The Determinacy of Arithmetic: the Puzzle and Its Solution

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Determinacy of Arithmetic: the Puzzle and Its Solution The Determinacy of Arithmetic: The Puzzle and Its Solution Jared Warren Abstract It seems that our arithmetical notions are determinate — that there is a fact of the matter about every single arithmetical question whether or not we can discover it. But the determinacy of arithmetic is extremely puzzling given the algorithmic nature of human cognition and famous limiting results in mathematical logic, such as Gödel’s incompleteness theorems, which seem to show that no theory of arith- metic learnable by algorithmic creatures like us could possibly be determinate. I call this the puzzle of arithmetical determinacy. This paper has three central goals: (i) to vividly present this puzzle and impress upon the reader that it isn’t a mere idle curiosity (section 1); (ii) to argue that extant attempts to solve the puzzle, in- cluding those using the open-endedness of our arithmetical notions, have thus far failed (sections 2 and 4); and (iii) to clearly explain the notion of open-endedness in a philosophically illuminating fashion and show how the notion can be used to solve the puzzle when coupled with the externalist lessons of contemporary metasemantics (sections 3, 5, and 6). Keywords: Arithmetic, Indeterminacy, Open-Endedness, Incompleteness, Metaseman- tics, Externalism 1 The Puzzle Consider the following three claims: 1. ARITHMETIC: we have a determinate conception of arithmetic 2. COGNITION: human cognition is algorithmic 3. FAILURE: no determinate theory of arithmetic is algorithmic 1 1 THE PUZZLE Here I’m going to briefly explain each of these claims and argue that they’re individ- ually plausible before showing that jointly they give rise to an important puzzle about our grasp of arithmetic. I call this The Puzzle of Arithmetical Determinacy. The puzzle is perhaps best classified as metasemantic or metaconceptual—it resides in the border- lands of the philosophies of mind, language, and mathematics. As such, this puzzle should be of interest to a wide assortment of philosophers, but it isn’t as widely appre- ciated as it should be. (1) ARITHMETIC: we have a determinate conception of arithmetic. Roughly, this means that there is a fact of the matter about any given arithmetical question that can be asked. To illustrate: consider Goldbach’s conjecture, a famous, unproven arithmetical conjecture saying that every even natural number greater than two is the sum of two, possibly repeated, prime numbers. Despite centuries of effort by mathematicians, this conjecture has been neither proven nor refuted. According to ARITHMETIC, there is a fact about Goldbach’s conjecture even though we haven’t found it. What’s more: even if we never prove or refute Goldbach’s conjecture, according to ARITHMETIC, the conjecture is currently either true or false, not both, not neither. ARITHMETIC encodes the plausible idea that arithmetical truth is bivalent: every single arithmetical sentence f is either true or false, not both, not neither.1 This is intimately related to, and often taken to be explained by, the fact that every single interpretation of our arithmetical language that isn’t somehow ruled out by our practice has the very same structure. Say that an interpretation I of our arithmetical language is “admissible” if it isn’t ruled out by our practice, “inadmissible” otherwise. If every admissible interpretation of arithmetic has the very same structure, then any sentence f will be true in an admissible interpretation of arithmetic I just in case it is true in every admissible interpretation of arithmetic. Against this background, ARITHMETIC claims that in every admissible interpreta- tion of our arithmetical language, the “numbers” form an w-sequence. This is a claim that platonists and structuralists alike can endorse.2 In addition, even nominalists— those who reject the existence of abstract objects like numbers—will need to provide 1Given this, it may be wondered I don’t simply characterize determinacy using truth and falsity predi- cates (“T”, “F”) and a name-forming device (“ , ”) as follows: T f F f (or perhaps this conjoined p q p q _ p q with “ (T f F f )” and “ ( T f F f )”)? I don’t because there are subtle issues concerning ¬ p q ^ p q ¬ ¬ p q ^¬ p q the relationship between claims like these “internal” to our formal truth theory and “external” claims like bivalence. In particular, I’m skeptical that this disjunction states bivalence in the sense we want unless cer- tain assumptions about the background logic and proof system are also made. In addition, note that the “not neither” conjunct of the more involved statement of bivalence is simply equivalent to the simpler, dis- junctive statement if the truth theory is formulated in a logic with the DeMorgan laws and double negation elimination. 2Platonism is endorsed in, e.g., Gödel (1964), Maddy (1990), and Woodin (2004); structuralism is en- dorsed in, e.g., Benacerraf (1965), Resnik (1997), and Shapiro (1997). 2 1 THE PUZZLE some surrogate theory to handle the work that arithmetic does in science and daily life, so nominalists can endorse a version of ARITHMETIC couched in terms of the primi- tive notions of their favored surrogate theory.3 The key point is that ARITHMETIC isn’t a philosophically controversial claim accepted only by those who favor a particular philosophy of mathematics; rather it is a key point of agreement that cuts across most other issues in the philosophy of mathematics. ARITHMETIC is intuitively appealing—it sure seems like there is a fact of the mat- ter about Goldbach’s conjecture that is independent of our ability to discover it. But intuitively appealing claims are sometimes false. Why should we think that ARITH- METIC is true? ARITHMETIC is so fundamental and ingrained in our way of thinking that it’s dif- ficult to argue for it in a non-question begging way. Perhaps the best we can do is to point to the difficulty of conceiving of its falsity. Goldbach’s conjecture is true if there is a natural number that is both even and not the sum of two primes, false otherwise; what possible borderline case could there be? The difficulty of even imagining ARITH- METIC’s falsity is itself some evidence that ARITHMETIC is true. The informal rule of inference being used here is: if D is some state of affairs, from the inconceivability of D’s obtaining, we can conclude that D doesn’t, in fact, obtain: D is inconceivable (Incon) D ¬ It’s plausible that (Incon) is highly reliable, but it’s almost certainly invalid. There are more things on Heaven and Earth than are dreamt of in our philosophy.4 Still, the difficulty of conceiving of the falsity of ARITHMETIC is some reason to accept its truth, however weak. In addition, as far as we can conceive of the falsity of ARITHMETIC, its falsity is implausible.5 Combined with its intuitive plausibility, these considerations give us serious (but perhaps not independent) reason to accept ARITHMETIC. (2) COGNITION: human cognition is algorithmic. An algorithm is a recipe for solving a problem using a sequence of small, mindless steps. To say that some process is algorithmic is to say that it results from the execution of algorithms. The general notion of an algorithm abstracts away from issues of memory, lifespan, and computa- tional speed. This means that a process can be algorithmic without being computation- ally feasible. Logicians have proposed a number of formalized mathematical analyses 3Nominalism is endorsed in, e.g., Azzouni (2005), Chihara (1990), and Field (1980). 4Consider the converse inference, from D to D is conceivable, there is no reason to think this is valid, unless our minds were somehow specially designed for universal fact finding. And in many contexts these two inference rules will be interderivable, e.g., if we start with (Incon) we can derive the validity of its converse using conditional proof and a contrapositive rule ( f y y f). ¬ !¬ ` ! 5Some countervailing considerations are adduced in Field (1994). 3 1 THE PUZZLE of this informal notion, e.g., Turing machines, register machines, recursive functions, etc.6 In perhaps the most remarkable convergence in the history of logic, virtually all formal analyses of the notion of an algorithm that have been seriously proposed turn out to agree—a function is computable by a Turing machine just in case it computable by a register machine just in case it is recursive and so forth and so on. In addition, everything that is intuitively algorithmic is Turing computable, recursive, etc. This alignment of our formal and informal notions gives rise to Church’s Thesis: a func- tion is computable by an algorithm just in case it is computable by a Turing machine just in case it is computable by a register machine just in case it is recursive, etc. Al- though the thesis links an informal notion (algorithmic computability) to formal notions (e.g., Turing computability, recursiveness) and so isn’t open to a rigorous mathematical demonstration, no serious threat to Church’s thesis has ever been proposed.7 So far we’ve just been discussing numerical functions, but as every modern com- puter user knows, algorithms can do much more than crunch numbers when hooked up to action performing input/output machines. In this way, our modern digital computers play movies, process documents, analyze visual data and so on and so forth. This opens up the possibility that anything the human mind can do is done via some algorithmic process. Given Church’s thesis, to say that human cognition is algorithmic is to say that the mind can’t do anything that can’t be done, in principle, by a Turing machine.8 Al- though the human mind isn’t perfectly understood, one central feature of any scientific approach to the mind is that human cognition results from brain activity; the relevant kind of brain activities consist of neurons firing in various complicated patterns and thereby executing various complicated algorithms.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter 3 Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 3 Induction and Recursion 3.1 Induction: An informal introduction This section is intended as a somewhat informal introduction to The Principle of Mathematical Induction (PMI): a theorem that establishes the validity of the proof method which goes by the same name. There is a particular format for writing the proofs which makes it clear that PMI is being used. We will not explicitly use this format when introducing the method, but will do so for the large number of different examples given later. Suppose you are given a large supply of L-shaped tiles as shown on the left of the figure below. The question you are asked to answer is whether these tiles can be used to exactly cover the squares of an 2n × 2n punctured grid { a 2n × 2n grid that has had one square cut out { say the 8 × 8 example shown in the right of the figure. 1 2 CHAPTER 3. INDUCTION AND RECURSION In order for this to be possible at all, the number of squares in the punctured grid has to be a multiple of three. It is. The number of squares is 2n2n − 1 = 22n − 1 = 4n − 1 ≡ 1n − 1 ≡ 0 (mod 3): But that does not mean we can tile the punctured grid. In order to get some traction on what to do, let's try some small examples. The tiling is easy to find if n = 1 because 2 × 2 punctured grid is exactly covered by one tile. Let's try n = 2, so that our punctured grid is 4 × 4.
    [Show full text]
  • The Consistency of Arithmetic
    The Consistency of Arithmetic Timothy Y. Chow July 11, 2018 In 2010, Vladimir Voevodsky, a Fields Medalist and a professor at the Insti- tute for Advanced Study, gave a lecture entitled, “What If Current Foundations of Mathematics Are Inconsistent?” Voevodsky invited the audience to consider seriously the possibility that first-order Peano arithmetic (or PA for short) was inconsistent. He briefly discussed two of the standard proofs of the consistency of PA (about which we will say more later), and explained why he did not find either of them convincing. He then said that he was seriously suspicious that an inconsistency in PA might someday be found. About one year later, Voevodsky might have felt vindicated when Edward Nelson, a professor of mathematics at Princeton University, announced that he had a proof not only that PA was inconsistent, but that a small fragment of primitive recursive arithmetic (PRA)—a system that is widely regarded as implementing a very modest and “safe” subset of mathematical reasoning—was inconsistent [11]. However, a fatal error in his proof was soon detected by Daniel Tausk and (independently) Terence Tao. Nelson withdrew his claim, remarking that the consistency of PA remained “an open problem.” For mathematicians without much training in formal logic, these claims by Voevodsky and Nelson may seem bewildering. While the consistency of some axioms of infinite set theory might be debatable, is the consistency of PA really “an open problem,” as Nelson claimed? Are the existing proofs of the con- sistency of PA suspect, as Voevodsky claimed? If so, does this mean that we cannot be sure that even basic mathematical reasoning is consistent? This article is an expanded version of an answer that I posted on the Math- Overflow website in response to the question, “Is PA consistent? do we know arXiv:1807.05641v1 [math.LO] 16 Jul 2018 it?” Since the question of the consistency of PA seems to come up repeat- edly, and continues to generate confusion, a more extended discussion seems worthwhile.
    [Show full text]
  • Mathematical Induction
    Mathematical Induction Lecture 10-11 Menu • Mathematical Induction • Strong Induction • Recursive Definitions • Structural Induction Climbing an Infinite Ladder Suppose we have an infinite ladder: 1. We can reach the first rung of the ladder. 2. If we can reach a particular rung of the ladder, then we can reach the next rung. From (1), we can reach the first rung. Then by applying (2), we can reach the second rung. Applying (2) again, the third rung. And so on. We can apply (2) any number of times to reach any particular rung, no matter how high up. This example motivates proof by mathematical induction. Principle of Mathematical Induction Principle of Mathematical Induction: To prove that P(n) is true for all positive integers n, we complete these steps: Basis Step: Show that P(1) is true. Inductive Step: Show that P(k) → P(k + 1) is true for all positive integers k. To complete the inductive step, assuming the inductive hypothesis that P(k) holds for an arbitrary integer k, show that must P(k + 1) be true. Climbing an Infinite Ladder Example: Basis Step: By (1), we can reach rung 1. Inductive Step: Assume the inductive hypothesis that we can reach rung k. Then by (2), we can reach rung k + 1. Hence, P(k) → P(k + 1) is true for all positive integers k. We can reach every rung on the ladder. Logic and Mathematical Induction • Mathematical induction can be expressed as the rule of inference (P(1) ∧ ∀k (P(k) → P(k + 1))) → ∀n P(n), where the domain is the set of positive integers.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1311.3168V22 [Math.LO] 24 May 2021 the Foundations Of
    The Foundations of Mathematics in the Physical Reality Doeko H. Homan May 24, 2021 It is well-known that the concept set can be used as the foundations for mathematics, and the Peano axioms for the set of all natural numbers should be ‘considered as the fountainhead of all mathematical knowledge’ (Halmos [1974] page 47). However, natural numbers should be defined, thus ‘what is a natural number’, not ‘what is the set of all natural numbers’. Set theory should be as intuitive as possible. Thus there is no ‘empty set’, and a single shoe is not a singleton set but an individual, a pair of shoes is a set. In this article we present an axiomatic definition of sets with individuals. Natural numbers and ordinals are defined. Limit ordinals are ‘first numbers’, that is a first number of the Peano axioms. For every natural number m we define ‘ωm-numbers with a first number’. Every ordinal is an ordinal with a first ω0-number. Ordinals with a first number satisfy the Peano axioms. First ωω-numbers are defined. 0 is a first ωω-number. Then we prove a first ωω-number notequal 0 belonging to ordinal γ is an impassable barrier for counting down γ to 0 in a finite number of steps. 1 What is a set? At an early age you develop the idea of ‘what is a set’. You belong to a arXiv:1311.3168v22 [math.LO] 24 May 2021 family or a clan, you belong to the inhabitants of a village or a particular region. Experience shows there are objects that constitute a set.
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I, Volume 48, Number 6
    fea-woodin.qxp 6/6/01 4:39 PM Page 567 The Continuum Hypothesis, Part I W. Hugh Woodin Introduction of these axioms and related issues, see [Kanamori, Arguably the most famous formally unsolvable 1994]. problem of mathematics is Hilbert’s first prob- The independence of a proposition φ from the axioms of set theory is the arithmetic statement: lem: ZFC does not prove φ, and ZFC does not prove φ. ¬ Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis: Suppose that Of course, if ZFC is inconsistent, then ZFC proves X R is an uncountable set. Then there exists a bi- anything, so independence can be established only ⊆ jection π : X R. by assuming at the very least that ZFC is consis- → tent. Sometimes, as we shall see, even stronger as- This problem belongs to an ever-increasing list sumptions are necessary. of problems known to be unsolvable from the The first result concerning the Continuum (usual) axioms of set theory. Hypothesis, CH, was obtained by Gödel. However, some of these problems have now Theorem (Gödel). Assume ZFC is consistent. Then been solved. But what does this actually mean? so is ZFC + CH. Could the Continuum Hypothesis be similarly solved? These questions are the subject of this ar- The modern era of set theory began with Cohen’s ticle, and the discussion will involve ingredients discovery of the method of forcing and his appli- from many of the current areas of set theoretical cation of this new method to show: investigation. Most notably, both Large Cardinal Theorem (Cohen). Assume ZFC is consistent. Then Axioms and Determinacy Axioms play central roles.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 4 Induction and Recursion 4.1 Induction: An informal introduction This section is intended as a somewhat informal introduction to The Principle of Mathematical Induction (PMI): a theorem that establishes the validity of the proof method which goes by the same name. There is a particular format for writing the proofs which makes it clear that PMI is being used. We will not explicitly use this format when introducing the method, but will do so for the large number of different examples given later. Suppose you are given a large supply of L-shaped tiles as shown on the left of the figure below. The question you are asked to answer is whether these tiles can be used to exactly cover the squares of an 2n × 2n punctured grid { a 2n × 2n grid that has had one square cut out { say the 8 × 8 example shown in the right of the figure. 1 2 CHAPTER 4. INDUCTION AND RECURSION In order for this to be possible at all, the number of squares in the punctured grid has to be a multiple of three. By direct calculation we can see that it is true when n = 1; 2 or 3, and these are the cases we're interested in here. It turns out to be true in general; this is easy to show using congruences, which we will study later, and also can be shown using methods in this chapter. But that does not mean we can tile the punctured grid. In order to get some traction on what to do, let's try some small examples.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 7. Induction and Recursion
    Chapter 7. Induction and Recursion Part 1. Mathematical Induction The principle of mathematical induction is this: to establish an infinite sequence of propositions P1,P2,P3,...,Pn,... (or, simply put, Pn (n 1)), it is enough to verify the following two things ≥ (1) P1, and (2) Pk Pk ; (that is, assuming Pk vaild, we can rpove the validity of Pk ). ⇒ + 1 + 1 These two things will give a “domino effect” for the validity of all Pn (n 1). Indeed, ≥ step (1) tells us that P1 is true. Applying (2) to the case n = 1, we know that P2 is true. Knowing that P2 is true and applying (2) to the case n = 2 we know that P3 is true. Continue in this manner, we see that P4 is true, P5 is true, etc. This argument can go on and on. Now you should be convinced that Pn is true, no matter how big is n. We give some examples to show how this induction principle works. Example 1. Use mathematical induction to show 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2n 1) = n2. ··· − (Remember: in mathematics, “show” means “prove”.) Answer: For n = 1, the identity becomes 1 = 12, which is obviously true. Now assume the validity of the identity for n = k: 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2k 1) = k2. ··· − For n = k + 1, the left hand side of the identity is 1 + 3 + 5 + + (2k 1) + (2(k + 1) 1) = k2 + (2k + 1) = (k + 1)2 ··· − − which is the right hand side for n = k + 1. The proof is complete. 1 Example 2. Use mathematical induction to show the following formula for a geometric series: 1 xn+ 1 1 + x + x2 + + xn = − .
    [Show full text]
  • 3 Mathematical Induction
    Hardegree, Metalogic, Mathematical Induction page 1 of 27 3 Mathematical Induction 1. Introduction.......................................................................................................................................2 2. Explicit Definitions ..........................................................................................................................2 3. Inductive Definitions ........................................................................................................................3 4. An Aside on Terminology.................................................................................................................3 5. Induction in Arithmetic .....................................................................................................................3 6. Inductive Proofs in Arithmetic..........................................................................................................4 7. Inductive Proofs in Meta-Logic ........................................................................................................5 8. Expanded Induction in Arithmetic.....................................................................................................7 9. Expanded Induction in Meta-Logic...................................................................................................8 10. How Induction Captures ‘Nothing Else’...........................................................................................9 11. Exercises For Chapter 3 .................................................................................................................11
    [Show full text]
  • THE PEANO AXIOMS 1. Introduction We Begin Our Exploration
    CHAPTER 1: THE PEANO AXIOMS MATH 378, CSUSM. SPRING 2015. 1. Introduction We begin our exploration of number systems with the most basic number system: the natural numbers N. Informally, natural numbers are just the or- dinary whole numbers 0; 1; 2;::: starting with 0 and continuing indefinitely.1 For a formal description, see the axiom system presented in the next section. Throughout your life you have acquired a substantial amount of knowl- edge about these numbers, but do you know the reasons behind your knowl- edge? Why is addition commutative? Why is multiplication associative? Why does the distributive law hold? Why is it that when you count a finite set you get the same answer regardless of the order in which you count the elements? In this and following chapters we will systematically prove basic facts about the natural numbers in an effort to answer these kinds of ques- tions. Sometimes we will encounter more than one answer, each yielding its own insights. You might see an informal explanation and then a for- mal explanation, or perhaps you will see more than one formal explanation. For instance, there will be a proof for the commutative law of addition in Chapter 1 using induction, and then a more insightful proof in Chapter 2 involving the counting of finite sets. We will use the axiomatic method where we start with a few axioms and build up the theory of the number systems by proving that each new result follows from earlier results. In the first few chapters of these notes there will be a strong temptation to use unproved facts about arithmetic and numbers that are so familiar to us that they are practically part of our mental DNA.
    [Show full text]
  • Elementary Higher Topos and Natural Number Objects
    Elementary Higher Topos and Natural Number Objects Nima Rasekh 10/16/2018 The goal of the talk is to look at some ongoing work about logical phenom- ena in the world of spaces. Because I am assuming the room has a topology background I will therefore first say something about the logical background and then move towards topology. 1. Set Theory and Elementary Toposes 2. Natural Number Objects and Induction 3. Elementary Higher Topos 4. Natural Number Objects in an Elementary Higher Topos 5. Where do we go from here? Set Theory and Elementary Toposes A lot of mathematics is built on the language of set theory. A common way to define a set theory is via ZFC axiomatization. It is a list of axioms that we commonly associate with sets. Here are two examples: 1. Axiom of Extensionality: S = T if z 2 S , z 2 T . 2. Axiom of Union: If S and T are two sets then there is a set S [T which is characterized as having the elements of S and T . This approach to set theory was developed early 20th century and using sets we can then define groups, rings and other mathematical structures. Later the language of category theory was developed which motivates us to study categories in which the objects behave like sets. Concretely we can translate the set theoretical conditions into the language of category theory. For example we can translate the conditions above as follows: 1 1. Axiom of Extensionality: The category has a final object 1 and it is a generator.
    [Show full text]
  • Prof. V. Raghavendra, IIT Tirupati, Delivered a Talk on 'Peano Axioms'
    Prof. V. Raghavendra, IIT Tirupati, delivered a talk on ‘Peano Axioms’ on Sep 14, 2017 at BITS-Pilani, Hyderabad Campus Abstract The Peano axioms define the arithmetical properties of natural numbers and provides rigorous foundation for the natural numbers. In particular, the Peano axioms enable an infinite set to be generated by a finite set of symbols and rules. In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are a set of axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly unchanged in a number of metamathematical investigations, including research into fundamental questions of whether number theory is consistent and complete. The need to formalize arithmetic was not well appreciated until the work of Hermann Grassmann, who showed in the 1860s that many facts in arithmetic could be derived from more basic facts about the successor operation and induction.[1] In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided an axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic.[2] In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a more precisely formulated version of them as a collection of axioms in his book, The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method (Latin: Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita). The Peano axioms contain three types of statements. The first axiom asserts the existence of at least one member of the set of natural numbers. The next four are general statements about equality; in modern treatments these are often not taken as part of the Peano axioms, but rather as axioms of the "underlying logic".[3] The next three axioms are first- order statements about natural numbers expressing the fundamental properties of the successor operation.
    [Show full text]
  • CONSTRUCTION of NUMBER SYSTEMS 1. Peano's Axioms And
    CONSTRUCTION OF NUMBER SYSTEMS N. MOHAN KUMAR 1. Peano's Axioms and Natural Numbers We start with the axioms of Peano. Peano's Axioms. N is a set with the following properties. (1) N has a distinguished element which we call `1'. (2) There exists a distinguished set map σ : N ! N. (3) σ is one-to-one (injective). (4) There does not exist an element n 2 N such that σ(n) = 1. (So, in particular σ is not surjective). (5) (Principle of Induction) Let S ⊂ N such that a) 1 2 S and b) if n 2 S, then σ(n) 2 S. Then S = N. We call such a set N to be the set of natural numbers and elements of this set to be natural numbers. Lemma 1.1. If n 2 N and n 6= 1, then there exists m 2 N such that σ(m) = n. Proof. Consider the subset S of N defined as, S = fn 2 N j n = 1 or n = σ(m); for some m 2 Ng: By definition, 1 2 S. If n 2 S, clearly σ(n) 2 S, again by definition of S. Thus by the Principle of Induction, we see that S = N. This proves the lemma. We define the operation of addition (denoted by +) by the following two recursive rules. (1) For all n 2 N, n + 1 = σ(n). (2) For any n; m 2 N, n + σ(m) = σ(n + m). Notice that by lemma 1.1, any natural number is either 1 or of the form σ(m) for some m 2 N and thus the defintion of addition above does define it for any two natural numbers n; m.
    [Show full text]