A Thousand Plateaus the Sheer Volume and Complexity of Deleuze and Guattari’S a Thousand Plateaus Can Be Daunting

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Thousand Plateaus the Sheer Volume and Complexity of Deleuze and Guattari’S a Thousand Plateaus Can Be Daunting page size 234 x 156mm but follows EUP PPC jacket Hires CMYK pdf from Indesign CS6 17mm 3mm Brent Adkins ‘Brent Adkins has provided a great service to scholars, teachers and students with this very clear, precise, and insightful work. I will definitely use it in my courses and have every reason to recommend it to other teachers as well as to professionals looking for an overview of Deleuze and Guattari’s complex and difficult text.’ Deleuze an Deleuze Deleuze anD Professor John Protevi, Louisiana State University A guide to Deleuze and Guattari’s masterwork, Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus The sheer volume and complexity of Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus can be daunting. What is an assemblage? What is a rhizome? What is a war D machine? What is a body without organs? What is becoming-animal? Brent Adkins Guattari’s demonstrates that all the questions raised by A Thousand Plateaus are in service A ThousAnd to Deleuze and Guattari’s radical reconstruction of the methods and aims of philosophy itself. To achieve this he argues that the crucial term for understanding A Thousand Plateaus is ‘assemblage’. An assemblage is Deleuze and Guattari’s answer to the perennial philosophical question ‘What is a thing?’, and they assert that PlATeAus assemblages are always found on a continuum between stasis and change. Using clear language and numerous examples, each chapter analyzes an individual a 234mm plateau and examines the tendencies toward both stasis and change for each assemblage found there – whether it be social, political, psychological, musical, t biological or linguistic. housan This book will appeal to teachers of the text or anyone wanting to engage with it at a deeper level. Key Features l D Explains all the major terms found in A Thousand Plateaus Plateaus l Each chapter corresponds to a ‘plateau’ for ease of reference l Provides a singular interpretation of the work in terms of assemblages and connects that interpretation with traditional and contemporary debates within philosophy Brent Adkins is Associate Professor of Philosophy at Roanoke College. a CritiCal introDuCtion anD GuiDe ISBN 978-0-7486-8646-9 www.euppublishing.com Cover image: Maranta leuconeura © Mary Sue Ittner Cover design: www.richardbudddesign.co.uk Brent Adkins 3mm 17mm 2mm 2mm 17mm 3mm 156 mm 156mm 3mm 17mm spine 16 mm Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus A Critical Introduction and Guide BRENT ADKINS © Brent Adkins, 2015 © Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, 1987, A Thousand Plateaus, The Athlone Press, by permission of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc. Edinburgh University Press Ltd The Tun - Holyrood Road, 12(2f) Jackson’s Entry, Edinburgh EH8 8PJ www.euppublishing.com Typeset in 11/13pt Monotype Baskerville by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Stockport, Cheshire, and printed and bound in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon CR0 4YY A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 8645 2 (hardback) ISBN 978 0 7486 8647 6 (webready PDF) ISBN 978 0 7486 8646 9 (paperback) ISBN 978 0 7486 8648 3 (epub) The right of Brent Adkins to be identified as Author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, and the Copyright and Related Rights Regulations 2003 (SI No. 2498). Contents Acknowledgements vi Introduction: A Perceptual Semiotics 1 1. Rhizome 22 2. 1914: One or Several Wolves? 34 3. 10,000 BC: The Geology of Morals 42 4. November 20, 1923: Postulates of Linguistics 65 5. 587 BC–AD 70: On Several Regimes of Signs 83 6. November 28, 1947: How Do You Make Yourself a Body without Organs? 96 7. Year Zero: Faciality 108 8. 1874: Three Novellas, or “What Happened?” 120 9. 1933: Micropolitics and Segmentarity 128 10. 1730: Becoming-Intense, Becoming-Animal, Becoming- Imperceptible . 141 11. 1837: Of the Refrain 171 12. 1227: Treatise on Nomadology—The War Machine 191 13. 7000 BC: Apparatus of Capture 218 14. 1440: The Smooth and the Striated 231 Conclusion: The Ethics of Becoming 244 Suggestions for Further Reading 251 Bibliography 254 Index 260 Introduction: A Perceptual Semiotics Neither Félix Guattari nor Gilles Deleuze ever shied away from the label “metaphysician.” This is a bold claim, particularly in a time when the “death of metaphysics” has been proclaimed so loudly and for so long, not only by philosophers such as Martin Heidegger but also by Deleuze and Guattari’s contemporary, Jacques Derrida.1 Since Deleuze and Guattari are unabashedly doing metaphysics, the place to begin understanding their work, as well as Deleuze’s single-author works, is with metaphysics. I want to begin by briefly describing the metaphysics that I see at work across Deleuze’s entire corpus, so that I can place A Thousand Plateaus in context. If I were to describe Deleuze’s metaphysics in a single word it would be “continuity.” This, of course, raises numerous questions, chiefly, Continuity of what? We will get to these questions, but first in an effort to clarify what I have in mind by continuity, I would like to contrast it with discontinuity. I think the dominant trend in Western metaphysics has followed from discontinuity. This discontinuity is most clearly and importantly seen in the work of Plato, who is at great pains to show the incommensurable distance between virtue and virtuous acts, between beauty and beautiful things, between the good and particular goods. These pairs cannot be merely different in degree, as if one could define beauty empiri- cally if one looked at enough beautiful things. No, these pairs must be different in kind. There can be no common measure between them. Beauty and beautiful things belong to different orders of being. This distinction between different orders of being becomes codified in philosophy as the distinction between the sensible and 1 Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus intelligible. This is the fundamental metaphysical discontinuity that organizes much of Western thought. Discontinuity, however, raises the issue of relation. If these two realms are ontologically distinct, what is the nature of their relation to one another? The typical answer given, although the details vary widely, is some kind of hylo- morphism. That is, the sensible and the intelligible are related to one another as content and form. Thus, in Plato the ability to rec- ognize any sensible object as beautiful depends on its participation to some degree in the form of beauty. In this case the integrity and universality of beauty itself is maintained, while we can still admit that sensible objects can be more or less beautiful. The problem with the discontinuity of the sensible and the intelligible and its concomitant hylomorphism is that it requires a doctrine of analogy or resemblance between the sensible and the intelligible. For Deleuze and Guattari, the difficulty with any doctrine of analogy is that it fundamentally fails at the task of meta- physics. If, for example, I claim that this statue is beautiful, several related corollaries necessarily arise. First, the statue is not beauti- ful in the same way that beauty is beautiful. (We’ll leave aside for the moment Aristotle’s objection that different beautiful objects are not beautiful in the same way.) Second, as a sensible object it cannot in principle be identical to the intelligible form of beauty, so it must be in some respects not beautiful. Analogy thus entails both affirmation and negation, and it is here that we can see the beginning of what will become negative theology in the Christian tradition.2 The reason, then, that discontinuity (and its attendant hylomorphism and analogy) fails at metaphysics is that it ultimately cannot say what “is” is. The solution to this difficulty for Deleuze is to reject the dis- continuity of the sensible and intelligible and affirm instead their continuity. Not surprisingly this move has entailments that inversely mirror the entailments of discontinuity. Since continuity does not treat the sensible and the intelligible as different in kind it need not resort to a doctrine of analogy to account for their interrelation. The continuity of the sensible and the intelligible instead entails the univocity of being. Being is said everywhere in the same way. Being speaks with “one voice.” Furthermore, continuity rejects hylomor- phism and replaces it with hylozoism. “Hylozoism” is a term coined by Ralph Cudworth in his The True Intellectual System of the Universe (1678) to describe any position that held that matter is alive. Of course, to describe matter as living is to impute to it the power of self-movement or self-organization, a position that can only be seen 2 Introduction: A Perceptual Semiotics as inherently contradictory by those holding to any form of hylo- morphism, which held that matter received its motive force from an external principle. Kant is explicit about the contradictory nature of hylozoism in both the pre-critical Dreams of a Spirit-seer (1766) and the critical Critique of Judgment (1790). For Deleuze and Guattari the affirmation of hylozoism is crucial, because it avoids anchoring life in a transcendent principle and instead seeks purely immanent principles. DELEUZE’S EARLY WORK Deleuze’s affirmation of the continuity of the sensible and intel- ligible manifests itself in different ways across all of his works. The first way it manifests itself is through the choice of subject matter. Deleuze’s earliest books (1953–68) are monographs on individual philosophical and literary figures. Some of the choices seem obvious, especially Proust, Kant, and Nietzsche. Some of the choices, though, seem very strange, especially Sacher-Masoch, Spinoza, and Bergson. There are also what appear to be glaring omissions for a scholar in France after World War 2.
Recommended publications
  • Becoming-Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Political Nature of Thought Vernon W
    Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 4-2014 Becoming-Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Political Nature of Thought Vernon W. Cisney Gettysburg College Follow this and additional works at: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/philfac Part of the Philosophy of Mind Commons Share feedback about the accessibility of this item. Cisney, Vernon W. "Becoming-Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Nature of Thought." Foucault Studies 17 Special Issue: Foucault and Deleuze (April 2014). This is the publisher's version of the work. This publication appears in Gettysburg College's institutional repository by permission of the copyright owner for personal use, not for redistribution. Cupola permanent link: https://cupola.gettysburg.edu/philfac/37 This open access article is brought to you by The uC pola: Scholarship at Gettysburg College. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of The uC pola. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Becoming-Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Political Nature of Thought Abstract In this paper I employ the notion of the ‘thought of the outside’ as developed by Michel Foucault, in order to defend the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze against the criticisms of ‘elitism,’ ‘aristocratism,’ and ‘political indifference’—famously leveled by Alain Badiou and Peter Hallward. First, I argue that their charges of a theophanic conception of Being, which ground the broader political claims, derive from a misunderstanding of Deleuze’s notion of univocity, as well as a failure to recognize the significance of the concept of multiplicity in Deleuze’s thinking. From here, I go on to discuss Deleuze’s articulation of the ‘dogmatic image of thought,’ which, insofar as it takes ‘recognition’ as its model, can only ever think what is already solidified and sedimented as true, in light of existing structures and institutions of power.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Part I Deleuze and Systematic Philosophy
    Notes Introduction 1. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen R. Lane (New York: Viking, 1977), p. 240. 2. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi. (Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 3. 3. Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations, trans. Martin Joughin. (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), pp. 88–89. 4. Gilles Deleuze, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, trans. Constantine Boundas (New York: Columbia University Press, 1991), p. 107. 5. Ibid., p. 106. 6. Henri Bergson, The Creative Mind, trans. Mabelle L. Andison (New York: Philosophical Library, 1946), pp. 21–28. 7. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), p. 8. Part I Deleuze and Systematic Philosophy 1. Gilles Deleuze, Negotiations (1972–1990), trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Columbia University Press, 1995), p. 31. 2. Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Brian Massumi (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), p. 18. 3. Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul Patton (New York: Columbia University Press), pp. 170–6. 4. Gilles Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, trans. Martin Joughin (New York: Zone Books, 1992). This logic of expression is developed in chapters 1–2 and 6–8. 5. Spinoza brings together the notion of substance and expression in Part 1 of the Ethics: definitions 4 and 6, Proposition 10, and the Scholium following Proposition 10. The treatment of modifications and individuals first appears in Part 2, Proposition 7 along with its Corollary and Scholium.
    [Show full text]
  • Spinoza: the Velocities of Thought SEMINAR at the UNIVERSITY of PARIS, VINCENNES-ST
    GILLES DELEUZE Spinoza: The Velocities of Thought SEMINAR AT THE UNIVERSITY OF PARIS, VINCENNES-ST. DENIS, 1980-1981 _____________________________________________________________________________________ LECTURE 1 25 NOVEMBER 1980 TRANSLATED BY TIMOTHY S. MURPHY FOR WEB DELEUZE AUGMENTED TRANSCRIPTION AND TRANSLATION REVIEW BY CHARLES J. STIVALE It's quite curious the extent to which philosophy, up to the end of the 17th century, ultimately speaks to us, all the time, of God. And after all, Spinoza, excommunicated Jew, is not the last to speak to us of God. And the first book of his great work The Ethics is called “Of God.” And from all of them, whether it's Descartes, Malebranche, Leibniz, we get the impression that the boundary between philosophy and theology is extremely vague. Why is philosophy so compromised with God, and right up to the revolutionary coup of the 18th century philosophers? Is it a dishonest compromise [compromission] or something a little purer? We could say that thought, until the end of the 17th century, must take considerable account of the demands of the Church, thus it's clearly forced to take many religious themes into account. But one feels quite strongly that this is much too easy; we could just as well say that, until this era, thought's lot is somewhat linked to that of a religious feeling. I'm going back to an analogy with painting because it's true that painting is replete with images of God. My question is: is it sufficient to say that this is an inevitable constraint in this era? There are two possible answers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • ARTICLE Becoming-Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Political Nature Of
    Vernon W. Cisney 2014 ISSN: 1832‐5203 Foucault Studies, No. 17, pp. 36‐59, April 2014 ARTICLE Becoming‐Other: Foucault, Deleuze, and the Political Nature of Thought Vernon W. Cisney, Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Gettysburg College ABSTRACT: In this paper I employ the notion of the ‘thought of the outside’ as developed by Michel Foucault, in order to defend the philosophy of Gilles Deleuze against the criticisms of ‘elitism,’ ‘aristocratism,’ and ‘political indifference’—famously leveled by Alain Badiou and Peter Hallward. First, I argue that their charges of a theophanic conception of Being, which ground the broader political claims, derive from a misunderstanding of Deleuze’s notion of univocity, as well as a failure to recognize the significance of the concept of multiplicity in Deleuze’s thinking. From here, I go on to discuss Deleuze’s articulation of the ‘dogmatic im‐ age of thought,’ which, insofar as it takes ‘recognition’ as its model, can only ever think what is already solidified and sedimented as true, in light of existing structures and institutions of power. Then, I examine Deleuze’s reading of Foucault and the notion of the ‘thought of the outside,’ showing the ‘outside’ as the unthought that lies at the heart of thinking itself, as both its condition and its impossibility. Insofar as it is essential to thinking itself, finally, I argue that the passage of thought to the outside is not an absolute flight out of this world, as Hallward claims, but rather, a return of the different that constitutes the Self for Deleuze. Thinking is an ongoing movement of deterritorialization and reterritorialization, or as Foucault says, death and life.
    [Show full text]
  • Politics and Its Double: Deleuze and Political Ontology
    POLITICS AND ITS DOUBLE: DELEUZE AND POLITICAL ONTOLOGY POLITICS AND ITS DOUBLE: DELEUZE AND POLITICAL ONTOLOGY By BORNA RADNIK, Hon. B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University © Copyright by Borna Radnik, September 2013 McMaster University MASTER OF ARTS (2013) Hamilton, Ontario (Philosophy) TITLE: Politics and its Double: Deleuze and Political Ontology AUTHOR: Borna Radnik, Hon.B.A. (York University) SUPRVISOR: Dr. Barry Allen NUMBER OF PAGES: v, 130 ii ABSTRACT: The objective of this thesis is to intervene into the ongoing dispute surrounding the political import of Gilles Deleuze’s single-authored work, specifically Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense . This thesis presents an alternative explanation to the question of whether or not Deleuze’s philosophy is political. By situating the debate surrounding Deleuze’s political implications in the contemporary ontological turn in political theory, this thesis argues that Deleuze’s works can be considered to be political in the non-conventional sense of the term, that is, insofar as a conceptual distinction is made between politics and the political . I further argue that Deleuze’s univocal ontology influences a concept of the political that is immanent to his thought, and in this respect he can be said to present a political ontology . The reading of Deleuze’s political ontology addresses not only the common critiques of his philosophy as posed by thinkers such as Alain Badiou, Peter Hallward, and Slavoj Žižek, but also sheds light on the problematic relationship between philosophy and politics.
    [Show full text]
  • Transgender People's Deterritorialization In
    manusya 23 (2020) 116-126 brill.com/mnya Transgender People’s Deterritorialization in Arundhati Roy’s The Ministry of Utmost Happiness and Trace Peterson’s “After Before and After” Tanrada Lertlaksanaporn (ธัญรดา เลิศลักษณาพร) MA (English), Department of English, Faculty of Arts, Chulalongkorn University, Bangkok, Thailand [email protected] Abstract Arundhati Roy’s The Ministry of Utmost Happiness and Trace Peterson’s “After Before and After” have been studied in several aspects related to transgender issues. The pre- sentation of transgender people, especially the transgender protagonist in The Ministry of Utmost Happiness, has been criticized as a formulaic depiction with little portrayal of their struggles and triumphs. At the same time, the transgender protagonist is viewed positively as an integral force in the novel. The poem “After Before and After” has been praised for its creative portrayal of transgender people. A study of transgen- der issues in relation to desire and connection helps to show that both texts offer more possibilities of liberation towards the state of “becoming.” This study applies Gilles De- leuze and Félix Guattari’s theory of schizoanalysis to explore transgender people’s lines of flight, rhizomatic movements and transversal connections towards the state of de- territorialization in India and the US. Keywords transgender – post structuralism – becoming – deterritorialization © Tanrada Lertlaksanaporn, 2020 | doi:10.1163/26659077-02301006 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the
    [Show full text]
  • Gilles Deleuze and the Apolitical Production of Being
    Gilles Deleuze And the Apolitical Production of Being by Tim Paugh B.A., St. Francis Xavier University, 2005 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Political Science © Tim Paugh, 2008 University of Victoria All rights reserved. This thesis may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without the permission of the author. ii Gilles Deleuze and the Apolitical Production of Being By Tim Paugh, B.A., St. Francis Xavier University, 2005 Supervisory Committee Warren Magnusson (Department of Political Science) Supervisor Rob Walker (Department of Political Science) Departmental Member Luke Carson (Department of English) Outside Member iii Supervisory Committee Warren Magnusson (Department of Political Science) Supervisor Rob Walker (Department of Political Science) Departmental Member Luke Carson (Department of English) Outside Member Abstract Gilles Deleuze’s ontology is often understood to ground a kind of radical pluralism, the political defense of which is thought to be articulated most strongly in the Capitalism and Schizophrenia books. It is clear, however, that this “politics” is defined in a wholly negative way, and that the revolutionary dimension of these books is animated by a strictly ethical logic. In my view, if there is a politics in Deleuze it must be understood in relation to the central problem of his ontology: namely, the problem of understanding how being is produced. To grasp politics as a singularity, as a mode of ontological production, has a number of radical consequences – consequences, however, that Deleuze himself did not embrace. Ultimately, Deleuze’s conception of ontological production appears marked by an apolitics, in that any effective mobilization Being’s transformative potential requires that we stand posed to sacrifice anything of the integrity and organizational capacity of political existence that limits the expression of Being itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Demystifying Deleuze an Introductory Assemblage of Crucial Concepts
    Demystifying Deleuze An Introductory Assemblage of Crucial Concepts Edited by: Rob Shields and Mickey Vallee Introduction 7 Actualization 11 Machinic Assemblage 107 Affects 13 Animal/Becoming- Majoritarian/Minoritarian 111 Animal 17 Arboroscent (compare Minor 113 Molar/Molecular 117 Rhizomatic) 21 Art and Creativity 25 Multiplicity 121 Nomadic 125 Assemblage 29 Becoming 33 Percepts 129 Body without Organs (BwO) 37 Control/Societies of Control 41 Plane of Composition 133 Desire 47 Difference 51 Plane of Consistency 137 Duration 53 Ecosophy 55 Potential 141 Power 145 Emergence 59 Event 61 Refrain 149 Rhizome/Arborescent 153 Fabulation 65 Faciality 67 Flow 69 Schizoanalysis 157 Sense 161 Fold 71 Force 75 Haecceities 79 Smooth Space 163 Strata 167 Image of Thought 83 Immanence / Striated Space 171 Subject 175 Plane of Immanence 87 Imperceptible (Becoming) 91 Intensity/Intensive 95 179 Time Image/ Line, Line of Flight 99 Action Image 183 Virtual/Actual 189 Machine 103 War Machine 195 Contributors 199 5 D EMy STIFy INg DELEuzE Introduction The wasp and the orchid For our students, families and friends. emystifying Deleuze is more than a guide to the basic theoretical edifce of Gilles Deleuze. It is a workbook. It puts con- Dcepts into motion rather than clarifying them for comprehension; it builds tools for use instead of identifying names to remember; it primes the reader for working through diffcult pages of original text instead of standing in to make the concepts appear autonomous. And although Deleuze’s long time writing partner, Félix Guat- tari, is absent in the title of this book, his work 6 7 D EMy STIFy INg DELEuzE I NTRODu CTION and infuence is pervasive in the entries which If the social sciences and humanities are follow.
    [Show full text]
  • Deleuze and Plato John Bova and Paul M. Livingston In
    Univocity, Duality, and Ideal Genesis: Deleuze and Plato John Bova and Paul M. Livingston In Difference and Repetition, Gilles Deleuze outlines a theory of ideas as problems, existent on the level of a virtuality distinct from, but irreducibly related to, that of their incarnation in a variety of specifically constituted theoretical domains: Following Lautman and Vuillemin’s work on mathematics, ‘structuralism’ seems to us the only means by which a genetic method can achieve its ambitions. It is sufficient to understand that the genesis takes place not between one actual term, however small, and another actual term in time, but between the virtual and its actualisation – in other words, it goes from the structure to its incarnation, from the conditions of a problem to the cases of solution, from the differential elements and their ideal connections to actual terms and diverse real relations which constitute at each moment the actuality of time. This is a genesis without dynamism, evolving necessarily in the element of a supra-historicity, a static genesis which may be understood as the correlate of the notion of passive synthesis, and which in turn illuminates that notion.1 Deleuze’s identification of ideas with problems is adopted, in part, from the novel synthesis proposed by the mathematical philosopher Albert Lautman in a series of essays of the 1930s and 40s, between an unorthodox but textually-grounded Platonism and the mathematics of his time.2 Deleuze takes Lautman’s work to provide at least partial means for a reconciliation of structure and genesis, so that an account of the virtual structure of an idea-problem can at the same time, and without irreducible tension, function as an account of its real genesis in a specific, concrete domain.
    [Show full text]
  • Christology and the 'Scotist Rupture'
    Theological Research ■ volume 1 (2013) ■ p. 31–63 Aaron Riches Instituto de Filosofía Edith Stein Instituto de Teología Lumen Gentium, Granada, Spain Christology and the ‘Scotist Rupture’ Abstract This essay engages the debate concerning the so-called ‘Scotist rupture’ from the point of view of Christology. The essay investigates John Duns Scotus’s de- velopment of Christological doctrine against the strong Cyrilline tendencies of Thomas Aquinas. In particular the essay explores how Scotus’s innovative doctrine of the ‘haecceity’ of Christ’s human nature entailed a self-sufficing conception of the ‘person’, having to do less with the mystery of rationality and ‘communion’, and more to do with a quasi-voluntaristic ‘power’ over oneself. In this light, Scotus’s Christological development is read as suggestively con- tributing to make possible a proto-liberal condition in which ‘agency’ (agere) and ‘right’ (ius) are construed as determinative of what it means to be and act as a person. Keywords John Duns Scotus, ‘Scotist rupture’, Thomas Aquinas, homo assumptus Christology 32 Aaron Riches Introduction In A Secular Age, Charles Taylor links the movement towards the self- sufficing ‘exclusive humanism’ characteristic of modern secularism with a reallocation of popular piety in the thirteenth century.1 Dur- ing that period a shift occurred in which devotional practices became less focused on the cosmological glory of Christ Pantocrator and more focused on the particular humanity of the lowly Jesus. Taylor suggests that this new devotional attention to the particular human Christ was facilitated by the recently founded mendicant orders, especially the Franciscans and Dominicans, both of whom saw the meekness of God Incarnate reflected in the individual poor among whom the friars lived and ministered.
    [Show full text]