THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Thomas Aquinas on How

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY of AMERICA Thomas Aquinas on How THE CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA Thomas Aquinas on How Habits Affect Human Powers and Acts A DISSERTATION Submitted to the Faculty of the School of Philosophy Of The Catholic University of America in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree Doctor of Philosophy By Blaise Edward Blain Washington, D.C. 2017 Thomas Aquinas on How Habits Affect Human Powers and Acts Blaise Edward Blain, Ph.D. Director: Tobias Hoffmann, Ph.D. The aim of this dissertation is to provide the groundwork for a deeper understanding of habits by considering in a systematic fashion some fundamental questions about the effects of habits on human powers and acts in light of Thomas Aquinas’s philosophical writings. The opening chapters offer a general consideration of human powers and acts in the context of which I also explain Aquinas’s account of why habits are necessary for the perfection of the human being. In the subsequent chapters, I explain how, on Aquinas’s account, habits with rational objects can be present in powers of the soul with corporeal organs and why the will is in need of habits. I also offer an account of Aquinas’s striking position that a habit in one power can affect the acts of a different power, even without the mediation of another act, giving special attention to Aquinas’s account of knowledge by connaturality. This dissertation by Blaise Edward Blain fulfills the dissertation requirement for the doctoral degree in philosophy approved by Tobias Hoffmann, Ph.D., as Director, and by Kevin White, Ph.D., and Angela Knobel, Ph.D. as Readers. Tobias Hoffmann, Ph.D., Director Kevin White, Ph.D., Reader Angela Knobel, Ph.D., Reader ii For the glory of God, In honor of the Blessed Virgin Mary and St. Joseph, her most chaste spouse, And for the love of my wife and children iii Acknowledgments I am especially grateful to my director Tobias Hoffmann, my committee members Kevin White and Angela Knobel, and John McCarthy, the Dean of the School of Philosophy for their encouragement and guidance during the writing of this dissertation. I would also like to thank in a special way Dominic Bolin, Herbert Hartmann and Michael Staron, whose conversations with me about philosophy have helped me to gain a more profound understanding of many truths. Finally, I am deeply grateful to my wife and children, who have supported and encouraged me throughout my graduate studies. iv Contents Introduction 1 1 Objects, Powers, and the Necessity of Habits 13 1.1 Objects, Powers, and the Complex World of Human Experience . 13 Powers .......................................... 13 Objects . 25 Rational Powers and Objects . 33 1.2 The Necessity of Habits . 49 Early Texts . 51 Later Texts . 56 Summary . 63 2 Human Acts 65 2.1 Aquinas and the Aristotelian Account of Natural Motion . 66 The Definition of Motion . 66 Motion As Imperfect Act . 69 Motion As Act of Mover and Mobile . 69 Inclination, Movement, and Rest . 70 2.2 Motion from Things to the Soul: Sensitive and Intellectual Cognition . 75 Sensation . 75 Abstraction . 84 Acts of Reason . 86 2.3 Motion of the Soul to Things: Appetite and Practical Reasoning . 91 Acts of the Sensitive Appetite . 91 Acts of Will and Practical Reason . 98 2.4 The Twofold Order of the Sensitive and the Rational . 127 The Continuation of the Sensitive and the Rational . 127 The Obedience or Subjection of the Sense Powers to Reason . 129 The Participation of the Sensitive in Reason . 131 Summary . 136 3 The Subject of Habit 138 3.1 Habits with Rational Objects and the Sensitive Part of the Soul . 138 Inadequate Responses to the Difficulty . 142 Aquinas’s Account of Habits . 144 v The Order of Habits in the Sensitive Part of the Soul to the Rational . 156 3.2 The Will’s Need for Habits . 166 Earlier Texts: A Reason to Doubt the Existence of Habits in the Will . 167 Later Texts: Why the Will Needs Naturally Acquired Habits . 169 Summary . 175 4 Habit As Principle of Acts 176 4.1 The Influence of Habit upon the Acts of Its Own Subject . 177 Habit: Infallible Inclination to Good or Evil . 178 Habit: Perfecter of Natural Inclination . 181 4.2 How Habits Affect the Acts of Powers to Which They Do Not Belong . 187 General Account . 189 Specific Cases . 190 4.3 Summary . 208 Conclusion 212 Bibliography 216 vi Table of Abbreviations De car. Quaestio disputata de caritate De card. Quaestio disputata de virtutibus cardinalibus De ebd. Expositio libri Boetii De ebdomadibus De ente De ente et essentia De malo Quaestiones disputatae de malo De pot. Quaestiones disputatae de potentia De spe Quaestio disputata de spe De spir. Quaestio disputata de spiritualibus creaturis De Trin. Super Boetium De Trinitate De ver. Quaestiones disputatae de veritate DGC In librum primum Aristotelis De generatione et corruptione expositio DVC Quaestio disputata de virtutibus in communi ELP Expositio libri Peryermeneias ELPA Expositio libri Posteriorum In de an. Sentencia libri De anima In Metaph. In duodecim libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis expositio In Phys. Commentaria in octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis In Sent. Scriptum super libros Sententiarum In Sent. (Earlier Redaction) Scriptum super tertio Sententiarum: Earlier Redaction QDA Quaestiones disputatae de anima Quod. II Quodlibet II Quod. V Quodlibet V Quod. VIII Quodlibet VIII Quod. X Quodlibet X Quod. XII Quodlibet XII SCG Summa contra gentiles SLE Sententia libri Ethicorum ST Summa theologiae vii Introduction Habit: Principle of Human Perfection According to Thomas Aquinas, human beings, unlike angels, do not acquire perfection all at once, but must instead be led by the hand from imperfection to perfection.1 Whereas the angels merited eternal happiness by a single act, human beings must struggle to achieve beatitude by means of many actions. For humans beings to persevere in this struggle with greater ease and assurance, however, these acts are not sufficient by themselves. We also need to acquire stable dispositions to these acts, dispositions that Aquinas calls habits (in Latin: habitus). Without such habits, consistently excellent behavior is impossible from a practical point of view. The necessity of habits in human life is clearly appreciated by Aquinas, for twice in his writings, he devotes an entire article to arguing for the necessity of habits.2 According to Aquinas, the need for habits is not restricted to moral activity alone; habits are also necessary for the life of the mind. For example, human beings need habits not only of justice and courage in order to act morally, but also of science and wisdom in order to know reality in a more complete and profound fashion. For this reason, habits are of great interest not only to students of ethics and moral theologians, but also to philosophers of knowledge and more generally to anyone wishing to perfect his or her human capacities, whether moral or intellectual. While the importance of habits is evident, a deep understanding of them is more difficult to obtain, 1 See for example SCG, IV, cap. 55. 2 One article appears in his early commentary on Peter the Lombard’s Sentences; the other appears in his Summa theologiae near the end of his career. See In Sent., III, d. 23, a. 1 and ST, I-II, q. 49, a. 4. There are also several other discussions of the necessity of habits developed by Aquinas in other contexts. A more complete account will be given below in chapter one. 1 2 because they are not known directly but only by means of the actions to which they give rise.3 One does not know what justice and courage are, for example, until one sees just and courageous acts. Yet in spite of their elusiveness, habits remain involved in a host of pressing ethical and psychological questions. Among these are questions such as whether there exist moral habits that always incline their possessor in the right way, how habits affect one’s perception of and judgment about moral situations, and what influence habits can have or ought to have on our emotions. The difficulty of providing satisfactory answers to such questions is evident, not only because we lack an immediate experience of habits, but also because adequately answering such questions presupposes a highly developed philosophical account of human nature and action. The philosophy of Thomas Aquinas provides a promising starting point from which to study habits, not only on account of his sharp mind and sound methodological principles, but also because he develops a philosophical account of habits against the backdrop of a detailed philosophy of human nature and action. However, even in the masterful work of Aquinas, certain of his teachings on habits are not immediately clear. In particular, important questions arise in connection with Aquinas’s account of how habits perfect powers and acts of the soul.4 In Aquinas’s account, the perfection brought about by a habit generally involves multiple powers and acts of the soul. For example someone with the habit of courage feels fear in accordance with reason. This means that the habit is somehow related both to that person’s capacity for fear and to his or her rational capacity. At the same time, Aquinas holds that the courageous person both correctly judges the amount of fear and daring that a situation demands and also feels fear in the right way and to the correct degree. Thus the habit of courage appears to have an influence on both affective and cognitive acts. Positions such as these illustrate the need for 3 Cf. ST, I, q. 87, a. 2. 4 It is worth mentioning that Aquinas speaks not only of habits in powers of the soul, but also of certain “habitual dispositions” of the body, such as health.
Recommended publications
  • Peter Harvey 6 Confucius 46 David L
    The World’s Great Philosophers The World’s Great Philosophers Edited by ROBERT L. ARRINGTON © 2003 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148-5018, USA 108 Cowley Road, Oxford OX4 1JF, UK 550 Swanston Street, Carlton South, Melbourne, Victoria 3053, Australia Kurfürstendamm 57, 10707 Berlin, Germany The right of Robert L. Arrington to be identified as the Author of the Editorial Material in this Work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. First published 2003 by Blackwell Publishing Ltd Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data The world’s great philosophers / edited by Robert L. Arrington. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-631-23145-5 (hardcover : alk. paper)—ISBN 0-631-23146-3 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Philosophers. 2. Philosophy. I. Arrington, Robert L., 1938– B29 .W69 2003 109¢.2—dc21 2002004264 A catalogue record for this title is available from the British Library. Set in 10/12.5 pt Baskerville by SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd., Hong Kong Printed and bound in Great Britain by T J International Ltd, Padstow, Cornwall For further information on Blackwell Publishing, visit our website: http://www.blackwellpublishing.com Contents List of Contributors viii Preface xi 1 Aquinas 1 Timothy Renick 2 Aristotle 9 Russell Dancy 3 Augustine 23 Vernon J.
    [Show full text]
  • The Future of Thomism: an Introduction
    THE FUTURE OF THOMISM: AN INTRODUCTION Deal W. Hudson Thomism usually comes in horrible wrappers. -Flannery O'Connor In spite of her complaint, the lady Thomist from Milledgeville, Georgia, read the Summa in bed every night before going to sleep. It was only where she read St. Thomas that was unusual. In fact, when she was reading St. Thomas and complaining about Thomism, his name was often heard and welcomed in, Catholic circles. Twentieth-century dis- ciples like Jacques Maritain, Etienne Gilson, Josef Pieper, Mortimer J. Adler,andYvesR.Sirnonweremuchinvogue,informingwhatwewould now call the "mainstream" of Catholic thought. All of this influence, it can be noted, in spite of the bad packaging. These days Thomism plays a minor role in philosophy at large, though a somewhat greater one among Catholic and Christian philoso­ phers. It is hard to say whether Thomistic exteriors are as gruff now as they once appeared to the author of Wise Blood, or whether its image is even the problem. We now enjoy access to a "readable" abridged Summa Theologiae in English with the form of the articles removed. 1 Who knows whether putting St. Thomas into modem prose will do the trick of making him popular again? There must still be readers coming to the Summa for the first time who find themselves anachronistically attracted to the old layout, objections, sed contra, response, replies, the spaces in between providing the silence for reflecticm and anticipation. But for those who love St. Thomas any attempt to let him speak to the present age has to be appreciated: because something has gone amiss.
    [Show full text]
  • The Political Implications of Thomas Aquinas's Theory of Conscience
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2013 Thinking Together about the Common Good: The Political Implications of Thomas Aquinas's Theory of Conscience Angela Concetta Miceli Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Miceli, Angela Concetta, "Thinking Together about the Common Good: The oP litical Implications of Thomas Aquinas's Theory of Conscience" (2013). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 252. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/252 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. THINKING TOGETHER ABOUT THE COMMON GOOD: THE POLITICAL IMPLICATIONS OF THOMAS AQUINAS’S THEORY OF CONSCIENCE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Louisiana State University Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Angela Concetta Miceli B.A., Thomas More College of Liberal Arts, 2005 M.A., Louisiana State University, 2010 May 2013 © Copyright 2013 Angela Concetta Miceli All rights reserved ii Acknowledgements I have written a dissertation in which I have reflected on how human beings depend upon one another for all the essential things in life. Writing a dissertation, while perhaps not an essential thing in life is such a task that indeed cannot be done in isolation, and I have depended upon the goodness and love of many to complete this project.
    [Show full text]
  • The Poiesis of 'Human Nature'
    THE POIESIS OF ‘HUMAN NATURE’ An exploration of the concept of an ethical self Leticia Worley Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of Social Sciences and Psychology Faculty of Arts, Education and Human Development Victoria University October 2011 To the memory of my husband, John Malcolm Worley, my beloved soul mate (1946-1993) And for Marianne and Luis, in whom their father’s generous spirit, inspiration and love, lives on ii Abstract This thesis inquires into our ‘human nature’ through an interdisciplinary approach that considers some of the radical changes in intellectual thought at those key points in Western culture in which this concept has been centrally deployed. The broad historical sweep that this study covers finds the preoccupation with defining who we are and what we are capable of inextricably linked with the focus, at most of the pivotal moments examined, on a dominant impulse to conceive human beings as moral creatures. The continuities and discontinuities in complex lines of thought about ‘human nature’, the origins and exploration of our ‘moral instincts’, and most importantly, of our sense of ethical commitment, is therefore central to this inquiry. Thinking of such an exploration as an ongoing poietic journey, and extending the etymological derivation of the term poiesis, the ancient Greek term for ‘to make’, the study hopes to awaken a sense of ongoing creation, an inscribing and revision, a process of meaning-making of the ideas that have shaped our sense of selfhood in the Western intellectual tradition; one that regards humans as rational and moral beings engaged in a search for self- realisation and fulfilment in our contemporary world.
    [Show full text]
  • Keeping the Command: Karl Barth's Moral Theology in Dialogue With
    Keeping the Command: Karl Barth’s Moral Theology in Dialogue with Late Medieval Scholasticism by James Andrew Edwards A Thesis submitted to the Faculty of Wycliffe College and the Theology Department of the Toronto School of Theology In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology awarded by the University of St. Michael’s College © Copyright by James Andrew Edwards 2016 Keeping the Command: Karl Barth’s Moral Theology in Dialogue with Late Medieval Scholasticism James Andrew Edwards Doctor of Philosophy in Theology University of St. Michael’s College 2016 Abstract Due to its dogged persistence in using the language of “divine command,” Karl Barth’s moral theology has, until recent years, been accused of being overly “voluntarist.” Recent scholars of Barth’s work, however, have attempted to exonerate his work, often by way of positive comparisons with the moral theology of Thomas Aquinas. Both perspectives, however, are inaccurate. Defenders and critics of Barth’s moral theology ignore the historical particularities of the voluntarist tradition of moral enquiry and thereby miss the positive contribution that it makes. Scholars interested in upholding Barth’s honor, therefore, need not presume that “voluntarism” is an a priori condemnation. The present thesis examines the voluntarist tradition of moral enquiry both in its late medieval scholastic and Barthian articulations. A shared “grammar” of divine command both “from above” and “from below” is demonstrated to exist in the moral theologies of John Duns Scotus, William of Ockham, and Karl Barth. Theological voluntarism “from above” is explored vis-à-vis the dialectic of divine omnipotence, in which God’s absolute power and possibility is consistently balanced with an equally absolute divine constancy.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Ethics and Objective Reason
    Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I. Culture and Values, Vol. 11 Ethics at the Crossroads Volume I Normative Ethics and Objective Reason Edited by George F. McLean The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy 1 Copyright © 1996 by The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy Gibbons Hall B-20 620 Michigan Avenue, NE Washington, D.C. 20064 All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Normative ethics and objective reason, vol. I of Ethics at the crossroad / edited by George F. McLean. p.cm. — (Cultural heritage and contemporary change, George F. McLean, gen. ed.; Series I. Culture and values ; vol. 11) Includes bibliographical references and index. 1. Ethics. 2. Objectivity. 3. Decision-making (Ethics). I. McLean, George F. II. Series. III. Series I, Culture and values ; vol. 11) BJ1012.E8935 1995 vol. I 92-13187 170s—dc21 CIP [170’.44] ISBN 1-56518-022-4 (pbk.) 2 Table of Contents Introduction 1 Part I. Ethics as Response to Changing Situations 1. Pragmatic Tests and Ethical Insights 9 by Abraham Edel 2. Naturalism, Situation Ethics and Value Theory 29 by Joseph Fletcher 3. The Character of Moral Reasoning 39 by Vincent C. Punzo 4. Humanism and Ethics 51 by Howard L. Parsons 5. Moral Agreement Under a Diversity of Values 87 by Peter Caws Part II. Ethics as Objective and Normative A. Objective Foundations: Dignity of the Person and the Morally Good 6. The Person, Moral Growth and Character Development 99 by George F. McLean 7. The Foundations of Moral Judgment 131 by David Schindler 8.
    [Show full text]
  • The Center for Thomistic Studies University of St
    The Center for Thomistic Studies University of St. Thomas Houston, TX History of the Center 1975-2012 1975-1978 Founding of the Center The Center for Thomistic Studies was founded in 1975 at the University of St. Thomas, a Catholic University founded by members of the Congregation of St. Basil and located in the Diocese of Galveston- Houston. English-speaking Basilians in North America have long been connected with fostering the study of Aquinas, most prominently by founding, along with Etienne Gilson, the Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies at the University of Toronto in 1929. In 1976, at the request of the Center’s principal founder, Fr. Victor B. Brezik, CSB, Professor Anton C. Pegis, formerly president of the Institute of Mediaeval Studies at Toronto, accepted the position of Director of the Center. His was the responsibility for designing the program, acquiring a suitable Fr. Brezik, Jacques Maritain, and Fr. Sullivan faculty, and supervising the accumulation of library resources. The Vision of Dr. Pegis: “Some fifty years ago, Catholic universities were teaching philosophy with a dogmatic dedication to truth, to St. Thomas Aquinas and to the guidance of theology. The dominant aim was to teach philosophical truth ‘according to the mind of St. Thomas Aquinas.’ Since St. Thomas was a theologian, this attitude in time raised a question. What, then, was the difference between teaching theology and teaching philosophy? Philosophy was a free intellectual inquiry, it was argued, and could not be taught dogmatically as theology was. Mainly after the Second World War, the dogmatic teaching of philosophy was succeeded, partly under the pressure of criticism (both hostile and benign) and partly under the influence of a new generation of teachers (coming to Catholic departments of philosophy from many intellectual climates) with a more pluralistic attitude toward the teaching of philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • A Tribute to Rev. Gerald B. Phelan: Educator and Lover of Truth
    A Tribute to Rev. Gerald B. Phelan: Educator and Lover of Truth Desmond J. FitzGerald Monsignor Gerald Bernard Phelan (1892-1965) was a priest from Halifax, Nova Scotia. After studies in the local seminary of Halifax, he was ordained in 1914. Fr. Phelan went to the Catholic University ofAmerica for his first graduate work and received a S.T.B. from there in 1915. In 1924, he received a Ph.D. from the University of Louvain, followed by the Agrege en Philosophie in 1925 from the same institution. In this way, he was part of that generation of Thomists who, having studied at Louvain, brought the enthusiasm of the Thomistic Revival to Canada. Interestingly, his Louvain dissertation concerned the experimental psychology of feeling and its mo­ dalities, and it was as a professor of psychology that Fr. Phelan came to St. Michael's, University ofToronto, in 1925. Fr. Phelan was thus at the University of Toronto when the Basilian Fa­ thers, especially Fr. Henry Carr, C. S.B., began planning an institute for medieval philosophy that, at the suggestion of Etienne Gilson, eventually becoming a Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies when it received its papal charter from Pope Pius XII in 1939. Working as co-director with Gilson, Fr. Phelan undertook the work of assembling a library suitable for medieval research, collecting microfilms of manuscripts, the originals of which existed in a number of European libraries. Fr. Phelan also developed a working relation­ ship with the Dean of the graduate school of the University of Toronto, whereby it came about that the courses in philosophy given in the Pontifical Institute would count for credit towards graduate degrees of the University 98 DESMOND J.
    [Show full text]