Alasdair Macintyre Introduction: After Virtue and Beyond: the Search for First Principles

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Alasdair Macintyre Introduction: After Virtue and Beyond: the Search for First Principles Alasdair MacIntyre Introduction: After Virtue and beyond: the search for first principles Alasdair MacIntyre (born 1929 in Glasgow, Scotland) 1951: Death of Ludwig Wittgenstein 1953: Publication of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations 1953: Marxism: An Interpretation. 1955 (edited with Antony Flew): New Essays in Philosophical Theology 1958: The Unconscious: A Conceptual Analysis. 1958: Publication of Elizabeth (GEM) Anscombe’s “Modern Moral Philosophy” 1959: Difficulties in Christian Belief. 1966 A Short History of Ethics. 1967: Secularization and Moral Change. 1969 (with Paul Ricœur): The Religious Significance of Atheism. 1970: Herbert Marcuse: An Exposition and a Polemic. 1981: After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory 1988: Whose Justice? Which Rationality? 1990: Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry. The Gifford Lectures. 1990: First Principles, Final Ends, and Contemporary Philosophical Issues 1999: Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues. Argument of After Virtue 1. Contemporary moral debates are interminable 2. Cause of this is the failure of the “Enlightenment project” to offer a universal secular ethic 3. Contemporary moral reasoning employs illusory notions of obligation that are ungrounded vestiges of an earlier moral vision. They function the way Taboos functioned in Polynesian culture. 4. Nietzsche understood the failure of the Enlightenment project, but his critique doesn’t hold for Aristotle’s moral vision: “Aristotle and Nietzsche represent the only two compelling alternatives in contemporary moral theory.” 5. An adequate reading of the genealogy of western ethics reveals that Aristotle’s conception of virtue had three features: (1) virtues are those qualities without which humans cannot obtain the goods internal to practices; (2) practices are "any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that form of activity are realized in the course of trying to achieve those standards of excellence which are appropriate to, and partially definitive of, that form of activity, with the result that human powers to achieve excellence, and human conceptions of the ends and goods involved, are systematically extended" (AV 175): examples of practices are farming and fishing, the pursuit of the sciences and the arts, and the playing of games as well as politics as Aristotle understood it. (3) Virtues are also those qualities required to achieve the good which furnish individual human lives their ultimate end (telos) within the narrative structure of unified form of life, a structure that only exists by being embedded with lived social traditions. 6. The failure to maintain the social structures that gave life a narrative structure lead to the Enlightenment rejection of the virtue tradition. 7. The rejection of Aristotelian virtue, however, was not warranted. The only way to understand the current situation and to recover an adequate conception of the moral good is by returning to social traditions that support a renewed narrative structure for a unified vision of human flourishing and the virtues proper to it. .
Recommended publications
  • Liberalism, Neutrality and the Politics of Virtue
    Koray Tütüncü Liberalism, neutrality and the politics of virtue Abstract The relationship between politics and virtue has been a controversial issue. Some significant scholars make a sharp distinction between what is political and what is not, but others underline the impossibility of separating politics from virtue. This article aims to re-consider the problem of virtue in terms of liberal politics. In doing so, it distinguishes three different arguments, namely the ‘inescapability of virtue’, ‘virtue lost’ and ‘reclamation of virtue’ arguments. The first argument underlines the impossibility of separating politics from virtue; the second shows the impossibility of virtuous politics in modern liberal politics; while the third criticises liberal neu- trality and individualism which undermines virtue politics. This article offers in their place a Rawlsian solution which centralises justice as the first virtue of a well-or- dered liberal society. It argues that, without negotiating fundamental rights and equal liberties, a Rawlsian solution transcends the limitations of liberal neutrality by articulating political virtuousness into liberalism. The result is that it concludes that liberal democracies would be politically virtuous without imposing any particular virtuous life conceptions. Keywords: virtue, liberal politics, good life, procedural and substantive neutrality, inequalities, justice, rights, perfectionism, freedoms, obligations, relativism, utili- tarian, Kantian, communitarian, individualism Introduction The relationship between politics and virtue has long been a controversial issue. Some significant political scholars make a sharp distinction between what is political and what is not, and consider morality and virtues as apolitical issues,1 while others underline the impossibility of separating politics from virtues, despite a unity of polit- ical and virtuous lives having been more apparent in ancient and medieval times.2 Some argue that modernity aims to separate politics not only from the religious but also from the virtuous.
    [Show full text]
  • After Virtue Chapter Guide
    After Virtue After Virtue by Alasdair MacIntyre. Wikipedia has a very useful synopsis (permalink as accessed Dec 9 2008). Citations refer to the 1984 second edition, ISBN 0268006113. Chapter Summary A note and disclaimer about the chapter summary: This summary is intended only to supplement an actual reading of the text. It is not sufficient in and of itself to understand MacIntyre's theory without having read the book, and even having read it, this guide is not sufficient to understand it in its entirety. A necessary amount of detail and nuance was eliminated in order to create the guide. Its intended purpose is to aid in comprehension of this complex but profoundly significant work during and after the process of reading it. I would suggest reading the synopsis of each chapter after reading the chapter. The goal is to present the outline of MacIntyre's claims and arguments with only a minimal gloss on the justifying evidence at each point. Thus, hopefully, the guide should prove reasonably sufficient to help a reader retain the crucial parts of MacIntyre's argument, and the text can be returned to for a full justification. It is easy to get bogged down in this book, but just take your time. No portion of his argument can be fully understood without understanding the whole— nevertheless, certain chapters deserve particular attention: Chapters 1-5, 9, 14, and 15. Enjoy. —Ari Schulman ([email protected]), Dec 9 2008 Chapter 1. A Disquieting Suggestion MacIntyre imagines a world in which the natural sciences "suffer the effects of a catastrophe": the public turns against science and destroys scientific knowledge, but later recants and revives science (1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Idea of a Communitarian Morality
    The Idea of a Communitarian Morality Philip Selznickt During the past few years, and especially since the publication of Alasdair MacIntyre's After Virtue in 1981, we have seen a renewed attack on the premises of liberalism.' There is nothing new about such criticism. A long list of writers-Hegel, Marx, Dewey, and many others, including several Popes-have recoiled in various ways from what seemed to be an impoverished morality and an inadequate understanding of human society. The contemporary criticism has raised some new issues and has been sparked, in no small degree, by a spate of impressive writing in legal, moral, and social philosophy-writing that has reaf- firmed the liberal faith in moral autonomy and in the imperatives of rationality. I refer, of course, to the work of John Rawls, Robert Nozick, and Ronald Dworkin. The new critics are called communitarian, an echo of similar views expressed in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries by English liberals like John A. Hobson and L.T. Hobhouse, and American pragmatists, especially John Dewey. Yet the communitarian idea is vague; in contemporary writing it is more often alluded to and hinted at than explicated. Furthermore, there are communitarians on both left and right. The quest for a communitarian morality is a meeting ground for conservatives, socialists, anarchists, and more ambiguously, welfare liber- als. Serious issues of social policy are at stake. It seems important, there- fore, to explore what a communitarian morality may entail. For if we shoot these arrows of the spirit we should know, as best we can, where they will light.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche's Ethic
    Nietzsche’s Ethic: Virtues for All and None? A thesis submitted To Kent State University in partial Fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Daniel Robinson May 2015 ©Copyright All rights reserved Except for previously published materials Thesis written by Daniel Robinson B.A., University of South Alabama, 2012 M.A., Kent State University, 2015 Approved by Linda Williams, Associate Professor, Masters Advisor Deborah Barnbaum, Chair, Department of Philosophy James Blank, Associate Dean, Dean of Arts and Sciences Table of Contents Introduction……………………………………………………….……………......01 Chapter I. Solomon’s Nietzsche: A Summary………………….………….....04 Introduction…………………………………..………...………….04 Concern for Character …………………………………………….05 Passion as the Root to the Virtues…………………………..……..15 Building Nietzsche’s Ethic: Virtues for All……………….….…...22 II. Nietzsche on Ethics……………………………………...……..….32 Introduction………………………………………………………..32 Custom & Natural Morality……………………………………….35 Master-type and Slave-type Moralities…………………………...41 Slave-type’s Universalization ……………………………………48 Nietzsche on Virtue and Virtues …………………….……………52 III. Ethical Contortions: Fitting Nietzsche into Virtue Ethics……...…59 Introduction…………………………………………………….…59 Against a Prescriptive Interpretation……………………….….….60 Redefining Virtue and Ethics……………………………….….…64 Nietzsche’s Individualism …………………………………..…....74 Relevant Bibliography…………………………………………………………….83 i Introduction A year ago I read Robert Solomon’s Living with Nietzsche: What the Great “Immoralist” Has to Teach Us for the first time with the hopes of finding a greater understanding of both Nietzsche and virtue ethics. I was undecided on whether Nietzsche was a virtue ethicist, but I was considering it, simply because of how frequently he mentions virtue and because Aristotle was one of the few major philosophers I knew of that Nietzsche didn’t routinely, vehemently reject. The beginning and middle of Solomon’s text made me very hopeful for his conclusion.
    [Show full text]
  • Kelvin Knight Aristotelianism Versus Communitarianism
    Analyse & Kritik 27/2005 ( c Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart) p. 259{273 Kelvin Knight Aristotelianism versus Communitarianism Abstract: Alasdair MacIntyre is an Aristotelian critic of communitarianism, which he understands to be committed to the politics of the capitalist and bureaucratic nation- state. The politics he proposes instead is based in the resistance to managerial insti- tutions of what he calls `practices', because these are schools of virtue. This shares little with the communitarianism of a Taylor or the Aristotelianism of a Gadamer. Although practices require formal institutions. MacIntyre opposes such conservative politics. Conventional accounts of a `liberal-communitarian debate' in political phi- losophy face the dilemma that Alasdair MacIntyre, often identified as a paradigmatic communitarian, has consistently and emphatically repudiated this characterization. Although neo-Aristotelianism is sometimes seen as a philosophical warrant for commu- nitarian politics, MacIntyre's Aristotelianism is opposed to communitarianism. This paper explores the rationale of that opposition. 1. Communitarianisms The term \communitarianism" was used by imaginative polemicists in the 1980s, and has been used by unimaginative textbook writers since then, to signify the criticism by a variety of Anglophone political philosophers of John Rawls' A Theory of Justice for resting upon overly individualist premisses. Despite the synthesizing efforts of Amitai Etzioni, it does not represent a coherent philo- sophical position. Nor can it do so unless some one theorist is chosen as its representative. Perhaps the best Anglophone candidate for such a position is Charles Taylor, yet Taylor considers the liberal-communitarian debate to have been conducted at `cross-purposes', with regard both to `ontological' issues of social theory and to moral or `advocacy' issues (Taylor 1989).
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Alasdair Macintyre's After Virtue
    Reading Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue Christopher S. Lutz Bloomsbury Publishing, New York-London 2012 Dario Mazzola 1. Christopher S. Lutz takes up the hard challenge of proving After Vir- tue’s relevance to philosophers and scholars of any school. Three elements of his rich reading guide are worth stressing: the relevance of the philosophy of science in relation to MacIntyre’s study in moral theory; the enquiry into Ma- cIntyre’s Marxist background; the usage of other works to clarify After Virtue’s claims, especially short essays and scarcely known early books. In addition to these and parallel to the unfolding of the main argument, the reader contains a retrieval of major critiques that takes into account the most controversial points of After Virtue. 2. The philosophy of science plays a fundamental role not only in After Virtue, but also in the preparatory works that precede MacIntyre’s best-known book. “Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative, and the philosophy of sci- ence” (MacIntyre 1977, first published inThe Monist, vol. 60 n. 4, pp. 453-72) is an article in which the scientific method, the enquiring subject’s existential certainties and moral philosophy come to interact. Lutz expounds the content of this essay and recalls the importance MacIntyre himself attached to it: [It] marks a major turning point in my thinking... It is elicited by my reading of and encounters with Imre Lakatos and Thomas Kuhn and what was transformed was my conception of what it was to make progress in philosophy (5). To explain this claim, Lutz pays much attention to the theories of Lakatos, Kuhn, and Popper: an understandable move, considered that the aim of his book is that of helping people at their first encounter withAfter Virtue.
    [Show full text]
  • After Virtue 3Rd Ed 10/23/08 9:24 AM Page Iii
    MacIntyre After Virtue 3rd Ed 10/23/08 9:24 AM Page iii After Virtue A Study in Moral Theory By ALASDAIR MACINTYRE Third Edition University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana © 2007 University of Notre Dame Press MacIntyre After Virtue 3rd Ed 10/23/08 9:24 AM Page iv Third edition published in the United States in 2007 by the University of Notre Dame Press Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 www.undpress.nd.edu All Rights Reserved Manufactured in the United States of America Second edition published in the United States in 1984 by the University of Notre Dame Press First edition published in the United States in 1981 by the University of Notre Dame Press First Edition first published in 1981 by Gerald Duckworth & Co. Ltd. The Old Piano Factory 43 Gloucester Crescent London NW1 Copyright © 1981, 1984, 2007 by Alasdair MacIntyre Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data MacIntyre, Alasdair C. After virtue : a study in moral theory / by Alasdair MacIntyre. — 3rd ed. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-268-03504-4 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 0-268-03504-0 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Ethics. 2. Virtues. 3. Virtue. I. Title. BJ1012.M325 2007 170'.42—dc22 2006102640 ∞ The paper in this book meets the guidelines for permanence and durability of the Committee on Production Guidelines for Book Longevity of the Council on Library Resources. © 2007 University of Notre Dame Press MacIntyre After Virtue 3rd Ed 10/23/08 9:24 AM Page ix Prologue After Virtue after a Quarter of a Century If there are good reasons to reject the central theses of After Virtue, by now I should certainly have learned what they are.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Download After Virtue a Study in Moral Theory, Second Edition 2Nd
    AFTER VIRTUE A STUDY IN MORAL THEORY, SECOND EDITION 2ND EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Alasdair MacIntyre | 9780268006112 | | | | | After Virtue A Study in Moral Theory, Second Edition 2nd edition PDF Book Kiyosaki , Paperback 4. Science Logic and Mathematics. With such an incomplete framework on which to base their moral understanding, the philosophers of the Enlightenment and their successors were doomed from the beginning. Kant's Conception of Virtue. Political Theory. Moral Reflection. Edit this record. Alasdair MacIntyre. Cunningham - - Catholic University of America Press. Add to cart. Published by University of Notre Dame Press. New Paperback Quantity Available: 1. The Enlightenment's failure led to the chaotic state of modern morality and ethics, leading to the utilitarian mode that shaped the 20th century and onward. The book was first published in and has since gone through two subsequent editions, which have added to, but not changed, the original text. Aristotle, revisited. These include:. Instead of using social sciences as science, which would involve the use of past knowledge to predict future events by virtue of the "science" part of "social sciences," social studies and humanist studies are essentially generalizations. He claims that the new sciences, though superficially similar to the old, would in fact be devoid of real scientific content, because the key suppositions and attitudes would not be present. This text is dense and complex, but here is the gist of what each of the 19 chapters indicates. We found something similar. Sign in to use this feature. This entry has no external links. Seller Inventory think The change toward hyper-individualized life brought about the pluralism of ideas that led to this problem of ethics in the first place, and perhaps there is a hint at the future of ethics as a return to teliology.
    [Show full text]
  • Profiles in Service
    Profiles in Service 1905–2005 Written & Edited by: Rebecca Blair ’80 Michael G. Cartwright A. James Fuller Layout & Design: Jeannine Allen 2006 University of Indianapolis 3 TABLE OF CONTENTS I ntroduction V. M entors & T eac H ers Michael G. Cartwright .....................................................................5 Robert McBride .............................................................................88 Fred Hill ........................................................................................92 I . F ounders & P arents Alice Friman ...................................................................................96 J. T. Roberts ...................................................................................11 Charlie Guthrie ...........................................................................100 Alva Button Roberts ......................................................................14 JoAnn Domb ...............................................................................104 “The Genesis of the College” by J. T. Roberts ................................17 Matt Brock ...................................................................................106 Laura Steed ..................................................................................107 I I B rot H ers & S isters Kristina Russell.............................................................................108 The Hilton Brothers .......................................................................21 David Hilton ..........................................................................22
    [Show full text]
  • Anti-Enlightenment Politics: Alasdair Macintyre and Contemporary Communitarianism
    3/4/11 Anti-Enlightenment Politics: Alasdair MacIntyre and Contemporary Communitarianism Some Definitions Practice: “Any coherent and complex form of socially established cooperative human activity through which goods internal to that activity are realized.” From After Virtue (1982), pp. 187-88. Virtue: “An acquired human quality the possession and exercise of which tends to enable us to achieve those goods which are internal to practices and the lack of which effectively prevents us from achieving any such goods.” After Virtue, p 191. 1 3/4/11 Virtues embedded in practices “It belongs to the concept of a practice as I have outlined it— and as we are all familiar with it in our actual lives, whether we are painters or physicists or quarterbacks or indeed just lovers of good painting or first rate experiments or a well-thrown pass —that its goods can only be achieved by subordinating ourselves within the practice in our relationship to other practitioners. We have to learn to recognize what is due to whom; we have to be prepared to take whatever self- endangering risks are demanded along the way; and we have to listen carefully to what we are told about our own inadequacies and to reply with the same carefulness for the facts.” After Virtue , p. 191. The Primacy of the Individual vs. the Group “I think, therefore I am.” Ubuntu alternative: “I am -Rene Descartes because we are, and since (1596-1650) we are, therefore I am.” -John S. Mbiti, 2001 2 3/4/11 Aristotle’s Teleological Scheme “We thus have a threefold scheme in which human-nature-as-it- happens-to-be (human nature in its untutored state) is initially discrepant and discordant with the precepts of ethics and needs to be transformed by the instruction of practical reason and experience into human-nature-as-it-could-be-if-it-realized-its- telos.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Analysis of Aristotle, Kant, and Mill’S Moral Theories Will Sileo
    Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Senior Theses CMC Student Scholarship 2020 Why Does Aristotle Make so Much Sense? A Philosophical Analysis of Aristotle, Kant, and Mill’s Moral Theories will sileo Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses Part of the Applied Ethics Commons This Open Access Senior Thesis is brought to you by Scholarship@Claremont. It has been accepted for inclusion in this collection by an authorized administrator. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Claremont McKenna College Why Does Aristotle Make so Much Sense? A Philosophical Analysis of Aristotle, Kant, and Mill’s Moral Theories Submitted to Professor Alex Rajczi By Will Sileo For Senior Thesis Fall 2019 December 9th, 2019 Acknowledgements I’ve had a lot of help in writing this thesis. First of all, I would like to thank Professor Alex Rajczi of CMC, my thesis reader, for the immense amount of time and effort that he has contributed to my philosophy education. When I first visited CMC as a prospective student, I decided to audit a philosophy class, and soon found myself sitting in Professor Rajczi’s classroom listening to a conversation about civic ethics that was way over my head but inspiring all the same. After taking a further two classes with him while here at CMC, there was no one I’d rather have guiding me through this project. Professor, thank you for always pushing me to do my very best both in classes and over the past semester with my thesis. I would also like to thank all those amazing people whose company I have enjoyed during my time here.
    [Show full text]
  • VIRTUE ETHICS and COMMUNITARIANISM Rui Silva, University of the Azores
    1 VIRTUE ETHICS AND COMMUNITARIANISM Rui Silva, University of the Azores Abstract: The last decades have witnessed a revival of virtue ethics, in opposition to impersonal approaches to ethics and to attempts to codify moral knowledge in a set of rules or principles. The article argues that the humanist idea of Bildung can be an important contribution to the project of virtue ethics and explores the connections between virtue ethics and communitarianism. Keywords: ethics – virtue – communitarianism – Bildung – relativism To help others where one can is a duty, and besides this there are many spirits of so sympathetic a temper that, without any further motive of vanity, or self-interest, they find an inner pleasure in spreading happiness around them and can take delight in the contentment of others as their own work. Yet I maintain that in such a case an action of this kind, however right and however amiable it may be, has still no genuinely moral worth. […] It stands on the same footing as other inclinations […]; for its maxim lacks moral content, namely the performance of such actions, not from inclination, but from duty. Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals The Scruple of Conscience Gladly I serve my friends, but alas I do it with pleasure Hence I am plagued with doubt that I am not virtuous The Verdict For that there is no other advice: you must try to despise them, And then do with aversion what your duty commands Schiller, Xenien Suppose you are in a hospital recovering from a long illness. You are very bored and restless and at loose ends when Smith comes in once again.
    [Show full text]