regularly inspired by how Michael makes good on his boundless curiosity. Zoltan Domotor has an uncanny knack for seeing my arguments more lucidly than they had been represented in my head or on my page. In addition to my official committee members, Lisa Miracchi and Dan Singer provided insightful and encouraging comments on large chunks of my dissertation. Susan Sauvé Meyer taught me to teach undergraduates. Karen Detlefsen has mentored me in ways that far exceed her obligations, challenging me (by advice and example) to go into the world and do the kinds of writing and teaching that make me happy. Before I came to Penn, Paul Davies and Kristin Andrews introduced me to the philosophical and psychological study of other minds. More than any other factor, the comradery of my fellow graduate students made the Penn philosophy department a joyful place to work. I had the privilege of entering as a member of a dream cohort; Marie Barnett, Steve Esser, Daniel Fryer, Kurt Gerry, Nabeel Hamid, Karen Kovaka, Charles Phillips, and Jordan Taylor all became excellent philosophers and better friends. Marie, Nabeel, and Jordan, along with Ben Baker, Justin Bernstein, Louise Daoust, Carlos Santana, and Rob Willison, deserve special thanks for countless discussions about the nature of belief (and related topics). If space permitted, I would thank thirty more beloved grads by name. I already miss living alongside you all. vi ABSTRACT HOW BELIEFS ARE LIKE COLORS Devin Sanchez Curry Gary Hatfield Teresa believes in God. Maggie’s wife believes that the Earth is flat, and also that Maggie should be home from work by now. Anouk—a cat—believes it is dinner time. This dissertation is about what believing is: it concerns what, exactly, ordinary people are attributing to Teresa, Maggie’s wife, and Anouk when affirming that they are believers. Part I distinguishes the attitudes of belief that people attribute to each other (and other animals) in ordinary life from the cognitive states of belief theoretically posited by (some) cognitive scientists. Part II defends the view that to have an attitude of belief is to live—to be disposed to act, react, think, and feel—in a pattern that an actual belief attributor identifies with taking the world to be some way. Drawing on scientific, scholarly, and literary sources of evidence, How Beliefs are like Colors provides a framework for research on belief across the humanities and sciences of the mind. vii How Beliefs are like Colors Table of Contents Acknowledgements . iv Abstract . vi Table of Contents . vii List of Figures . xi Preface . xii–xx Part I: Belief as Attitude, Belief as Cog . 1–222 Chapter 1: A Rylean ancestry . 2–59 1. Introduction . 2 2. Dispositionalisms . 4 2.1. Ryle . 4 2.2. Baker . 11 2.3. Schwitzgebel . 17 3. Interpretivisms . 20 3.1. Quine . 20 3.2. Dennett . 25 3.3. Davidson . 36 3.4. Mölder . 45 4. Ryleanisms . 49 Chapter 2: Varieties of (theory of) belief . 60–109 1. Introduction . 60 2. Thirteen distinctions between varieties of belief . 67 2.1. First distinction: implicit belief vs. explicit belief . 68 2.2. Second distinction: binary belief vs. degrees of belief . 70 2.3. Third distinction: system 1 belief vs. system 2 belief . 72 2.4. Fourth distinction: dispositional belief vs. dispositions to believe . 73 2.5. Fifth distinction: dispositional belief vs. occurrent belief . 75 2.6. Sixth distinction: belief vs. assent . 77 2.7. Seventh distinction: computational belief vs. algorithmic belief . 79 2.8. Eighth distinction: personal belief vs. subpersonal belief . 82 2.9. Ninth distinction: normative belief vs. natural belief . 84 2.10. Tenth distinction: first-order belief vs. higher-order belief . 87 2.11. Eleventh distinction: folk psychological belief vs. psychological belief . 89 2.12. Twelfth distinction: manifest image belief vs. scientific image belief . 95 2.13. Thirteenth distinction: attitude of belief vs. cognitive state of belief. 99 3. Ryleans and representationalists as bedfellows . 100 viii 4. Fifteen theoretical alternatives concerning the metaphysics of belief . 103 5. The argument to come . 108 Chapter 3: Beliefs as inner causes? . 110–162 1. Introduction . 110 2. Unpacking Davidson’s dogma . 113 2.1. ...beliefs as inner causes that produce behavior . 113 2.2. The folk construe... 115 2.3. Davidson vs. Davidson’s dogma . 117 3. The folk craft of belief attribution . 120 3.1. Cognitive scientific theories of belief attribution . 121 3.2. A Rylean model theory of belief attribution . 123 4. The (lack of) evidence from mindreading research . 129 4.1. The empirical literature on lay belief attribution . 129 4.2. A Rylean interpretation of the evidence about lay belief attribution . 134 4.3. Mindreading researchers assume Davidson’s dogma . 136 5. The (lack of) evidence from attribution theory . 140 5.1. The empirical literature on lay behavior explanation . 140 5.2. A Rylean interpretation of the evidence about lay behavior explanation . 146 5.3. Attribution theorists assume Davidson’s dogma .
Recommended publications
  • Haecceitism, Chance
    HAECCEITISM, CHANCE, AND COUNTERFACTUALS Boris Kment Abstract. Anti-haecceitists believe that all facts about specific individuals—such as the fact that Fred exists, or that Katie is tall—globally supervene on purely qualitative facts. Haecceitists deny that. The issue is not only of interest in itself, but receives additional importance from its intimate connection to the question of whether all fundamental facts are qualitative or whether they include facts about which specific individuals there are and how qualitative properties and relations are distributed over them. Those who think that all fundamental facts are qualitative are arguably committed to anti-haecceitism. The goal of this paper is to point out some problems for anti-haecceitism (and therefore for the thesis that all fundamental facts are qualitative). The article focuses on two common assumptions about possible worlds: (i) Sets of possible worlds are the bearers of objective physical chance. (ii) Counterfactual conditionals can be defined by appeal to a relation of closeness between possible worlds. The essay tries to show that absurd consequences ensue if either of these assumptions is combined with anti-haecceitism. Then it considers a natural response by the anti-haecceitist, which is to deny that worlds play the role described in (i) and (ii). Instead, the reply continues, we can introduce a new set of entities that are defined in terms of worlds and that behave the way worlds do on the haecceitist position. That allows the anti-haecceitist to formulate anti-haecceitist friendly versions of (i) and (ii) by replacing the appeal to possible worlds with reference to the newly introduced entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal) Libraries at University of Nebraska-Lincoln July 2005 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Hamilton College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac Part of the Library and Information Science Commons Herold, Ken R., "Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information" (2005). Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal). 27. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac/27 Library Philosophy and Practice Vol. 3, No. 2 (Spring 2001) (www.uidaho.edu/~mbolin/lppv3n2.htm) ISSN 1522-0222 Librarianship and the Philosophy of Information Ken R. Herold Systems Manager Burke Library Hamilton College Clinton, NY 13323 “My purpose is to tell of bodies which have been transformed into shapes of a different kind.” Ovid, Metamorphoses Part I. Library Philosophy Provocation Information seems to be ubiquitous, diaphanous, a-categorical, discrete, a- dimensional, and knowing. · Ubiquitous. Information is ever-present and pervasive in our technology and beyond in our thinking about the world, appearing to be a generic ‘thing’ arising from all of our contacts with each other and our environment, whether thought of in terms of communication or cognition. For librarians information is a universal concept, at its greatest extent total in content and comprehensive in scope, even though we may not agree that all information is library information. · Diaphanous. Due to its virtuality, the manner in which information has the capacity to make an effect, information is freedom. In many aspects it exhibits a transparent quality, a window-like clarity as between source and patron in an ideal interface or a perfect exchange without bias.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind and Language Seminar: Theories of Content
    Mind and Language Seminar: Theories of Content Ned Block and David Chalmers Meetings • Main meeting: Tuesdays 4-7pm over Zoom [4-6pm in weeks without a visitor] • Student meeting: Mondays 5-6pm hybrid • Starting Feb 22 [only weeks with a visitor] • Enrolled students and NYU philosophy graduate students only. • Feb 2: Background: Theories of Content • Feb 9: Background: Causal/Teleological Theories • Feb 16: Background: Interpretivism • Feb 23: Nick Shea • March 2: Robbie Williams • March 9: Frances Egan • March 16: Adam Pautz • March 23: Veronica Gómez Sánchez • March 30: Background: Phenomenal Intentionality • April 6: Imogen Dickie • April 13: Angela Mendelovici • April 20: Background: Conceptual-Role Semantics • April 27: Christopher Peacocke • May 4: David Chalmers Assessment • Draft paper due April 19 • Term paper due May 17 Attendance Policy • Monday meetings: Enrolled students and NYU philosophy graduate students only. • Tuesday meetings: NYU and NYC Consortium students and faculty only • Very limited exceptions • Email us to sign up on email list if you haven’t already. Introductions Short History of the 20th Century • 1900-1970: Reduce philosophical questions to issues about language and meaning. • 1970s: Theories of meaning (philosophy of language as first philosophy) • 1980s: Theories of mental content (philosophy of mind as first philosophy). • 1990s: Brick wall. Theories of Content • What is content? • What is a theory of content? Content • Content (in the broadest sense?) is intentionality or aboutness • Something has content when it is about something. Contents • Content = truth-conditions • Content = satisfaction-conditions • Content = propositions • Content = objects of intentional states • Content = … What Has Content? • What sort of thing has content? What Has Content? • What sort of thing has content? • language (esp.
    [Show full text]
  • The Puzzle of Conscious Experience (Chalmers)
    The Puzzle of Conscious Experience David J. Chalmers * From David Chalmers, "The Puzzle of Conscious Experience," Scientific American, 273 (1995), pp. 80-6. Reprinted by permission of the author. Conscious experience is at once the most familiar thing in the world and the most mysterious. There is nothing we know about more directly than consciousness, but it is extraordinarily hard to reconcile it with everything else we know. Why does it exist? What does it do? How could it possibly arise from neural processes in the brain? These questions are among the most intriguing in all of science. From an objective viewpoint, the brain is relatively comprehensible. When you look at this page, there is a whir of processing: photons strike your retina, electrical signals are passed up your optic nerve and between different areas of your brain, and eventually you might respond with a smile, a perplexed frown or a remark. But there is also a subjective aspect. When you look at the page, you are conscious of it, directly experiencing the images and words as part of your private, mental life. You have vivid impressions of colored flowers and vibrant sky. At the same time, you may be feeling some emotions and forming some thoughts. Together such experiences make up consciousness: the subjective, inner life of the mind. For many years consciousness was shunned by researchers studying the brain and the mind. The prevailing view was that science, which depends on objectivity, could not accommodate something as subjective as consciousness. The behaviorist movement in psychology, dominant earlier in this century, concentrated on external behavior and disallowed any talk of internal mental processes.
    [Show full text]
  • The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense As Well As Critique
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- The ('('Orthodox" View of Theories: Remarks in Defense as well as Critique The purpose of the following remarks is to present in outline some of the more important features of scientific theories. I shall discuss the "standard" or "orthodox" view, mainly in order to set up a target for criticisms, some of which I shall briefly sketch by way of anticipation. The standard account of the structure of scientific theories was given quite explicitly by Norman R. Campbell [7], as well as independently in a little-known article by R. Carnap [12]. A large part of the voluminous literature in the philosophy of science of the logical empiricists and re­ lated thinkers contains, though with a great many variations, develop­ ments, modifications, and terminological diversities, essentially similar analyses of the logical structure and the empirical foundations of the theories of physics, biology, psychology, and some of the social sciences. Anticipating to some extent Campbell and Carnap, Moritz Schlick, in his epoch-making AIIgemeine Erkenntnisiehre [38], championed the doc­ trine of "implicit definition." In this he was influenced by David Hil­ bert's axiomatization of geometry, as well as by Henri Poincare's and Albert Einstein's conceptions of theoretical physics and the role of ge­ ometry in physics. These matters were then developed more fully and precisely in the work of H. Reichenbach, R. Carnap, C. G. Hempel, R. B. Braithwaite, E. Nagel, and many other logicians and methodolo­ gists of science. In order to understand the aim of this important approach in the philosophy of science it is essential to distinguish it from historical, so­ ciological, or psychological studies of scientific theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy Ofscience Oflogical Empiricism
    -----HERBERT FEIGL----- Some Major Issues and Developments in the Philosophy ofScience ofLogical Empiricism AsouT twenty-five years ago a small group of philosophically minded scientists and scientifically trained philosophers in Vienna formulated their declaration of independence from traditional philosophy. The pamphlet Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis (1929) contained the first succinct statement of the outlook which soon after became known as "logical positivism." In the first flush of enthusiasm we Viennese felt we had attained a philosophy to end all philosophies. Schlick spoke of a "Wende der Philosophie" (a decisive turning point of philosophy). Neurath and Frank declared "school philosophy" as obsolete and even suggested that our outlook drop the word "philoso­ phy" altogether, and replace it by "Einheitswissenschaft" or by "scien· tific empiricism." The notable impact of Alfred Ayer's first book in England, and my own efforts ~oward a propagation of Logical Positiv­ ism in the United States during the early thirties, and then the immi· gration of Carnap, Frank, von Mises, Reichenbach, Hempel and Berg­ mann created a powerful movement, but it elicited also sharp opposition nncl criticism. Through the discussions within the movement and its own production and progressive work, as well as in response to the NO'l'F.: This essay is a revised and considerably expanded .version of a lecture given in plenary session at the International Congress for Philosophy of Science, Zurich, /\ngust 25, 1954. It was first- published in Proceedi11gs of the Secono International Congress of the International Union for tl1e Philosophy ot Science (Neuchatel, Switzerland, 19 55). In the cordial letter of invitation I received from Professor Ferdinand Gonseth, president of the Congress, he asked me to discuss "I'empirisme logi<\ue,-ce qu'il fut, et ce qu'il est clevenu." Much as I appreciated the honor of t 1is ambitious assignment, I realized of course that the limitations of time would permit me to deal onJy with some selected topics within this larger frame.
    [Show full text]
  • Stephen Lumsden B1 15.1.18
    Stephen Lumsden, essay for Units 1-3, Program B: Philosophy Of Mind (Essay for Question 5. What is the philosophical significance of the idea of disembodiment and/or the idea of a ‘zombie’?) What is the philosophical significance of the idea of the idea of a ‘zombie In this essay I will briefly summarise the origin of the idea of philosophical zombies and explain what they are. Arguments for their relevance in philosophical enquiry will be then made in order to gauge whether they are a useful tool to use. The idea of a philosophical zombie is a fully functioning person who exists without any inner life or consciousness. This was first put forward by David Chalmers a form of thought experiment and goes as follows: P1: I can consistently conceive of a beings that are physically identical with us, yet have no conscious experience. P2: Conceivability implies possibility C: Therefore we are not purely physical beings In accepting the conceivability of the argument this implies possibility and therefore zombies are possible. In turn the possibility of the zombies will counter the physicalist view that consciousness can be solely defined in functional terms. In turn this can be seen as a victory for supporters of Cartesian Dualism (the idea that the mind is a separate immaterial entity which exists independently of the physical body, as outlined by Descartes in his Meditations on First Philosophy). This argument raises questions in relation to two areas in the philosophy of mind, namely that of Dualism vs physicalism and the problem of other minds.
    [Show full text]
  • An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 8-2018 Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action Jiajun Hu University of Tennessee, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Recommended Citation Hu, Jiajun, "Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2018. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/5008 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Jiajun Hu entitled "Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Philosophy. David W. Palmer, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: Richard E. Aquila, Eldon F. Coffman Jr., Bruce J. MacLennan Accepted for the Council: Dixie L. Thompson Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) Actions Are Not Events: An Ontological Objection to the Causal Theory of Action A Dissertation Presented for the Doctor of Philosophy Degree The University of Tennessee, Knoxville Jiajun Hu August 2018 Copyright © 2018 by Jiajun Hu.
    [Show full text]
  • Goldman and Siegel on the Epistemic Aims of Education
    Goldman and Siegel on the epistemic aims of education Alessia Marabini & Luca Moretti [email protected] [email protected] First Draft (April 25, 2018) ABSTRACT Philosophers have claimed that education aims at fostering disparate epistemic goals––for instance: knowledge, true belief, understanding, epistemic character, critical thinking. In this paper we focus on an important segment of the debate involving conversation between Alvin Goldman and Harvey Siegel. Goldman claims that education is essentially aimed at producing true beliefs. Siegel contends that education is essentially aimed at fostering both true beliefs and, independently, rational beliefs. We summarize and criticize the arguments from both sides. We find Siegel’s position intuitively more plausible than Goldman’s, but we also find Siege’s defence of it wanting. We suggest a novel argumentative strategy on Siegel’s behalf that goes from general epistemology to epistemology of education. (shrink) KEYWORDS: epistemic aims of education, epistemic aims, epistemic rationality, critical thinking, testimony, deontological justification, Alvin Goldman, Harvey Siegel 1. What we do in the paper The debate on the epistemic aims or goals of education is very hot and on-going. Philosophers have claimed that education aims at fostering disparate epistemic goals––for instance: knowledge, true belief, understanding, epistemic character, critical thinking (for an introduction see Carter and Kotzee 2015: §6). In this paper we focus on an important segment of the debate involving conversation between Alvin Goldman and Harvey Siegel. Goldman claims that education is essentially aimed at producing true beliefs. Siegel contends that education is essentially aimed at fostering both true beliefs and, independently, rational beliefs.
    [Show full text]
  • Russellian Panpsychism: Do We Need It and Is It Enough?
    Russellian Panpsychism: Do We Need It and Is It Enough? By Damian Aleksiev Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Philosophy Supervisor: Philip Goff CEU eTD Collection May 2016 Abstract The main aim of this thesis is to clarify the ontological status of phenomenal experience. In order to do this, I first examine how pure physicalism explains phenomenality. Pure physicalism relies on the structural and causal vocabulary of physics, and is compatible with the causal closure of the physical. Nonetheless, I argue that pure physicalism is false since it cannot account for our intuitive understating of phenomenal experience as something beyond-structural. I supplement these intuitions, first with the knowledge and conceivability arguments, and second with my own argument for the transparency of phenomenal concepts called the argument from solipsism. Then, I investigate Russellian panpsychism as a promising alternative to pure physicalism that attempts to solve its problems without any drawbacks. Russellian panpsychism places phenomenal experience at the fundamental ontological level, and at the same time remains compatible with the causal closure of the physical. Finally, I argue against Russellian panpsychism based on the combination problem, as well as my own: reverse conceivability argument, and combination problem for value. The conclusion of this enquiry is that neither pure physicalism nor Russellian panpsychism can provide a satisfactory account of phenomenal experience. CEU eTD Collection I Acknowledgments I would like to thank my supervisor Philip Goff for his continual support and willingness to discuss my ideas during the entire academic year.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979). Henceforth 'RTH'. the Position Th
    [The Journal of Philosophical Research XVII (1992): 313-345] Brains in a Vat, Subjectivity, and the Causal Theory of Reference Kirk Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL 32611-8545 1. Introduction In the first chapter of Reason, Truth and History,1 Putnam argued that it is not epistemically possible that we are brains in a vat (of a certain sort). If his argument is correct, and can be extended in certain ways, then it seems that we can lay to rest the traditional skeptical worry that most or all of our beliefs about the external world are false. Putnam’s argument has two parts. The first is an argument for a theory of reference2 according to which we cannot refer to an object or a type of object unless we have had a certain sort of causal interaction with it. The second part argues from this theory to the conclusion that we can know that we are not brains in a vat. In this paper I will argue that Putnam’s argument to show that we cannot be brains in a vat is unsuccessful. However, the flaw is not in the argument from the theory of reference to the conclusion 1 Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth and History, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1979). Henceforth ‘RTH’. The position that Putnam advances in this first chapter is one that in later chapters of RTH he abandons in favor of the position that he calls ‘internal realism’. He represents the arguments he gives in chapter 1 as a problem posed for the ‘external realist’, who assumes the possibility of a God’s eye point of view.
    [Show full text]
  • Ryle and the Para-Mechanical
    BRYAN BENHAM Ryle and the Para-mechanical WINNER OF mE 1999 LARRY TAYLOR MEMORIAL AWARD The thesis of this paper is the unconventional claim that Gilbert Ryle is not a logical behaviorist. The popular account ofRyle clearly places his work in The Concept ofMind (1949) in the camp oflogical behaviorist.! The object of this paper, however, will be to illustrate how the conventional interpretation of Ryle is misleading. My argument is not an exhaustive account of Ryle, but serves as a starting point for understanding Ryle outside of the behaviorist label that is usually attached to his work. The argument is straightforward. First, it is apparent on any reasonable construal that logical behaviorism is a reductionist project about the mind. The basic claim of logical behaviorism is that statements containing mental vocabulary can be analyzed into statements containing only the vocabulary of physical behavior. Second, any reasonable account ofRyle will show that he is not a reductionist about the mental, in fact he was adamantly anti-reductionist about the mind. Once these two claims are established it follows quite readily that Ryle was not a logical behaviorist. The first premise is uncontroversial. Anyone familiar with logical behaviorism understands that its aim is to show that mental terminology doesn't refer to unobserved phenomena, supposedly in the head of the person described, but rather to the observed physical behaviors or dispositions to behave (Hempel 1999). In fact, in its strict formulation, logical behaviorism claims that mental terminology signifies only these observed behaviors or dispositions to behave. Thus, I will take it as a reasonably established claim that logical behaviorism is reductionist about the mind.
    [Show full text]