<<

ROBERT E. HALL MassachusettsInstitute of Technology

Investment, Rates, and the Efects of Stabilization olicies

THE RESPONSE of investmentexpenditure to changesin interestrates is at the heartof any analysisof stabilizationpolicy. The more sensitivethe response,the more potent is monetarypolicy and the weakeris fiscal ex- penditurepolicy. The stimulusof lowerinterest rates on investmentis one of the principalchannels of monetaryinfluence in virtuallyall macroeco- nomictheories. On the otherhand, the negativeinfluence of higherinterest rates on investmentmay inhibitthe macroeconomiceffect of expenditure policy. The net effect of governmentexpenditures on gross national producthas been and remainsthe single most importantsource of dis- agreementover stabilizationpolicy among .My purposehere is to examinethe empiricalevidence on the interestresponse of investment withthe hope of narrowingthe disagreementabout the effectsof expendi- ture and monetarypolicies. Thoughthe evidenceis disappointinglyweak, it does suggestthat the modem Keynesianview embodiedin large-scale macroeconometricmodels-that the expendituremultiplier is around1.5 -and the simple monetaristview-that it is essentiallyzero-are both incorrect.The most reasonablevalue lies in the middle, perhapsat 0.7. Unfortunately,the evidenceis probablynot strongenough to convincethe firmadherent of the othertwo positions. Note: This research was supported by the National Science Foundation. I am grateful to Dale W. Jorgenson and members of the Brookings panel for helpful comments. 61 62 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977

The EmpiricalIssues

The interestresponse of investmentdepends fundamentally on the sub- stitutabilityof for other factors, and there seems to be general agreementtoday that factor substitutioncan take place. In fact, the uni- tary-elasticityproperty of the Cobb-Douglasproduction function is not a bad summaryof the findinigsof more generalstudies: a decline of 1 per- cent in the serviceprice of capitalraises the capital-outputratio by about 1 percent.But this is a -runrelationship, and it is muchless generally agreedthat the flow that bringsabout the changein the capitalintensity- extra investment-is highly responsiveto changesin the of capital over the one- to three-yearhorizon of chief concern in stabilization. Skeptics about the interest of investmentpoint to three con- siderationsthat cause the adjustmentin factor intensitiesto take place slowly: 1. Lags in putting capital in place. It can take at least a year to design,order, build, and install capital equipment after a changein relative factorprices makes new equipmentdesirable. 2. The putty-clay hypothesis. Capital already in place cannot be adaptedto a differentcapital intensity; factor proportions are fixed at the time the equipmentis designed.Changes in factor intensitiesdictated by changesin the priceof capitaltake place only as the old capitalis replaced. 3. The term structure of interest rates. Stabilization policies affect the -terminterest rate, but investmentresponds to the long-termrate. Longrates respond to shortrates with an importantlag. Evidencefrom a varietyof sources,discussed below, seemsto converge on the pointthat lags in the investmentprocess are long enoughto limit the immediateeffect of changesin the serviceprice of capitalon investment. The investmenttaking place in a given year is largelythe consequenceof irrevocabledecisions made in earlieryears, and only a small fractioncan be affectedby changesin that yearin the financialattractiveness of invest- ment.This considerationmakes expenditure policy strongerand weaker than they would be in an with more flexibility aboutinvestment in the shortrun. Evidence on the putty-clayhypothesis is much more ambiguous.The paper containsa theoreticalexposition of the hypothesisthat emphasizes the centralissue with respectto its implicationsfor investmentbehavior: Robert E. Hall 63 Underputty-clay, firms do not face an economicdecision about how much output to produceon their existingcapital equipment.If there is such a decision-for example, if more output can be squeezed out of existing equipmentby operatingit for longerhours or addingmore labor in other ways-then the putty-clayhypothesis in its strict form is wrong and the response of investmentto the price of capital is not just the change in the factor intensity of newly installed capacity but involves substitutionbetween new and old capitalas well. The paperdemonstrates a seriousproblem in the majorexisting attempt to measurethe influence of the putty-clayphenomenon in the investmentequation. No definite conclusionemerges about the importanceof putty-clay. The questionof the properinterest rate for an investmentequation is tackled only at the theoreticallevel. The simple argumentthat capital is long-livedand that consequentlythe investmentdecision should be based on the long-terminterest rate is examinedand confirmed, but this principle does not imply that the serviceprice of capitaldepends on the long rate. Rather,the serviceprice emergesfrom a comparisonof investmentdeci- sions madethis yearon the basisof this year'slong rate, andthose thatwill be made next year on the basis of next year'slong rate. This comparison involves the expectedchange in the long rate, which is measuredby the currentshort rate. As a matterof theory,it seems quiteunambiguous that an investmenttheory built aroundthe conceptof a serviceprice of capital shoulduse the shortrate. The prospectfor empiricalconfirmation of this principleseems slight, in view of the major difficultiesassociated with measurementof the role of interestrates of anykind.

An EmpiricalIS-LM Framework

Generationsof economists have been taught to study the effects of monetaryand within Hicks' IS-LM framework.In the dia- grambelow the IS curve traces the combinationsof the interestrate and real grossnational product that are consistentwith the expenditureside of the economy.Higher interest rates are associatedwith lower levels of GNP becauseof the negativeresponse of investment.The LM curve describes the alternativeinterest rates and levels of GNP that clear the .Higher levels of GNP requirehigher interestrates to clear the marketfor a given exogenousquantity of money. Increasedgovernment 64 BrookingsPapers onzEconomic Activity, 1:1977 expendituresshift the IS curveto the right,say to IS'. Real GNP rises from Y to Y'. The magnitudeof the increasedepends on the relativeslopes of the two curves:it is largeif the LM curveis flat and the IS curveis steep and small in the oppositecase. An increasedmoney supplyshifts the LM curveto the right,say to LM". Again, the effect on GNP dependson the relativeslopes of the two curves:monetary policy is potentif the IS curve is flatand the LM curveis steep. The centralquestion of this papercan be statedsuccinctly in the IS-LM framework:how flatis the IS curverelative to the LM curve?An algebraic developmentof the IS-LM model is a necessaryprelude to an empirical study.Start with a simpleconsumption function: C - o + 61Y, LM LM LM"?

_~~~~_ / ~ ~~~~~

is, f t I 5

y yP ytt ~~~RealGNP where C is in real terms and Y is real GNP, and thus 0, is the marginal propensity to consume out of GNP. Next is the investment function,

I I+ eY Y-72y; where I is real investmermtand r is the interestrate; GyN measures the ac- celeratoreffect of output on investmentand y2 is the crucialinterest re- Robert E. flail 65 sponse. The expenditureside of the economy is governedas well by the GNP identity, Y = C + I + GI where G is real governmentexpenditures. The IS curve is obtained by solvingthe threeequations for r as a functionof Y:

r do + yo + G -(I - 01 - 1) Y 72 The finalequation is the money-demandfunction,

M/p =-1'o + '1 Y - VI2r, whereM is the nominalmoney supply and p is the ; 'P.is the incomeresponse of moneydemand and 2 iS the interestresponse. The LM curveis just the money-demandfunction solved for r:

r- 0 + AY - M/p 'P2 The intersectionof the IS andLM curvesis obtainedby equatingthem and solvingfor Y: Y =o + I, G + g2 M/p, wherepu, is the effectof expenditureson GNP: 1 1-01 - 7Yl + IP (72/P2)'

Note the crucialrole of the ratio of the two slope parameters,y2/'2. If the IS curveis steep and the LM curveis flat, y2/'2 is small and t,u is close to the simple Keynesian , 1/(1 - 0, - Yl). With a flat IS and a steep LM curve, 72/2 will be large, ,t will be small, and the interest-rate effectwill largelyoffset the simplemultiplier effect. The influenceof the realmoney supply is describedby2:

rU=4 l + (- 01 - 7') (VP2/72)-

Again, the ratio of the slope parameters,'P2/Y2, plays a centralrole, now in reciprocalform. If the IS curve is steep and the LM curveis flat, 'P2/y2 is largeand pt2is small. With a flat IS and a steep LM curve, the effect of monetaryexpansion on GNP will be close to the extremevalue of the crudequantity theory, 1/'P,. How relevantis such a simplemodel to stabilizationpolicy in the mod- 66 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 em U.S. economy?In the firstplace, it takesthe real moneysupply, M/p, as predeterminedby monetarypolicy. Unless the monetaryauthorities offset every movementin , exogeneity of M/p is realistic only if pricesare takenas predetermined-thatis, if the pricelevel does not react to developmentsin the economy within the period.1This paper is con- cerned with the effect of stabilizationpolicy only for the first year after policy actionsare taken.A good deal of recentresearch on price determi- nation seems to supportunresponsive prices as a reasonableapproxima- tion, thoughthere are some important dissenters. The responsivenessof pricesto stabilizationpolicy over a longerhori- zon influencesthe resultseven when the analysisconcerns only the initial year after a policy action. Investmentdepends on the real interestrate while moneydemand depends on the nominalinterest rate, and the differ- ence betweenthem is the expectedrate of inflationfrom one year to the next. The assumptionof unresponsiveexpectations about the rateof infla- tion could be justifiedeither as an extensionof the rigid-pricehypothesis to the secondyear or as a failureof rationalexpectations. Experimentswith a more elaboratemodel that permitsa good deal of priceflexibility in the firstyear and even morein the secondsuggested that the rigid-pricecase enhancesthe stimulusof monetarypolicy by a con- siderablemargin and slightlydiminishes the effectof expenditurepolicy.2 Since the firmestbelievers in the efficacyof expenditurepolicies generally also considerprices rigid or deny rationalexpectations, it seems best to proceedon the hypothesisof unresponsiveprices. The simplemodel also omitsany influence of interestrates on consump- tion, either directly or through the effects of wealth on consumption. Though the evidence seems to supportthe life-cycle permanent-income hypothesis,in which consumptiondepends entirely on a comprehensive measureof wealth,3there is little evidenceabout the influenceof interest rateson thatmeasure of wealth.The short-runcorrelation of interestrates, the stockmarket, and consumptionmay not identifythe structuralrelation

1. Of course, prices this year react to events in earlier years, so prices vary over time. Predetermineddoes not mean fixed over time. 2. The model with appears in Robert E. Hall, "The Macro- economic Impact of Changes in Income in the Short and Medium Runs," Journal of , special issue, forthcoming. 3. See Robert E. Hall, "The Life Cycle-PermanentIncome Hypothesis and the Role of Consumption in Aggregate Economic Activity" (Massachusetts Institute of Technology, January 1977; processed). Robert E. Hall 67 amongthem becausethey all reactstrongly to othereconomic events and influences.4In any case, zero interest-elasticityof consumptionis an ap- propriateassumption for this paperbecause any suchresponse would only make the IS curveflatter and expenditurepolicy even less effective. The model also assumes a closed economy, or more precisely, that importsand exportsdo not respondwithin a yearto changesin GNP and interest rates. Adding import and export equations sensitive to GNP would changethe Keynesianmultiplier only slightly,and thus would only slightly alterthe estimatesof the policy effects, y1 and . The omission of interestrates from the net demandfor foreigngoods is more serious- even the directionoi this effect,let aloneits magnitude,is unsettledtoday.

PARAMETER ESTIMATES Most of the paperwill concernthe numericalvalues of the parameters of the investmentequation. Their implicationswill be studied againsta particularset of values of the parametersof the other equationsof the simple IS-LM model. The appendixdiscusses the sourcesfor these esti- mated parametervalues. Briefly, the marginalpropensity to consume (MPC) out of GNP, 01, is taken as 0.36, which includesthe accelerator effects on consumerdurables as well as the conventionalMPC for non- durablesand services. There are good reasonsto thinkthat 0.36 overstates the true structuralresponse of consumptionto the transitorychanges in income broughtabout by variousstabilization policies.5 As the formulas for 1qand Ic2show, the upwardbias in 0 will resultin an upwardbias in the responseof GNP both to expendituresand to money,but in the lightof the valuesof the otherparameters, the bias turnsout to be quitesmall. The criticalparameters of the model apartfrom those of the investment equationare the effectof income on money demand,+, and the effectof the interestrate on money demand,q2. From the somewhatmixed evi- dence discussedin the appendix,I settled on the following compromise estimatesof the two parameters: -increase in real money demandassociated with an increaseof $1 billionin real GNP $0.135 billion; 4. See the discussion of Frederic Mishkin's paper, "What Depressed the Con- sumer? The Household and the 1973-75 ," in this issue. 5. See Hall, "Life Cycle-PermanentIncome Hypothesis." 68 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977

= decreasein real money demand associatedwith an increase of 100 basispoints in the short-terminterest rate

- $2.0 billionl. Finally,a previewof the conclusionsof the rest of the paperis needed to fill in the remainingparameters of the IS curve.Begin with the capital- demandfunction implied by the Cobb-Douglasproduction function, as derivedby Dale W. Jorgenson:6 a Y = K* Kvs I whereK* is the demandfor capitalor desiredcapital , Y is real GNP, v is the real serviceprice of capital,and a is the elasticityof the produc- tion functionwith respect to capital.At 1977 levels, real GNP is about $1,325 billion and the real service price is $0.23 per $1 of capital per year (assumingdepreciation of 10 percent a year). The income share of capitalis the usual estimateof a and is 0.31. Then, underthe extreme assumptionof full adjustmentof actual capital to desiredcapital within a year after a policy is implemented,the parametersof the investment functionare

y, = accelerator effect, -K = $1.36 billion of investmentper $1 billion of GNP; av = interest-rate effect - 72 O,(9vOr = $83.8 billion per 100 basis points. In the second calculation,I have assumedthat the real service price of capitalchanges point for point with the interestrate (Ov/Or= 1), which is a close approximation. Table 1 presentsthe derivedvalues of the policy effects under these parametervalues. The first row maintainsthe strong (and surely incor- rect) assumptionof full adjustmentof capital in the first year. In this economy the crude quantitytheory holds quite closely. An increase in governmentexpenditures of $1 billion raises GNP by only $0.2 billion; 6. The initial statement of Jorgenson'stheory was made in "CapitalTheory and Investment Behavior,", vol. 53 (May 1963), pp. 247- 59. For a complete bibliography of his later work with many collaborators, see his "Econometric Studies of Investment Behavior: A Survey," Journal of Economic Literature,vol. 9 (December 1971), pp. 1111-47. Robert E. Hall 69 Table 1. Effects on Real GNP of Monetary and ExpenditurePolicies under AlternativeAssumptioIIs of First-Year Response of Investment Billions of dollars Effect of increase of $1 billionin Effect of increase real government of $1 billionin Assumptionabout the investment expenditures real moneysupply responsein thefirst year ,5 A2 Full responseto both output and interestrate 0.2 8.5 One-fourthof both responses 0.6 6.1 One-halfof output responseand one-eighthof interest-rateresponse 1.4 7.8 One-eighthof both responses 0.8 4.4 Sources: Derived from IS-LM model using parameter values developed in the appendix and further explained in the text.

the Keynesianmultiplier effect is almost entirelyoffset by higherinterest rates and consequentlylower investment.Monetary policy is correspond- ingly potent: a $1 billion increasein the money supplydepresses interest ratesand stimulatesinvestment sufficiently that GNP risesby $8.5 billion. The evidenceon lags in the investmentprocess shows that neitherthe strongaccelerator effect nor the stronginterest-rate effect of the firstrow describesthe modernAmerican economy. Rather, only a fractionof both responsescan take place within a year. Jorgenson'sinvestment function recognizesthis lag, and the secondrow embodieshis conclusionthat both responsesare limitedin the firstyear to aboutone-quarter of the full long- run amount predictedby the capital-demandfunction. The interesting featureof this case is the continuinglow of the effect of an expen- diturepolicy: $1 billion in expendituresraises GNP by only $0.6 billion. The inhibitingnegative from higher interestrates to lower in- vestmentis still substantialeven whenconsiderable sluggishness of invest- ment is recognized.Monetary policy remainsstrong: its impact on real GNP is nearlythree-fourths as large as that in the firstrow, even though the direct stimulativeeffects of lower interest rates are now only one- quarteras large.The paradoxemerges because the sluggishnessof invest- mentresults in less "crowdingout" as well as in less stimulation.At the end of the paper, I will argue that the empiricalevidence is fully com- patiblewith the economyof the secondrow. Note the strongdisagreement with the conventionalview that $1 billion of expenditureraises GNP by about$1.5 billionin the firstyear. 70 Brcookin-gsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 The third row of table 1 considersthe implicationsof the putty-clay model, in which the outputresponse takes place much more quicklythan the interest-rateresponse. The implied effect of an expenditurepolicy is quite conventional:$1.4 billion in GNP per $1 billion of expenditure. This follows from the high value of the acceleratoreffect and the low value of the inhibitinginterest-rate effect. But monetarypolicy is also extremelypotent with the putty-clayinvestment function: the effect of a monetaryexpansion of $1 billion is to raise GNP by $7.8 billion, only slightlyless than the $8.5 billion implied by the full-adjustmentcase in the firstrow. This implicationmay cause some believersin the putty-clay hypothesisto reconsider.It turnsout that the IS curve for row 3 is posi- tively sloped. Recall that the slope of the IS curve is (1 - 0O - 71) /72; the MPC, 01, is 0.36 and the acceleratorcoefficient, /i, is 0.68 (one-half of the extreme1.36 noted above). Then the marginalpropensity to spend, 01 + Yl, is 1.04, so the pure Keynesianexpenditure process is unstable and the expendituremultiplier is effectively infinite. The interest-rate feedbackmakes the IS-LM model stable but the shape of the IS curve implieshigh sensitivityof GNP to monetarypolicy. Most economists,in- cludingthis writer,will probablyreject the possibilitythat the marginal propensityto spend exceeds one, but this implies rejectionof the quick responseof investmentto outputassociated with rows 1 and3. The last row of table 1 shows the implicationsof an even more slug- gish investmentfunction, in which only one-eighthof the long-runre- sponse occursin the firstyear. As I interpretthe empiricalfindings from JamesTobin's "q theory"of investmentbelow, this functionis consistent with them. Longerlags make expenditurepolicy strongerand monetary policy weaker,but it is still strikingthat the effect of a $1 billion expendi- ture on GNP, $0.8 billion, is little more than half its conventionalvalue of $1.5 billion, and monetarypolicy remainsan extremelypotent tool for stabilizationeven when investmentis this unresponsiveto interestrates. The rest of the paperinvestigates the evidencethat mightenable one to choose one of the four cases of table 1 as the closest descriptionof the U.S. economy.It beginswith a restatementof investmenttheory in a form amenableto discussingthe variouscompeting hypotheses, especially putty- clay. Afterbriefly surveying the evidenceon long-runfactor substitution, it turnsto the first majorempirical issue, the nature of the distributedlag in the investmentfunction. This part includes an investigationof the q theoryas an alternativeway to look at lags in investment.A discussion Robert E. Hall 71 of the putty-clayhypothesis follows. The commonsensecase for and againstputty-clay is discussed,and the limitationson empiricaltesting of the hypothesismentioned. A detailedreview of CharlesBischoff's invest- ment functionis presented.The generalconclusion is that the evidence favorsthe secondcase of table 1, but it is not overwhelmingand the deter- minedbeliever may understandably remain unswayed. But only exception- ally strongaccelerator effects seem to justifyconventional views aboutthe strengthof expenditurepolicy as a stabilizationtool.

A Restatementof InvestmentTheory

The usualtextbook exposition of the theoryof investmenthas lookingdeeply into the futureand equatingthe presentvalue of the future marginalproduct of capitalto its acquisitioncost today. By contrast,in the neoclassicalinvestment function pioneered by Jorgenson,which forms the basis of most recent empiricalwork, investorsneed look ahead only one periodand equatethe currentmarginal product of capitalto its service cost. The relationbetween the two versions of the theory is a matterof some confusion.In particular,Jorgenson's celebrated formula for the ser- vice cost of capitalas a functionof the acquisitioncost, the depreciation rate, and the interestrate is often thoughtto requirea long-term interest rate because capital is a long-livedasset. I will arguethat this reflectsa misunderstandingof the role of the interestrate in the formula.Further, Jorgenson'sformula is frequentlyattacked as a very special case that de- pends on the existenceof marketsfor second-handcapital goods, which again seems to be a misunderstanding.Finally, the literatureon invest- ment theoryreflects a greatdeal of confusionwith respectto assumptions aboutthe competitivenessof outputmarkets. In his originaldevelopment of the neoclassicaltheory, Jorgenson set up the problemas one of maxi- mizingthe presentvalue of the firm subjectto a fixed outputprice. This assumptionhas been attackedfor its unrealism,7but in fact the theorycan be restatedwithout it. The centralassumption is only that firmsproduce at minimumcost.

7. For example, Dennis Anderson, "Models for Determining Least-Cost Invest- ments in Electricity Supply," Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, vol. 3 (Spring 1972), pp. 267-99. 72 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 The restatementmakes use of the followingnotation: rt = nominalinterest rate Rs t = presentvalue in period t of one dollar receivedin 1 1 1 period s: R,,, 1+r=I1+r, * +re+i P = price of one unit of capital equipment Ks = numberof units of new capitalinstalled in periods Q= total outputto be producedin periods C8(Q,,,Ko,..,K8) = variable costs of producing in period s, given capital installedin this and earlieryears M =, = marginalvalue in periods of investmentin periodt: M8, t -OC-/dKi. Total cost is just the presentdiscounted value of futurecosts, including the acquisitioncost of capital,

co E R8,t[C8(Q8,Ko,. .,K8) + p8K.]. a-t The first-orderconditions for a minimumwith respect to investmentin period t is

00 (1) ,~~~~~~Rs,tM8, t Pt, -*t exactly the textbookequality of the presentvalue of the future earnings of today'sinvestment, M8,t, and the currentacquisition cost of capital,pt. Before makinguse of this versionof the cost-minimizingcondition, the firmmust formexpectations about the contributionof today'sinvestment to reducingcost in the future.In most cases, there is a stronginteraction betweenthe productivityof this year'sinvestment in futureyears with the productivityof investmentmade in other years. This implies that the equalityof the presentvalue of the productivityto the acquisitioncost is not by itself enough to determinethis period's cost-minimizinglevel of investment;the implicationsof futureinvestment must be kept in mind in evaluatingtoday's investment.In general,complete investmentplans for the futuremust be formulatedat the same time that currentplans are made. If the interactionamong vintages of capitalis sufficientlystrong, how- ever, there is an importantexception to this rule which gives rise to Jor- genson'srental formula and the investmentprincipal of equatingtoday's Robert E. Hall 73 marginalproduct of capitalto today'srental price. Consider the first-order conditionfor nextperiod's capital,

co E Rs, tM, t+1 =R t+, tpt1 8=t+I p t+1

The problemis to relateM^,, to M,t +,. Jorgensonmakes the assumption that they have a fixed relationattributable to depreciationbut otherwise unresponsiveto factorintensities or othereconomic considerations:

Me = Ms,t+1/(l+3). Here 8 is the proportionalloss in efficiencyper period on accountof de- preciation.This assumptionmakes it possible to restate the first-order conditionfor nextperiod's capital as

0o p t+ (2) e2+ Rs, XM t = rl Now considerthe benefitsand costs associatedwith investingone unit of capital today instead of 1/(1 + 8) units next period. The benefits are measuredby the differencebetween the benefitsof the investmentin period 1, the left-handside of equation 1, and the benefitsof the investmentin period t + 1, the left-hand side of equation 2. Very conveniently,the differenceis just the currentmarginal benefit of capital, M,,t. The costs aremeasured by the differencebetween the right-handside of equations1 and2:

Pt+? P' (l +r,) (l1+6)' This is the serviceor rentalcost of capitalas derivedby Jorgenson-"Then thefirst-order conditions for currentinvestment can be statedas

P t+i Mtt =-Pt -(+rt) (1+6)' whichinvolves no deeplook into the future. The derivationof this form of the investmentcriterion makes it clear thatthe serviceprice of capitaldepends on the short-run interestrate. The

8. Jorgenson derived his formula in continuous time as p(r + 8) - dp/dt and then used the discrete version, pt(rt + 8) - (Pt+l - Pt), which is a close approxima- tion to the formula given here. 74 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 interestrate entersthe formulathrough the comparisonof the streamof futurereturns from an investmentmade today with the streamfrom an investmentpostponed one period.The separateevaluation of each stream involves the long-runinterest rate, but the comparisondoes not. In Jor- genson'sframework, are decidingwhen to schedulean invest- ment,and this decisiondepends on the short-runinterest rate. This derivationof Jorgenson'sformula also makes it clear that the dependenceon the short-runinterest rate and the short-runchange in the priceof capitalgoods does not rest on any assumptionthat investmentcan be or is undertakenfor the shortrun alone. Firmsneed not be viewed as buyingcapital in one periodand sellingit on a second-handmarket in the next period.The theorydoes not requirethe existenceof a second-hand market,nor does the lack of such a marketcall into questionthe conclu- sion that the short-runinterest rate and the rate of inflationin prices of capitalgoods belong in the formulafor the serviceprice. As long as the firmfaces an open choice aboutthe schedulingof investment,the formula holds.9 The major limiting feature of Jorgenson's theory is its implicit assump- tion that the relation between the productivityof differentvintages of capital is technologicallypredetermined. In particular,this assumption rulesout the "putty-clay"hypothesis, in whichdifferent vintages of capital are physically distinct and embody alternativefactor intensities deter- mined at the time of installation.Although the generalrule remainsvalid that investmentshould be pushed to the point of equalityof the present value of the futuremarginal value of the capitalto its acquisitioncost, as a matterof theorythis rule cannotbe transformedinto a simple relation between the currentmarginal value and a predeterminedrental cost of capital.'0 An empiricalinvestment function not based on Jorgenson'scrucial simplifyingassumption appears hopelessly complex, so it is useful to in-

9. Thus, the formula does require that the firm plans to make some investment in both periods. Positive gross investment is an important assumption of the theory. It invariably holds in the aggregate, but this may conceal a fraction of firms who are at the corner solution of zero gross investment. These firms will not respond to small changes in the short-runinterest rate. 10. There is always a rental price for which this simple relation is true, but in the general putty-clay case it will not be a predeterminedfunction of prices and interest rates. It can be derived only by solving the complete simultaneousproblem of deter- mining optimal present and future investment. Robert E. Hall 75 quirehow well his formulamight approximate a technologyin which the assumptiondoes not hold literally.Recall that the problemis to achieve

Rt,tMt,t + Rt+i tMj+i t + .. . = pt, but that Mt+?,tand the otherfuture marginal values of capitaldepend on futureinvestment. Again, it is known at time t that investmentdecisions in t + 1 will planto achieve

RtE+,tMt+? t+1 + Rt+2, tM+2,1+1+ .++

Two considerationsmake Mt+,,t+,differ from Mt+,,tin terms of expecta- tions formed at time t: depreciationand obsolescence.As long as these are expectedto occur at constantproportional rates in the future,follow- ing Jorgenson,a parameter,3, easily takes them into account.Otherwise, it is hardto think of realisticconsiderations that would lead to important discrepanciesbetween the marginalvalues of presentand futurevintages of capitalin the same futureyear. If it were known,for example,that the relativeprice of laborwas goingto doublesuddenly five yearsfrom today, the marginalvalue of today's investmentin five years would be lower than a generaldepreciation formula would predict, and the more elab- orate simultaneousmodel would be required.But events like this are almostnever predictable; expectations for the futureare generallysmooth even thoughthe actualityturns out to have suddenchanges. As a practical matter,then, a model that assumesa simple predeterminedrelation be- tween the futuremarginal values of differentvintages seems a good guide for investment.In otherwords, Jorgenson's rental formula is a reasonable startingpoint for an investmenttheory even if his strong assumptionof highsubstitutability of vintagesex post is incorrect.

Long-RunSubstitutability of Capital

An early point of attack on Jorgenson'sinvestment function focused on his assumptionthat the underlyingdemand for capital is unit-elastic with respect to the service price of capital. When there is only a single factorother than capital-namely, labor-this amountsto assumingthat the elasticityof substitutionbetween capital and laboris unity, or that the productionfunction is Cobb-Douglas. was a leadingcritic 76 Rrnakinos Panprs on ECrnnomiC ACtivitfv 1:1977 of this aspect of Jorgenson'swork." Jorgensonreplied that a large body of researchon productionfunctions supportedthe assumptionof unit elasticity.'2The controversyebbed when CharlesBischoff presented evi- dence that the elasticityof substitutionat the time capital equipmentis designed and installedis indeed aroundone, but that capital and labor are less substitutableafter installation.'3Jorgenson has not defendedhis assumption of unit elasticity of substitution ex post against Bischoff's alter- native view, thoughthere is very substantialdifference between the two views in the short run.'4Bischoff's evidence is scrutinizedlater in this paper. The Eisner-Jorgensoncontroversy left the impressionamong many readersthat an unresolveddiscrepancy remained between time-series and cross-sectionevidence on the elasticityof substitution.Adherents of the putty-clayhypothesis had a readyexplanation for this finding,since cross- sectionsought to revealthe long-runproduction function ex ante and time series the short-runfunction ex post. However,a recent carefulstudy of the time-seriesevidence by Ernst Berndtl5 casts doubt on the existence of any discrepancyat all. By improvingthe measurementof all the relevant variables,especially the serviceprice of capital,Berndt obtains estimates of the elasticityof substitutionthat are aroundone. Errorsin variables, not putty-clay,may be the explanationof earlierfindings of low substitu- tion in time-seriesdata. Later in this paperrepeated emphasis is placed on the importanceof 11. " Policy and Investment Behavior: Comment," American Economic Review, vol. 59 (June 1969), pp. 379-88; and two papers with M. I. Nadiri, "Invest- ment Behavior and Neo-classical Theory," Review of Economics and , vol. 50 (August 1968), pp. 369-82, and "Neoclassical Theory of Investment Behavior: A Comment,"Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 52 (May 1970), pp. 216-22. 12. For example, in Dale W. Jorgenson, "InvestmentBehavior and the Produc- tion Function," Bell Journal of Economics and Management Science, vol. 3 (Spring 1972), pp. 220-51. 13. Charles W. Bischoff, "Hypothesis Testing and the Demand for Capital Goods," Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 51 (August 1969), pp. 354-68; and Bischoff, "The Effect of Alternative Lag Distributions," in Gary Fromm, ed., Tax Incentives and Capital Spending (, 1971), pp. 61-130. 14. The only mention of the subject in Jorgenson'ssurvey article in the Journal of Economic Literature is: "An important secondary problem is the time structure of financial determinantsof investment;Bischoff has suggested that real output and the cost of capital should have separate lag structuresin the determinationof invest- ment expenditures"("Econometric Studies of Investment Behavior,"p. 1142). 15. Ernst Berndt, "Reconciling Alternative Estimates of the Elasticity of Sub- stitution,"Review of Economics and Statistics, vol. 58 (February 1976), pp. 59-68. Robert E. Hall 77 econometricsimultaneity in obscuringthe true relationbetween capital and investmenton the one hand and theirdeterminants on the other. The joint determinationof currentinvestment and the currentservice price of capitalis an obstacleto measurementof the elasticityof substitutionfrom time series. The supply functionof capital slopes upward:both interest rates and the acquisitionprice of capitalrise if demandrises. As in every econometricstudy of demand,regression estimates of the elasticity of demandfor capitalwith respectto the serviceprice of capital are biased towardzero because of the competinginfluence of the supply function. Berndt attemptsto eliminatethis bias throughthe use of two-stageleast squares,but as usual thereis a seriousquestion about the true exogeneity of the instrumentalvariables. The directionof the bias is unambiguous,so Berndt'sevidence strengthens the case for a reasonablyhigh elasticityof substitutionbetween capital and labor. Today, few believersin the short-runinelasticity of investmentwith respect to interestrates and other determinantsof the service price of capital place much weight on the lack of substitutabilityof capital and laborin the long run.Rather, the case againstthe flat IS curverests on the three short-runconsiderations listed at the beginningof the paper: lags in the investmentprocess, limited factor substitutabilityex post, and the slow responseof long-terminterest rates to changes in short-termrates. The purposeof this brief considerationof the evidenceon long-runsub- stitutabilityis simply to guardagainst the revivalof the argumentabout limitedlong-run substitutability in view of the criticismsof the threepoints offeredhere.

DistributedLags in the InvestmentFunction

Virtuallyall econometricstudies of investmentmake use of a distributed lag betweenchanges in the determinantsof investmentand the actualin- vestmentitself. Throughouthis work, Jorgensonhas attributedthis lag to the time requiredto plan, build, and installnew capitalonce the need for it is apparent.Other investigatorshave attributedthe lag to the process by which expectationsof future needs for capital are formed. Until re- cently,the distinctionbetween the two sourcesof lags seemedunimportant, but new work on the structuralinterpretation of distributed-lagmech- anismsfor expectationshas suggestedthat the source of the lag matters 78 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 a great deal.16If policymakersintroduce an investmentcredit today, for example,there is no reasonfor thoughtfulinvestors to adjusttheir expecta- tions aboutthe futurecost of capital accordingto a distributedlag, even thoughthe distributedlag is a reasonablesummary of the predictivevalue of previouschanges in the cost of capitalwith respectto the futurecost. In contrast,there is no reasonto thinkthat the physicalprocess of invest- ment will take place at a differentspeed if the investmentis a responseto a tax credit ratherthan any other change in the demandfor capital. In other words, a distributed-lagexpectation mechanism is not a structural feature of the investmentequation, whereas the physical deliverylag is precisely a structuralfeature. Policy analysis is now seen to require a separationof lags relatedto expectationsfrom those of the physical in- vestmentprocess. Suppose,following Jorgenson, that the processof designing,ordering, and installingcapital can be describedby a fixed distributionof lags. Let /3i be the fractionof capital that can be installedin i quarters.Today's capital stock is thus a weightedaverage of targetsset in past quarterson the basisof informationavailable then:

i-o whereK, is actualcapital and K'* t is the targetfor quartert set in quarter t - i. Note that this hypothesisassumes that capital with short delivery lags cannotsubstitute for capitalwith longer deliverylags, else Kt could be equatedto K' t in each quarter.Next, supposethat thereis an observed variable,X,, with the propertythat the targetcapital stock set this quarter for some quarterin the futureis equal to the expectedvalue of X in the futurequarter:

= K*t-. E (Xt). t-i In Jorgenson'swork, X is the nominal value of output deflatedby the nominalservice cost of capital,but the principlediscussed here can apply to a varietyof alternativeformulations of the demandfor capital.

16. Robert E. Lucas, Jr., "EconometricPolicy Evaluation: A Critique,"in Karl fBrunnerand Allan H. Meltzer, eds., The and Labor Markets (Amster- dam: North-Holland, 1976; distributedin the and Canadaby American Elsevier), pp. 19-46. Lucas deals explicitly with the problems of naive expectations in the investment function in section 5.2. Robert E. Hall 79 Next, supposethat Xt obeys a stationarystochastic process,

xt = Xt + E 1PrUt-T.

Here, X, is a deterministictrend, ut - is a seriallyuncorrelated random variable,and the &, are lag, weights that describewhatever persistence there is in the movementof X, aroundits trend over time. The random innovations,u, cannot be forecast from their own past values, by hy- pothesis.Under the furtherassumption that no other variablesknown to investorsin quarterI - i have any bearingon the futurevalue of u,, the best forecastof u, made in quartert - i is zero. Thus the expectationof X0 formed in t -i is

E (Xe) = Xt + E PTUt-T.

Combiningthe physicaland expectational lags gives

K= E Pi E (Xt) i=O t-i

Xt + E 2i E 1'TUt-T 10 TX

~ti + "O i i0'pu t-0 whereBo is the fractionof all investmentthat requires0 or fewer quarters to complete:

0 i.=o The final relationshipbetween today's capital and earlier values of the innovation,u, has the followinginterpretation: The new informationthat became available in quarter t - 0, measured by ut-, is expected to affect the demand for capital in quarter t by fout,. However, only those com- ponentsof capital that can respondwithin 0 quarters,a fractionBO, are actuallyaffected by the information,so the totalcontribution is Bopou-o. 80 BrookingzsPaDers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 The derivationof the distributedlag betweenKt andX, is muchsimpli- fiedthrough the use of the lag operatornotation. Let

0-0co

_ E Bo'0L0. VjB(L) oo Thenthe processassumed for X, can be expressedas X = t + J(L)ut, andthe derivedprocess for capitalin thepresence of deliverylags is

Kt = Xt + iPP(L)ut. The impliedrelation between X, and K, is obtainedby eliminatingut by substitutingthe firstequation into the second:

= K-t Xt + VIP(xLt X- xt)* Thus the large body of econometricwork that has involved fittinga dis- tributedlag betweenKY and a variable(or compositeof variables),Xr, yields a certaincombination of the physical-lagcoefficients and the co- efficientsof the processfor formingexpectations. In general,the lag dis- tributioncannot be interpretedas reflectingthe physical lags alone. In this respect, Jorgenson'sdiscussion of lags in the investmentprocess is incomplete. Some idea of the biases involvedcan be gained throughexplicit solu- tion of the representativecase in whichthe distributionof deliverytimes is second-orderPascal, fl- =( 1 - p) 2is , andX, follows a first-orderauto- regressive process with serial correlation, /: ir = /t. Then the distributed lag is

Kt= x + ff(-Xfol whichis second-orderPascal with a declinerate equal to the product,pip, of the declinerate of the physicaldistributed lag, 8, and the serialcorrela- tion parameter, ,. The average lag is 23f/(1 - pt), which understates the averagephysical lags, 2A/(1 - fl), provided p is less than one. The casualimpression that the combinationof a physicallag and an expecta- tional lag would be longer than just the physical lag is mistaken.The Robert E. Hall 81 reason is revealedclearly in the case where X, is not seriallycorrelated at all (+ = 0). Then earlierfluctuations in Xt, are irrelevantfor predict- ing capitalneeds in quartert, and thereis no distributedlag at all. On the otherhand, thereis one importantcase in which the observeddistributed lag is exactlythe sameas the distributionof deliverytimes-namely, when the serial-correlationparameter, v,is one. Then Xt evolves as a random walk. The best predictor of X, - X, at time t - i is just Xt - Xyti, so static expectationsare optimal. Bischoff has pointed out that static ex- pectationsunderlie his interpretationof the distributedlags in his invest- ment equation,but apparentlyconsiders static expectationsa naive rule of thumband does not investigatewhether optimal expectations would be verydifferent from static expectations.'7 Many of Jorgenson'sempirical distributed lags are close to second- orderPascal with a mean lag of abouttwo years.His implicitestimate of Bl>,then, is 0.5. The impliedestimate of p is 0.5/1, which is differentto the extentthat &differs from one. Followingare two regressionestimates of + obtainedfrom Berndt's annual data on Jorgenson'scomposite capital- demandvariable for the years1950 through1968: K*=--1.2 + 1.060 KA; (3.4) (0.039) K*- = 5.4 + 0.928 K'i + 0.48 t. (8.7) (0.165) (0.58) = 1 in 1950. The numbersin parenthesesare standarderrors. In the first regression, only the laggedvalue of the variablecan explainits trend,so the estimated serial-correlationparameter, &, exceeds one. The second regressionlets the deterministictrend, XT, be a linearfunction of time, which of course reducesthe serialcorrelation to a value less than one. The firstregression is relevantfor appraisingthe bias in a capital-demandregression with no time trend, or, equivalently,in a net-investmentequation with no con- stant.The secondapplies when there is a timetrend or whenthe net-invest- mentequation includes a constant.If f is actually1.060, as suggestedby the firstregression, then the value of fi is 0.47 and the true mean of the physical-lag is 1.79 years, not 2 years. The error is about 11 percentand is easily withinthe rangeof samplingvariation. On the other

17. "Effectof Alternative Lag Distributions." 82 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity. 1:1977 hand,if the value of , fromthe secondregression is correct,then the value of p is 0.54 and the true mean of the distributionis 2.34 years. Many of Jorgenson's(and others') equations included constants, so the secondesti- mateis probablysomewhat more relevant than the first.These calculations do suggestthat the bias in the lag distributionson accountof the role of the laggedvariables in the formationof expectationsis not one of the most importantempirical issues in investmentanalysis. Further refinement of thesecalculations is probablynot justifiedin view of the potentiallyserious problemscaused by simultaneityof the right-handvariables in investment regressions,a topicto whichI nowturn.

IMPLICATIONS OF THE ENDOGENEITY OF OUTPUT There is one importantfurther obstacle to measurementof the dis- tributedlag in the investmentequation: the econometricproblems posed by the endogeneityof the major right-handvariables in an investment equation.18Endogeneity arises from two sources.First, the randomdis- turbancein the investmentfunction feeds back throughthe expenditure process to influenceoutput and the interestrate. An upwardshift in the investmentfunction raises GNP and the interestrate in much the same way as an increasein governmentexpenditures does. A regressionof in- vestmenton outputand the interestrate (or a serviceprice of capitalthat dependson the interestrate) will tend to overstatethe positive effect of outputand understate the negativeeffect of the interestrate. The second, more serious,source of endogeneityarises from the cor- relationof the disturbancein the investmentfunction with the disturbances in the other majorstructural equations of the economy.Unmeasured in- fluencesassociated with the arrivalof favorableor unfavorableinforma- tion shift the investmentfunction and also shift the other determinantsof GNP and of the interestrate. Again, the likely patternis positivecorrela-

18. Some authors have argued beyond the econometric difficulty to say that an equation with, for example, output on the right-handside is somehow logically defec- tive because output is determinedjointly with investment;see, for example, John P. Gould, "The Use of Endogenous Variables in Dynamic Models of Investment," QuarterlyJournal of Economics, vol. 83 (November 1969), pp. 580-99. This line of argument appears to involve a misunderstandingof the notion of a structuralequa- tion. For a more complete discussion, see Robert E. Hall and Dale W. Jorgenson, "Tax Policy and Investment Behavior: Reply and Further Results," American Eco- nomic Review, vol. 59 (June 1969), pp. 388-401. Robert E. Hall 83 tion of output, the interestrate, and the disturbancein the investment equation.Here, too, a regressionwill overstatethe effect of output on investmentand understate the effectof the interestrate. In principle,econometric techniques are availablefor recoveringthe true structuralinvestment lag in the presenceof the correlationof the right-handvariables and the disturbancein the investmentequation. These techniquesrely on instrumentalvariables that are independentof the dis- turbance.However, the logic of the investmentequation-that today's investmentis the realizationof plans made one, two, or threeyears ago- rules out the most fruitfulsource of instruments-namely,lagged endog- enous variablessuch as GNP in earlierquarters. Apart from demographic trends and variationsin the weather, the only admissibleinstrumental variablesfor the investmentequation are truly exogenous measuresof macroeconomicpolicy. Whethersuch measureswith any power as instru- mentsexist is doubtful. Though the prospectsfor estimatingthe investmentequation through two-stageleast squaresare not entirelyfavorable, the previous analysis does suggest a useful test for endogeneityof the right-handvariables in an investmentequation. The investmentequation relates investment to the firstdifjerences of GNP while the correlationof GNP and the disturbance may generatean apparentrelation between investmentand the level of GNP. Then the observeddistributed lag betweeninvestment and GNP is useful in the followingrespect: If the sum of the lag coefficientsis zero, then the observedrelation actually depends on the firstdifferences of GNP and may actuallybe the true investmentequation. If the sum is unam- biguouslypositive, then it is impossiblethat the estimatedlag distribution is the true distribution.In other words, a findingthat the level of invest- ment dependson the level of GNP invalidatesany claim that the relation is an investment equation alone.'19 The problemsof endogeneityare further compounded in cases in which separatedistributed lags are fittedto the influencesof real output and of the relativeservice cost of capital, notablyin the work of Bischoff.The bias from the endogeneityof the right-handvariables probably is most severein the contemporaneouspart of the distributedlags. Then the lag distributionfor output will exaggeratethe acceleratoreffect in the short

19. All of this applies as stated to net, not gross, investment. When the proposed test is applied to data on gross investment later in the paper, the test is suitably modified. 84 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 run and that for the serviceprice will understateits true effectin the short run. There is a clear bias in the regressionaway from the simplermodel in which the responsesto the two variablesare equal in magnitudeand oppositein sign. Again, a useful test for endogeneityis based on the gen- eral predictionof investmenttheory that the level of outputhas no influ- ence on net investment.If level effectsare revealed by the regression,there is a presumptionagainst its interpretationas a pure structuralinvestment equation.

EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE ON THE DISTRIBUTED LAG Many authorshave fitted distributedlags between investmentand its determinants.20Except for a numberof studieswith obviouseconometric problemsassociated with the use of Koyck distributedlags withoutcor- rectionfor serial correlation,there is remarkablyclose agreementabout the basic featuresof the lag functions.They are smooth, hump-shaped distributionswith an averagelag of about two years. Withinthe general class of flexibleaccelerator investment models, this conclusionseems to hold overquite wide variations in the specificationof the demandfunction for capital and in the econometricmethod used to estimatethe lag dis- tributions.2'Of course, all of this evidence is subject to the potentially seriousbias from endogeneity discussed earlier. Though some studieshave used simultaneousestimation techniques, none to my knowledgehas come to gripswith the basic obstaclethat the logic of the distributed-laginvest- ment function makes any lagged endogenousvariable ineligible as an instrumentunless it is laggedmore than the most distantpart of the invest- ment lag distribution.Two featuresof investmentfunctions of the type fittedby Jorgensonmay reduce this bias, but there is no reason to think they eliminateit: First, his constraintthat output and the rentalprice of

20. Many of these are summarizedby Jorgenson,"Econometric Studies of Invest- ment Behavior."I will not discuss the equally large body of evidence on the lag be- tween appropriationsor new orders and the determinantsof investment.Though this lag is free from pure delivery lags, it includes many of the planning stages that I include in a full description of the investment process. Throughout the paper, "de- livery lags" is a short-handterm for all of the time-consuming steps in investment. 21. For example, the more refinedversion of my own work with Jorgensonwhich used the modern Almon lag technique and made a full correction for serial correla- tion certainly fits within this general summary; see Robert E. Hall and Dale W. Jorgenson, "Application of the Theory of Optimum ," in Fromm, ed., Tax Incentives and Capital Spending, pp. 9-60. Robert E. Hall 85 capital enter as a ratio offsets the positive bias associatedwith the cor- relationof GNP andthe disturbancewith the negativebias associatedwith the correlationof the interestrate and the disturbance.Second, his con- straintthat the level of the demandfor capitalhas no permanenteffect on net investmentprobably reduces the bias causedby the correlationof the level of GNP withthe disturbance.The reviewbelow of Bischoff'swork in which both of these constraintsare dropped suggests that they have a majorinfluence. In additionto the somewhatquestionable econometric evidence about lags in investment,there is an importantbody of surveyevidence collected by ThomasMayer,22 which has beencited extensively by Jorgenson.Mayer findsthat the averagelag betweenthe decisionto undertakean investment projectand the completionof it is abouttwenty-one months. To this must be added any lag that occurs betweenthe arrivalof informationthat in- vestmentis needed and the decisionto carryout the investment.As Jor- genson argues,Mayer's evidence seems perfectlyconsistent with modern econometricfindings about the lag distribution. This evidenceon lags in investmentconfirms the view that they are a majorlimitation in the responseof investmentto changesin interestrates and otherdeterminants of the serviceprice of capital, and thus an impor- tantinfluence in making,the IS curvesteeper than it wouldbe if investment respondedquickly to its determinants.Any realisticmodel for the analysis of stabilizationpolicies must incorporatea seriousconsideration of these lags.

TOBIN'S "Q THEORY" OF INVESTMENT The majorcompetitor to Jorgenson'stheoretical framework for invest- menthas been createdby JamesTobin.23 Tobin observes that unexpected changesin the demandfor capitalgenerate discrepancies between the cur- rentmarket value of existinginstalled capital and the cost of reproducing

22. "Plant and Equipment Lead Times," Journal of , vol. 33 (April 1960), pp. 127-32. 23. Tobin's thinking on the subject considerablypredates Jorgenson's,of course. Two recent fairly complete expositions are , "A General Equilibrium Approach to Monetary Theory," Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking, vol. 1 (February 1969), pp. 15-29, and Tobin " Markets and the Cost of Capital" (with William Brainard), Discussion Paper 427 (March 1976), forthcoming in a Festschrift for . 86 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 that capital. The ratio between the two is his famous "q." It is essential to understandthe relationbetween the two theoriesin orderto interpretthe empiricalevidence obtainedby the disciples of the two major figures, especiallybecause Tobin and his followersgeneraliy seem to view the lags in the investmentprocess as extremelylengthy. So far as I know,the litera- turedoes not containa reconciliationof the two theories. Tobin cites two reasonsfor q to departfrom unity. First, lags in de- liveringcapital goods generatetransitory departures. Second, costs of in- vestmentthat rise more than proportionatelyto the rate of investment bringabout both transitory and permanent departures. I proposeto ignore the secondconsideration. Adjustment costs and deliverylags are probably best viewed as alternativeexplanations of the lagged responseof invest- ment to its determinants.A modelcontainiing both would be complexand redundant. If deliverylags are the only obstacleto instantfulfillment of the basic conditionthat the presentvalue of the future marginalcontributions of capitalequal its currentacquisition cost, then q departsfrom one only to the extent that capitalalready in place is now expected to yield more or less than it was expectedto at the time of installation.That is, qt - 1 is the presentvalue at time t of the extra rent attributableto recent unex- pected events.This rentwill be earnedonly over the period duringwhich capitalcannot be adjusted.A simplemodel of this process is the follow- ing: As before,let Ki,t be the stock of capitalwith deliverylag i, and let Xt be the stock that would be held today if there were no deliverylag. Supposethat the excess rent in real termsis a simplemultiple of the gap, X(Xt K-- t). Then today'sqt for capital of type i is, in the absenceof discounting, W+-1 qi,t - I = E(X -Ki).- 8t G

Note that no excess rents are expectedafter t + i - 1, since in t -+ i and beyond,the capitalstock will be adjustedtoday to eliminateany expected gap. Supposethat capital demandconsists of a deterministictrend, Xt, plus a residualthat is approximatelya randomwalk. Then staticexpecta- tions are appropriatefor the residual,and the expectedfuture value of the demandis the sumof the futuretrend and the currentresidual:

E(X8) 2s + (Xt - t). t Robert E. Hall 87 Now the currentanld future values of Ki,t were based on expectationsof Xt formedby the sameprocess in past quarters: Ki,8=-8 + (X8,-i-Xs_0. Putting these into the formula for qi,t gives

t?i-1 qi, t - 1 Xi(Xt - - E 1.-0. = Xt) X 8-t (Xs-i- The firstterm is today'sexpectation of the total futureexcess rent if the capital stock remainsat its presentlevel and the second adjustsfor in- vestmentcommitments made in the recentpast thatwill be installedwithin the next i quarters. Takingthe weightedaverage of the qi,t over the delivery-timedistribu- tion, p3i,gives the generalformula for qt: qg 1 = iqi,t- 1

= (Xt - -t)X (1-Bo)Xt-. 0=0 Here y is the firstmoment or mean lag of the pl-distributionand B0 is, as before, the fractionof capital with deliverylags of 0 or less. Again, the second term adjustsfor the futureinvestment already in the pipeline. The next step is to combinethis model of the determinationof qt with the earliermodel of investment.First, define X(L)= Xi-X X2(I - Bo)LO; thus q- = X(L)(Xt - t) Recallthat K = f3(L)(Xt - Xt) + Xt, so there is, in fact, a relation between Kt and qt as posited by Tobin:

= Kt X(L)(q t 1) + fct. Tlhelag betweenq and K is not the distributionof deliverytimes, P(L). In fact, in one importantcase, the relationshipturns out to be a purely contemporaneousone betweenqt and the first differenceof Kt, which is simplynet investment.Suppose the distributionof deliverytimes is geo- metric:

,B(L)= 1 - /L 88 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 Then

1(1 )2 1 (t-1) + or

AKt 1(qt )X. 1)++ This is exactly the equationproposed by Tobin; it is an implicationof Jorgenson'smodel understatic expectations and a geometricdistribution of deliverytimes. A careful empiricalinvestigation of the q theory has recently been carriedout by JohnCiccolo.24 Working with a varietyof concepts,he finds a statisticallyunambiguous relation between investmentand empirical measuresol q. In all of his regressions,the dependentvariable is gross investmentdivided by the capitalstock, andq enterswith an unconstrained distributedlag. The sum of the lag coefficientsvaries from a low value of 0.033, whenaggregate fixed investment from the nationalincome accounts is the dependentvariable, to 0.1322, when new ordersfor equipmentis the dependentvariable. In a pair of regressionsin whichfixed investment is brokeninto structuresand equipment,the sum is 0.052 for structures and 0.124 for equipment.Tobin has summarizedCiccolo's findingsby stating 0.08 as a reasonableestimate of the sum of the lag coefficients, whichseems entirely fair. With respect to the natureof the lag distribution, Ciccolo invariablyobtains fairly short distributions,with means in the rangefrom two to four quarters.Although the hypothesisthat the relation is purelycontemporaneous is rejected,the simplemodel with a geometric distributionof deliverytimes is a reasonablygood approXimationto the underlyingdistributed lag, whichturns out to be fairlylong. Interpretationof Ciccolo'sresults requires an assumptionabout X. Re- call thathis regressionhas the form

I-y(L)(q -1) + whereX is the derivativeof the real serviceprice with respectto the capital stock. As Tobin suggests,a first guess about the elasticityof the relation is unity,as impliedby a Cobb-Douglasproduction function. Since the real 24. John H. Ciccolo, Jr., "Four Essays on Monetary Policy" (Ph.D. dissertation, , 1975); and Ciccolo, "Money, Equity Values, and Income-Tests for Exogeneity," Working Paper (Boston College, Department of Economics, n.d.; processed). Robert E. Hall 89 serviceprice is around0.06 at quarterlyrates, the impliedvalue of XKis the same 0.06 underunit elasticity.Now approximateCiccolo's short dis- tributedlag y(L) by the sum of its coefficients,say yo 0.08. Then an estimateof the parameterof the underlyinggeometric lag distributionis availablefrom

1 (l1-gi'2

The resultis p = 0.966. The mean of the geometricdistribution is twenty- eight quarters,or seven years; 13 percentor just over one-eighthof the adjustmentto a changein the desiredcapital stock takes place in the first fourquarters. Taking account of the shortdistributed lag foundby Ciccolo wouldreduce this fractionsomewhat, but thiswould be offsetby the oppo- site bias to be discussedshortly. Ciccolo'sresults seem to confirmthe q theorists'view that investment is a sluggishprocess. This sluggishnessapplies both to the acceleratorre- sponse to changesin outputand to the responseof investmentto changes in interestrates. Recall from table 1 that the effect of expenditurepolicy is still remarkablyweak even if only an eighthof the adjustmentof capital occursin the firstyear. In that case, $1 billion in expenditureraises GNP by only $0.8 billion.Monetary policy is correspondinglystrong. The majorconclusion of this paper-that thereis a real possibilitythat expenditurepolicy is nowherenear as potentas most economistsbelieve- survivescomplete acceptanceof the evidence of the q theory. However, thereis one importantreason to expect a bias in Ciccolo'sresults toward an overstatementof the lengthof the investmeritlag. In the q theory,slug- gishnessof investmentis inferredfrom the low value of the coefficient(or sum of coefficients) of q in the investmentequation. To the extent that the empiricalmeasure of q in an investmentregression contains important measurementerrors, a familiarprinciple of econometrictheory holds that its coefficientwill be biased downwardas an estimateof the true relation betweenq and the rate of investment.Ciccolo infers q fromllimperfect data on corporatevaluations; neither the value of nor the value of is measureddirectly for the sectorsfor which he has investmentdata. He infersthe valuationby discountingdividend and interestflows by price- dividendratios and marketyields for much narrowersectors. In the case of debtespecially, this procedureis boundto introducesignificant random measurementerrors. A more basic obstacleto unbiasedestimation is the 90 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 inabilityto measureq specificallyfor capitalgoods. The marketvaluation of the corporatesector upon which Ciccolo relies is the value of every- thing owned by corporations,not just their physical capital. Intangible capital,natural resources, goodwill, position, and firm-specific human capital all contributeto the marketvalue of a firm. They cause importantfluctuations in the measuredq that areirrelevant for investment in physicalcapital. Again, these bias downwardthe coefficientof q in an investmentregression. On this account,the length of the underlyingin- vestmentlag inferredfrom Ciccolo'sregression ought to be treatedas an upper bound. Of course, Jorgenson'sapproach to measuringthe invest- ment lag is also biasedby measurementerror, though the directionof the bias is less clear. Withinmodels of the Jorgenson-Tobinclass, in which output and interestrates affect investmentwith the same lag, it appears that somewherebetween 10 percent and 30 percent of the ultimatead- justmentof capital takes place within the first year after a stabilization policytakes effect.

The Putty-ClayHypothesis

The putty-clayhypothesis has a central role in investmenttheory.25 Under strictputty-clay, the supply of outputfrom existingcapital is un- responsiveto the serviceprice of capital;a stimulusto investmentoperat- ing throughinterest rates, for example, affects only the investmentto increaseoutput and does not causesubstitution toward less labor-intensive use of the existingcapital. Of course,there is a continuousrange of alter- nativesbetween strict putty-clay and the putty-puttycase in whichinstalled capital is just as flexible as new capital. The issue is to decide where in this rangethe best descriptionof the substitutionpossibilities of a modern economylies. 25. Leif Johansenoriginally proposedthe hypothesis in "Substitutionversus Fixed Production Coefficients in the Theory of : A Synthesis,"Econo- metrica, vol. 27 (April 1959), pp. 157-76. Apparently, is responsible for the misunderstandingof the physical properties of the two substances that gave rise to the name of the hypothesis. What is called the putty-clay hypothesis ought to be the clay hypothesis (malleable ex ante and hard ex post) and the putty-putty alternative should be simply the putty technology. But it is too late to inflict this rationalization of the terminology on the reader, and I will perpetuate Phelps' blun- der. A bibliographyof other contributionsappears in ChristopherBliss, "On Putty- Clay," Review of Economic Studies, vol. 35 (April 1968), pp. 105-32. Robert E. Hall 91

IMPLICATIONS FOR INVESTMENT THEORY One task of investmenttheory not undertakenby Jorgensonis to inte- gratethe putty-clayhypothesis into the theory.I have arguedearlier that Jorgenson'srental formula and the attendingprinciple that today'sinves- ment should proceed to the point of equality of the marginalvalue of capital to the rentalprice are good approximationseven outside of the strictassumptions of his model,but even so the completeinvestment equa- tion embodyingthe putty-clayhypothesis is quite different.The inability to varythe laborintensity of existingvintages of capitallimits the response of investmentto changesin the relativeprice of capital,even thoughthe responseis exactlydescribed by Jorgenson'sprinciple. Supposethat the technologyfor today'svintage of capitalis described by its full cost function, QNyt, where QN is the level of output to be pro- ducedwith new capitaland /t is the averageand marginalcost at today's and rentalprice of capital.On the other hand, the variablecosts for producingon existingvintages of capitalare

C?t(Q?,Kjj... .,Kt-1). Here Q? is the level of outputto be producedusing existingcapital, and K1,.. ., Kt-l are quantities of capital of vintages 1 through t - 1. The dependenceof cost on the prices of variablefactors, especiallylabor, is incorporatedsimply through the time subscriptof the cost function.Pre- sumably,to the extentthat the putty-clayhypothesis holds, this cost func- tion shows sharplyrising at some level of outputidentified as the capacityof the existingcapital stock. The overallcost function(ex- cept for the irrelevantfixed costs of the existingcapital) is

Ct(Q,Ki,... ,Kt_) = min [C'(Q,K1,... ,Kt-1) + Q tt]. Qt + Q? = Q The minimumof total cost occursat an allocationof outputbetween old and new capital that equates the marginalcost on each. Since marginal cost on new vintages is the predeterminedconstant, /t, this means that outputon the old capitalis pushedto the point at whichthe marginalvari- able cost equalsthe total marginalcost of producingon new capital.Thus Qt is determined by

aC?t OQ?? 92 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 which can be solved explicitlyfor Q?:

Q? = S?t(pt,Ki,... jKt_j)j where S? is the supplyfunction for output on old vintages,in the sense thatQ? would be the supplyof a competitivefirm that had capitalK1, .... Kt-l but no new capital, selling in a marketfor outputwith price Itt. Of course, nothingin this analysisdeals with the outputmarket and no as- sumptionof competitionis requiredfor whatfollows. All outputnot producedon old capitalis producedby investingin new capacity:

Q7 = Qt -St(AtjKj,...Kt_j). Supposethat the optimalcapital-output ratio for new capacityis pt. Then investment is QNpt and the final putty-clay investment function is achieved: Kt = (Qt - Q9)O3t = [Qt - St(tK,...Kt_,)]ot. The responseof investmentto changesin the rentalprice of capitalv has two components:

-Kt = QN dAt OS_ S 9 t OVt t Ovt O/.LtOvt Both termsare negative. The firstsays thatan increasein the cost of capital decreasesthe capital intensityof the new capacity;this effect is propor- tional to the amount of new capacity, as measuredby Qt. The second term says that high capitalcosts raise the marginalcost of producingon new capital and thereforeinduce higher output on the existing capital. The magnitudeof the second term depends on the output elasticity of marginalcost on old capital.Under the strictputty-clay hypothesis, under which existingcapital has absolutelyfixed capacity,the second term dis- appears.The conclusionfollows that the responseof investmentto interest ratesand taxes is weak in the shortrun because the responseapplies only to the smallamount of outputproduced on new capital,as emphasizedby Bischoff.On the other hand, if more outputcan be squeezedout of old capitalby incurringhigher costs, then the second termmay be important as well. The priorcase for limitedsubstitutability ex post is based on the plau- sible notion that designersof plant and equipmentface a much broader Robert E. Hall 93 set of alternativesthan the usersof the capitalafter the designerhas made a specificchoice and the equipmentis installed.In the extreme,designers decidehow manywork stations, how manyelectric motors, and so on, are requiredto accomplisha certainpurpose, and the installedfacility cannot operate withoutthe specifiedlabor and electricalinput and cannot use extralabor or electricity.The view that most capitalhas this characteristic underliesthe belief that the strictputty-clay hypothesis is a good approxi- mationto reality,though none would arguethat it is absolutelyprecise. There is an equallystrong prior case againstthe hypothesis.The idea that most of the cooperationbetween labor and capitaltakes the form of workerstending machines in a routineway specifiedby the designerof the machinedescribes only a smalland shrinkingsector of a moderneconomy. In 1973, only 13 percentof the U.S. labor force were classifiedas opera- tors of machines(other than vehicles). The modernelectronic computer is a good exampleof the case in which few importantdecisions about the relationbetween capital and labor are made irrevocablyat the time of design.Every user of a computermakes choices constantly about the sub- stitutionof the computer'sservices for humaneffort. When an investment credit or other influencemakes computer services cheaper, computers become cost effectivein tasks that had been at the margin.For this sub- stitution,existing computers are just as good as new ones. More generally, the observationthat the numberof workerstending a machineis largely predeterminedby the designerdoes not establishthe putty-clayhypothe- sis, since the importantdimension of substitutionmay be between the machineand its crew and laborthat cooperateswithout working at a sta- tion on the machine.In the exampleof the computer,the kind of substitu- tion ex post that refutes the putty-clayhypothesis is not between the computerand its operators,but betweenthe packageof the computerand operators,and all of the workersinvolved in handlingdata in an enterprise. Beyond the generalobjection that the putty-clayhypothesis has an ex- cessivelynarrow view of the opportunitiesfor substitutionex post, there is one ratherspecific objection that is fatal to the hypothesiseven as an approximationto reality.One of the most importantdimensions of factor substitutionis variationsin the annualhours of operationof capital.The labor requiredfor the marginalhour of operationmust usuallybe paid a weekendor shift differential,so often capital is used for fewer than the 8,760 hoursin a year. When capitalbecomes cheaper, its optimalannual hours of operationdrop, and what amountsto substitutionof capitalfor 94 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 laborhas occurred.In particular,the price elasticityof supplyon existing vintagesof capital, identifiedin the earliertheoretical discussion as the crucialaspect of the putty-clayhypothesis from the point of view of in- vestmenttheory, is potentiallyhigh if shift differentialsfor labor are not too large and if not too high a fractionof the capitalstock is at the corner solutionof full-timeoperation. Robert Lucas has developed a complete analyticaltreatment of the productionpossibilities in an economywith variablehours of capitaluti- lization.26He points out that variationsin hours can give a theoretically soundexplanation of threepuzzling facts aboutthe U.S. economy: (1) the unit elasticityof employmentwith respectto outputin the shortrun; (2) the cyclicalstability of real ;and (3) the astonishinglevel of output achievedat the peak of WorldWar II, far above the limit suggestedby any simpleproduction function. The theoryexplains the proportionalre- lation betweenlabor input and real output as reflectingvariations in the annualhours of operationof the existingcapital stock. The theory does not have a definiteprediction about the behaviorof the averagereal wage (averagedacross workers paid regularwages for the firstshift and a higher wageat othertimes), but constancyis perfectlycompatible with it. Finally, WorldWar II was a periodof peakutilization of almostall typesof capital. This level of utilizationwas economicallyefficient only underthe extreme conditionsof the war,and would never be reproducedby the privateecon- omy in normalperiods. All in all, superficialarguments in favor of the putty-clayhypothesis do not survivecareful scrutiny. Higher prices may well bring forth sub- stantialadditional output from the existingcapital, and this refutesstrict putty-clayeven as an approximation.The questionbecomes an empirical one, with no strongprior in favorof putty-clay.So far as I know, the con- nection betweenthe behaviorof marginalcost in the short run and the putty-clayhypothesis has not been exploited in empiricalwork, though it seems a promisingapproach. The only full-scaleempirical investigation of the hypothesisin whichit is testablerather than maintained is in Charles Bischoff'swork on investment,to whichI now turn.

BISCHOFF 'S INVESTMENT EQUATION In a series of importantpapers, Charles Bischoff has fitted an invest- ment functionin which differentdistributed lags apply to real outputand 26. Robert E. Lucas, Jr., "Capacity,Overtime, and Empirical Production Func- tions," American Economic Review, vol. 60 (May 1970), pp. 23-27. Robert E. Hall 95 to the serviceprice of capital.27One of his principalmotives was to test the putty-clayhypothesis, which he interpretedas predictinga longerlag betweenchanges in the serviceprice and the responseof investment,com- paredwith the lag for changesin output.His resultsshow a strongasym- metryin the two responsesand have been widely cited as confirmingthe putty-clayhypothesis. Representative results from Bischoff's work appear in table 2.28 To interprethis findings calls first for understandingthe implicationsof the use of grossinvestment as the dependentvariable. Sup- pose for simplicitythat the capitalstock is relatedby a distributedlag to a variable,Xt, thatindexes the demandfor capital:

Kt E oiXt_1. i=O

Now gross investmentis the sum of net investmentKt - Ktl and de- terioration,8Kt-l:

It = K - (1 -6)Kt1; so a functionfor grossinvestment is

It = 2 i[Xt - (I -6)Xt-i-1]. The analogof Bischoff'sprocedure for this simplemodel wouldbe to fit a distributedlag to the levels of Xt:

It = Xt_i. Thelag parameters,/3 and,1 arerelated by

i'= i- (1 -a)i However, the level form is more general in one central respect: in the differenceform, the functionis constrainedso thatnet investmentdepends only on the firstdifferences and not on the long-runlevel of demand,while in the level form this basic conclusionof investmenttheory can be vio-

27. "HypothesisTesting and the Demand for Capital Goods"; "Effectof Alterna- tive Lag Distributions";and Charles W. Bischoff, "BusinessInvestment in the 1970s: A Comparisonof Models,"BPEA, 1:1971, pp. 13-58. 28. I calculated these from the data in the appendix to his paper, "Effect of Alternative Lag Distributions." They do not agree exactly with any of Bischoff's published results, but the difference is unimportant. In the process of this work, I verified Bischoff's claim that his findings are extremely robust with respect to the choice of lag specification.Even specificationsthat take a very different approachto fittingseparate lags for output and the service price of capital showed the same strong asymmetryreported by Bischoff. 96 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 Table 2. Bischoff's InvestmentFunction in Level and Difference Form Equations 2.1 Levelforma 11 11 it 'VteiQt-i + 7AVtii Q _i

,B= -0.165 yA = 0.177 (0.026) (0.026) 2 0.9918 standard error = 0.637 2.2 Differenceforms 10 it = I SitV_i Q t-i -(1 -) t_iiQ t-i-l i=o 10 +> 'Yi[Vt-i_1Q t-i-(I - 6) Vt-i2Qt-i-11 i=o gi = -0.465 EYi = 0.604 (0.140) (0.138)

k2 = 0.9215 standard error 1.972 Lag coefficients Levelform, 2.1 Differenceform, 2.2 Service-price Service-price Lag Outputeffect, effect, Outputeffect, effect, (quarters) ,B '+ y ,B' + 1Y-I f3i + yi 13i + Yi-1 0 0.012 -0.002 0.019 -0.010 1 0.008 -0.001 0.009 0.008 2 0.004 0.001 0.003 0.002 3 0.001 0.001 -0.001 0.002 4 -0.001 0.002 -0.003 0.004 5 -0.002 0.002 -0.003 0.004 6 -0.002 0.002 -0.003 0.006 7 -0.002 0.002 -0.001 0.006 8 -0.001 0.003 0.002 0.005 9 -0.001 0.002 0.011 0.004 10 -0.001 0.001 0.002 0.006 11 -0.003 -0.001 -0.016 -0.008 12 0.000 0.000 0.000 -0.022 Sources: The lag coefficients are representative results calculated from data in Charles W. Bischoff, "The Effect of Alternative Lag Distributions," in Gary Fromm, ed., Tax Incentives and Capital Spending (Brookings Institution, 1971), pp. 128-30. a. It = gross investment; Vt inverse of real service price of capital; Qt = real output; a = quarterly depreciation rate, assumed to be 0.04. Standard errors are in billions of 1958 dollars. lated. In termsof the lag parameters,8B of the level form,this restrictionis

2 (1- -ig' = Q. This linear restrictionon the regressioncoefficients can be tested with Robert E. Hall 97 standardtechniques. If it is rejectedin favor of a positive value of the weightedsum, then net investmentdepends on the level of the demandfor capitaleven in the long run, and the equationcannot be called an invest- ment function.Again, the obviousinterpretation of this findingis that the disturbancein the investmentequation is correlatedwith the right-hand variables. As the equationsin table 2 show, Bischoff actuallyfits separatedis- tributedlags to compositevariables that are the productsof his relative price of capital services, Vt, which containsthe service price in the de- nominator,and real output, Qt. In this case, in order to qualify as an investmentfunction, both sets of distributed-lagcoefficients should satisfy the constraint;in other words, Bischoff'sinvestment equation ought to look like equation2.2. The resultsin table2 show thatBischoff's equation is devastatedby the constraintthat it be a genuineinvestment equation. The unexplainedresidual variance rises by a factor of more than nine, fromless than 1 percentto almost8 percent.29The problemwith Bischoff's equationcan be seen in the first two columns at the bottom of table 2, wherethe separateinfluence of outputand the serviceprice of capitalare computedfor the unconstrainedequation. Most of the positive effect of outputis in the contemporaneousquarter or in the immediatelypreceding quarter.Eventually the influencebecomes negative,but the negativeco- efficientsare nowherenear large enough to counteractthe strong con- temporaneouseffect. As Bischoffemphasizes, the patternof responseto the serviceprice of capitalis very different:it starts at zero, builds to a peak, and thensubsides. But only threeof the coefficientsare negative; the equationhas the erroneousimplication that a permanentlylower interest rate makes net investmentpermanently higher. The explanationfor this findingis not transparent,but it is plainly incompatiblewith the most generalprinciple of investmenttheory. The thirdand fourthcolumns of table 2 show the resultsof constrain- ing the coefficientsto eliminatepermanent effects on net investment.The contemporaneousrelation between output and investmentremains strong, but the negativepart of the distributioncomes earlierand is stronger.The

29. Now it is clear why Bischoff's equation was so dominant in his comparison with other investment equations ("A Comparisonof Models"). The equations based on Jorgenson'swork do embody the constraintand so run under an enormous handi- cap. Most of Bischoff'svictory is attributableto this handicap and not to the separate distributedlags he fits. 98 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 effect of the serviceprice remainsvery different;Bischoff's central argu- ment that outputand the serviceprice are relatedto investmentin rather differentways is stronglysustained in these results.But there is no rea- son to believe a priori,and no evidencein these results,that imposingthe theoretical constraintsomehow completely overcomes the problem of simultaneity.The negativeweights at the very end of the distributionfor the service-pricevariable are particularlysuspect: theory permits them to be zero but not negative. Anotherway to expressthe unsatisfactorynature of Bischoff'sresults is to computethe value of the depreciationparameter, 8, for which the equationreally is an investmentfunction. This can be done separately for the outputeffects and the service-priceeffects. The rate of depreciation that achieves1(6B + y')(1 - 8)- = 0 for the first column of table 2 is 8.6 percenta quarter,or 30 percentper year, far above any reasonable value. Equipmentthat depreciatesthis quickly is often not classifiedas capitalat all, in fact. The correspondingcalculation for the service-price effectsyields the evenmore unreasonable value of 59 percenta quarter. Takenat face value,Bischoff's results are by far the strongestchallenge to the principalthesis of this paper.According to a correctedversion of his equation,about half of the acceleratorresponse of investmentto output is estimatedto occurwithin a year while interesteffects take muchlonger. Those resultscorrespond roughly to row 3 of table 1, and thus implythat expenditurepolicies can have a substantialeffect on GNP. However,this conclusionrests on the propositionthat the sum of the acceleratorand the marginalpropensity to consumeis almost exactly one, so that the pure expenditureprocess is explosiveor nearlyso. This implicationof the cor- rected putty-clayfindings has not been widely appreciatedand probably makes them less plausiblethan they appearto be when the equationis studied in isolation. Unfortunately,it appearsthat a strong correlation betweenthe disturbancein the investmentequation and the level of GNP is biasingthe equationtoward too sharpan initialresponse to changesin output.Certainly the overwhelmingstatistical rejection of the accelerator hypothesispoints in this direction.Much more study of the investment equation,with a great deal more attentionto the critical issue of simul- taneity,will be requiredto give convincingevidence that the accelerator effect is as strongas it appearsto be in regressionsthat follow Bischoff's approachbut are made consistentwith investmenttheory. For now, it appearsmore reasonableto put the first-yeareffect at no more than 30 Robert E. Hall 99 percentof the long-runeffect, ratherthan the 50 percentfigure implied by equation2.2. This bringsthe effect of expenditureson GNP into the range of 0.5 to 0.8, rather than the 1.4 implied by that investment equation.

Summaryof Evidenceon the Three"Qualifications"

This paperhas presentedevidence bearing on the validityof the three qualificationsof the investmentprocess listed at the outset.

LAGS The evidencedoes have somethingto say aboutlags in the investment process, and they are an importantinfluence in inhibitingthe response of investmentthat would otherwisemake the IS curve very flat. Within the class of investmentfunctions in which the same lag applies to both the acceleratoreffect and the interest-rateeffect, the evidence suggests that somewherebetween 10 percent and 30 percent of the long-runre- sponse of capitaloccurs within the firstyear. Investmentis very sluggish comparedto the aim of stabilizationpolicy. Still, the results in table 1 suggestthat the interestsensitivity of investmentover the first year is a majorinfluence in weakeningexpenditure policy and strengtheningmone- tary policy within that period, even when the investmentresponse is at the low end of the range.

PUTTY-CLAY

Neitherthe strictputty-clay nor the strictputty-putty hypothesis seems plausible,but researchhas not uncoveredthe right compromisebetween them. To the extent that putty-claypredominates, both expenditureand monetarypolicies have major effects within the first year, because the acceleratoreffect acts well beforethe inhibitinginterest-rate effect. Con- sistentregressions that correctBischoff's approach support this view, but strongevidence of simultaneityundermines the usefulnessof those results. The sharpaccelerator response of investmentin the firstyear afteroutput changesis an unreasonablefeature of the equationquite apartfrom the more complicatedcriticism offered earlier in this paper. It is the strong 100 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 accelerator,much more than the weak interestresponse, that makes ex- penditurepolicy so powerfulwith that type of investmentequation.

TERM STRUCTURE OF INTEREST RATES As a matterof theory,what belongs in the serviceprice of capitalis a short-runinterest rate, thoughthe issue of short againstlong rates is un- likely to be resolvedempirically. But this is hardlythe end of the story. A more generalquestion, quite beyond the realmof the investmentequa- tion, is the relationbetween the short-runinterest rate appropriatefor investmentdecisions and the marketreturn to short-termfinancial that is appropriatefor decisions about holding money.30The traditional view, adoptedin the simpleIS-LM model at the beginningof the paper, is thatinterest-bearing financial assets and real capital are close substitutes, and money is a weak substitutefor either.Then marketsshould equalize the short-runyields of all nonmoneyassets, and the commonyield is what belongsin the investmentequation. If the variouskinds of assets,real and financial,are not close substitutes,there is no reasonto expectmarkets to equalizeyields. In particular,the yield from a very money-likefinancial asset, say Treasurybills or commercialpaper, is not a good guide to the market'sshort-run interest rate or net yield from real capital. A better choice might be the expected short-runyield from long-termfinancial assets. This line of argumentdoes not seem to suggestthat the long rate itself belongs in the investmentequation, however. Further,it does not have any definiteimplication with respectto the basic issue of the interest elasticityof investmentand the effectsof alternativestabilization policies.

Conclusions

Economistsdo not seem to be readyto make precisestatements about the effectsof stabilizationpolicies on gross nationalproduct. This paper has focused on the role of the investmentprocess in stabilization.The IS-LM model makes it clear how importantthe negativeresponse of in- vestmentto interestrates is in limitingthe effectof expenditurepolicy and providingthe principalimmediate effect of monetarypolicy. Empirical evidenceon the interestand acceleratorresponses of investmentis weak, 30. I am grateful to BenjaminFriedman for a helpful discussion of this point. Robert E. Hall 101 however. The calculationsat the beginningof the paper do suggestthat the conventionalestimate for the effect of expenditureincreases-about $1.5 billionin GNP in the firstyear for each $1 billionof expenditure-is probablyon the high side. Indeed,perfectly reasonable assumptions give rise to effectsonly half as large.A hardlook at the limitedevidence on the IS curve makes exclusivereliance on expenditurepolicy seem an unwise approachto stabilization. The same factors that make one policy weak make the other strong. Given the uncertaintyabout these factors, especiallyabout the slope of the IS curve, it would make sense to adopt balanced combinationsof stabilizationpolicies. The negativecovariance of the effectsof the policies would makethe uncertaintyabout the effectof the total packageless than the uncertaintyabout any individualcomponent. The designof stabiliza- tion policies needs to protectagainst the very real possibilityof a flat IS curve.

APPENDIX

Parametersof the IS-LMModel

THIS APPENDIX outlinesthe derivationof the parametersof the IS-LM modelused in the text.

ConsumptionFunction

To get roughestimates of the marginalpropensities to consumeout of grossnational product, I simplyran two regressionsof the firstdifference of real consumptionof nondurablesand servicesand the first difference of realexpenditures on durableson the firstdifference of real GNP for the years 1950-76. The resultingcoefficients (actually the sum of the current and three lagged quarterlycoefficients) were 0.20 for nondurablesand servicesand 0.16 for durables,so 01 is takenas 0.36. 102 Brookings PaDers on Economic Activity, 1:1977

Money-DemandFunction

Researchon money demandis currentlyin an unsatisfactorystate be- cause of the puzzlingbehavior of interestrates relative to income and the money supplyin 1976 and 1977. StephenM. Goldfeld'scareful investiga- tions of money demandboth before and after the puzzle appearedare difficultto embedin a simpleLM curve.31First, Goldfeld finds consistently that the incomeelasticity of money demandover a one-yearperiod is less than 1/2.The result is a startlinglylarge shift in the LM curve for each billion dollars of monetaryexpansion: at least a 2 percent increase in income is necessaryto hold interestrates constantin the face of a 1 per- cent increasein the .Goldfeld's low income elasticityarises from the pronounceddownward trend in M, relativeto GNP. Since there is no other trend variablein his equation,the coefficientof log GNP is determinedlargely by the requirementthat the rate of growth of real money demandis about half as high as the rate of growthof real GNP. Adding a time trendto his equationincreases the estimatedincome elas- ticity substantially,to almost0.8. Second, Goldfeld'smost importantin- terest rate is the yield on time deposits at , which is not likely to respondvery much to monetaryor fiscalpolicy. In an effortto sort out these two problemsin adaptingGoldfeld's equa- tion for the presentpurposes, I fitted the following regressionto annual datafor M. for 1954 to 1976: log M/p = 0.56 + 0.78 log Y - 0.014 log r - 0.021t. (0.86) (0.14) (0.13) (0.005) A2 = 0.94; standard error = 0.013; p = 0.81. The numbersin parenthesesare standarderrors. The single interestrate here is the yield on four- to six-monthcommercial paper. Variants of this equation,including the use of quarterlydata, produced similar results. In all cases, the statisticalevidence in favor of the trendis unambiguousand the inclusionof the trend dramaticallyincreases the income elasticity.It also reducesthe interestelasticity, which in all caseswas smallerin magni- tudethan Goldfeld found. At probable 1977 levels (GNP of $1,325 billion and money supply

31. "The Revisited,"BPEA, 3:1973, pp. 577-638, and "The Case of the Missing Money," BPEA, 3:1976, pp. 683-730. Robert E. Hall 103 of $230 billion,both in 1972 prices), the incomeelasticity of 0.78 implies that an increaseof $1 billion in GNP will raise money demandby $0.135 billion. This income effect was used in the IS-LM model (, = 0.135). The regressionimplies that an increasein the interestrate of 100 basis points, from 5 percentto 6 percentper year, will reducereal money de- mandby $0.59 billion.By contrast,in Goldfeld'sbasic equation ("Case of the MissingMoney," table 1, firstline, p. 686), an increaseof the same amountin the commercialpaper rate alone raisesreal money demandby $1.84 billion. If both the commercialpaper rate and the rate on time depositsincrease by 100 basis points, real money demandrises by $6.13 billion, accordingto Goldfeld.As a compromiseI took the interest-rate parameterof the IS-LMmodel ('2) to be 2.00. Commentsand Discussion

ChristopherA. Sims:Hall arguesfor the view that capitalis homogeneous and flexible,for practicalpurposes, and that thereforeprice incentives can be effectivein stimulatinginvestment even when output is below trend. This is to be contrastedwith the perhapsmore widely acceptedview that at low points of the cycle excess capacityforms a heavy cloud over in- vestors'spirits, preventing price incentivesfrom brighteningthings much. Hall's view is internallyconsistent and broadlyconsistent with the exist- ing statisticalevidence, in my view. Where I may differfrom Hall is in thinkingthat the "excesscapacity as a heavy cloud"view is equallycon- sistentinternally and consistentwith the statisticalevidence. The truthis, as Hall makes apparent,we don't know much about some of the critical issuesrelated to evaluatingthe effectsof monetaryand expenditurepolicy on investment. The centralquestion is whetherit is reasonableto treat new and old capital as technicallyinterchangeable. There is no solid statisticalevi- dence that the cost of capital stronglyaffects investment (as opposed to long-runcapital stock), in my view. Estimatesthat claim to have found such an effectfall into two classes: thoseusing models in whichoutput and cost-of-capitaleffects are tied togethera priori,and those in which equity prices are introducedinto the formulafor the rental price of capital. If capitaladjusts very slowly to its equilibriumvalue, one expectsto see in- vestmentshowing strong positive correlationwith stock prices, because both investmentand stockprices will reflectexpected future yields. Thus a strong negative "effect"on investmentof the ratio of dividendyield to equityprices is not strongevidence against a view that investmentis price inelastic. But this appearsto be the only kind of evidence availablein empiricalwork. 104 Robert E. Hall 105 Hall is right to suggest that identificationproblems might well com- pletely explainthe erraticbehavior of cost-of-capitalvariables in invest- ment-equationregressions, however. In the absence of conclusive statisticalevidence, Hall presentsthree argumentsthat vintage effects are negligible.In evaluatingthese argu- ments,it is importantto have in mindthe correctcondition that will allow vintage effects to be ignored.Franklin Fisher developed that in a 1965 articlein Review of EconomicStudies: at any one time capitalof all vin- tages must have the same gross margin.This conditionis a little weaker than Hall's conditionthat their marginalproducts differ only by an ex- ponentialdepreciation factor. One can easily imagineexamples in which the Hall conditionis violated-for instance,in any situationin which in- vestors expect that capitalcurrently being purchasedwill all be replaced at roughlythe same time. Hall's first argumentfor negligiblevintage ef- fects, that it is "hardto thinkof realisticconditions" under which Fisher's conditionsare violated, is thereforeunconvincing. The Fisher capital-aggregationcondition is exactly what Hall needs for his argumentearly in the paper that short rates are all that matter in the investmentfunction. Later in the paper, Hall arguesthat it is the price elasticityof outputon old equipmentthat determinesthe degreeto which investmentresponds to changesin the price of capital. While it is truethat the priceelasticity of outputcould be highon old equipmenteven though Fisher's aggregationcondition is not close to being true, Hall's argumentis incomplete.The response of investmentto capital cost de- pendson the responseof priceto capitalcost (Hall's dju/dv) as well as on the responseof outputon old equipmentto price. If averagevariable cost on old equipmentcannot be radicallyreduced by reducingoutput on the old equipment,one gets the commonsenseresult that changesin the short interestrate that arenot expectedto persisthave little effecton investment, even if outputon old equipmentis price elastic. Hall's second argument, that vintageeffects are negligiblebecause the price elasticityof outputon old equipmentis high, thereforefounders on his havingfailed to consider vintageeffects on d,u/dv. Hall claims that the positivelysloped IS curve that emergesfrom his versionof Bischoff'sequation is a prioriimplausible. Perhaps because of a deficiencyin my stock of a prioriknowledge, I find this third argument unconvincingas well. Now for some otherissues. On the shortversus the long rate: If capital 106 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 is in infinitelyelastic supply and investmentis reversible,it is hardly surprisingthat a short rate is what matters for such a liquid asset. If putty-clay effects are important,the whole term structureis relevant. Even without putty-clayeffects, if capital is in inelastic supply, the ex- pected rate of changeof the price of capitalgoods entersthe servicecost. The expectedrate of changeis not derivablefrom the historyof capital- goods prices in general, and in fact, under some assumptions,may be embodiedin the gap betweenthe long and the shortrate. Expectationallags are not so easily handledas Hall suggests.First, if the autoregressivestructure of "desiredcapital" is not second-orderPascal as in Hall'sexample, it couldeasily happen that expectational lags lengthen ratherthan shorten the estimatedlag distributionrelative to the physical- lag distribution.More important,expectational lags for eitherthe cost of capitalor outputwill in generalinvolve both variables.Thus relativesizes of sumsof coefficientsin distributedlags bearno necessaryrelation to the policy-relevantprice and output elasticities. Measurementerror, on which Hall relies to cast doubt on the small coefficientsin the "q theory"regressions, does not in fact createa bias of determinatesign here. It seems quite likely that fluctuationsin the 'sevaluation of intangiblecapital are positively correlatedwith fluctuationsin the stock market'sevaluation of tangible capital. Thus measurement-errorbias from this source might actually tend to inflate ratherthan reduce the estimatedcoefficient on q. Hall is rightto suggestthat simultaneityproblems are probablycritical to whatcomes out of "'investment"or ""function regressions. Hall's idea for testingfor simultaneityis not a good one, however.The idea that long-runeffects of outputon net investmentmust be zero is plausiblein a model with static technology.But the underlyingreason is that in such a modelstationary fluctuation in outputcannot plausibly lead to unbounded variationin capital-outputratios. It is also implausible,however, that with static functions and stationaryfluctuations in income, desired wealth-incomeratios wander unboundedly. There is no carefullyworked out theory of saving that implies a relationof the level of saving to the level of outputin the long run.Thus there is no good argumentthat simul- taneous-equationsbias will bias sums of coefficientson output in net- investmentequations away from one. So where does the levels relationcome from?In part, from statistical artifact.Plausible assumptionssuggest that the negative part of the lag Robert E. Hall 107 distributionon outputshould be long and flat. It is easy to show that such long, flat, low tails are difficultto estimate,and that thereis likely to be a strong temptationto truncatethe lag distributionbefore the long thin tail and end up with only the short,fat, positivepart. Also, in reality,non- stationarymovement in technologymay occur. And finally,Hall claims to adapt his test for a stable capital-outputratio to a gross-investment equationunder general putty-clayassumptions; but in a general putty- clay model thereis no exogenous,fixed rate of depreciation.Since Hall's adaptedtest rests on use of a fixed depreciationrate, its interpretationis at best debatable.

FrancoModigliani: By way of introduction,I shouldexplain that, as MIT colleagues, and I agreedto avoid praisingeach other, and insteadto takeour gloves off. When I tried to formulatemy commenton this paper, I recalled the famousfable by EdmundPhelps in his classic paper on the golden rule, and I shall use a similartale. I imaginethat the prince of the realm de- cides one nightthat he wantssomebody to showthat fiscal policy is power- less and monetarypolicy very powerful.He asks his adviser,"Who is the most brilliantyoung economistin the realmto carryout this task?" The designatedman then is askedto do that.He does it withgreat relish, andfinds that it is just his cup of tea. For severalmonths he worksas hard as he can, makingthe case-without violatingconspicuously the rules of the game. The outcomeof that effortis now before us. It is full of interestingand challengingideas, even though it is some- times irritating,and even thoughit takes several days to read it because the readerhas to be carefulabout what mightbe slippedby him. But for all its brilliance,I doubt that it will persuademany that the first year's effects of fiscal and monetarypolicy are, respectively,as puny and as giganticas they arereported to be in table 1! But let us follow our hero on the path that leads to table 1. Of course, the brilliantyoung man knows that, to make monetarypolicy powerful and fiscalpolicy powerless,it takes a very steep LM curve and a very flat IS curve. He furtherknows that three factors stand in the way of a flat IS curve.One is adjustmentlags; the secondis the putty-claytechnology; and the third is the fact that money affects short-terminterest rates promptlyand directly, while investmentdepends on long-terminterest rates. Brookinps Paners on Economic Activity. 1:1977 I need not say much about the first issue, the lags, because even our brillianteconomist, after all, cannotbudge the findingof substantiallags, whetherthese be due to putty-clayor other reasons. A majornovelty in Hall's attackis his criticismof the traditionalview that investment depends on the long-term interest rate. He argues, instead,that the only ratethat mattersis the short-terminterest rate. One may well acceptthe propositionthat short-terminterest rates may matterfor investment.Stephen Marglin once argued,quite rightly,that a single investmentproject must meet two tests. One is the long-runtest: it must be profitableat the currentlong rate. If it meets that test, the next questionis, "Couldit be profitablypostponed?" That answerdepends, es- sentially,on the relationbetween the currentshort and long rates. If the projectmeets the firsttest, but the shortrate is too high, it may be worth- while to postpone,because the projectwill not pay for itself in the near future. If, on the other hand, the short rate is below the long rate, then the secondtest is immaterialbecause any projectthat meets the long-ratetest will also beat the short rate. It is only when the short rate is above the long ratethat the doubletest applies.In earlywork on the MPSmodel, we looked for evidencethat shortrates mattered when they were above long rates.We did not get any significantresults, but in principlethat is a valid point. But how can one claim that only the short rate matters?One possible way is to imaginethat capitalis just putty: the firmhas a certainquantity of it, but it can disposeof as muchas it wantsin the next period.Clearly, if the firmcan resell the putty in the next period at a known price, it need only be concernedwith the interestcost for the currentperiod-that is, the shortrate. But our economistmakes a far moregeneral claim. He con- tends that with putty-puttytechnology it is immaterialwhether or not the capitalgoods can be readilyresold. Actually,this claim can be shown to be valid only in one special case-namely, on the assumptionthat the quantityof "putty"capital that the firmis consideringholding today on the basis of the shortrate is less than (or at least not morethan) the quan- tity it would want to have tomorrow,after allowingfor the depreciation betweentoday and tomorrow.Under these circumstances,the firmmakes a decisionnow that has no bearingon whatit will have tomorrow,because tomorrowit can add whateveris needed. In that event, our economistis Robert E. Hall 109 absolutelyright: only the short-termrate will matter.In principle, the one-day rate is all that is needed to decide on the amountof capital to hold each day. The merefact that the putty-puttymodel can lead to this absurdconse- quence is a good reason why it makes no sense. As soon as putty-clay characteristicsare recognized,the whole argumentdisappears, and in- vestors have to worry about the whole future path of interest rates. In particular,especially when one recognizeslimited ex post substitution,it will normallybe the case that for long-livedinvestments what mattersis the long-runinterest rate-except when the short rate is so much above the long ratethat it maybe a sufficientbarrier to investment.One wonders whetherHall is reallyserious when he states that it is "clearthat the ser- vice priceof capitaldepends on the short-runinterest rate." Since the argumentabout the short rate rests to a large extent on putty-putty,our authorhas to destroythe competingputty-clay hypoth- esis. That attacktakes many forms in the paper.First he sets forth a num- ber of arguments,old and new, as to why theremay be significantex post substitutionbetween labor and capital.As far as I can see, the most rele- vant one is that even thoughthe ratio of plant to labor may be fixed per unit of time, the substitutioncan occur by way of varyingthe numberof hours per year that a plant is combinedwith labor; thus a higherrental rate for capitalmight well, in principle,lead to introducingan extrashift. But, even grantingthe validityof this argumentin principle,I would ex- pect the elasticity of substitutionthrough this mechanismto be quite smallbecause of extremediscontinuities. To be sure, in the shortrun one can changeutilization through overtime and some extra shifts;but in the long run, one mustbasically operate with one shift or two (or three), but cannot respondto a 10 percentrise in the rental rate by addinga small fractionof a shift. On the whole, I see Hall's argumentsas merelyprovid- ing one more illustrationof the propositionthat nothingin economicsis ever completelyblack or white. If asked: "Is there never any ex post substitutionbetween capital and labor?" I wouldhave answered:"Never? Well, hardlyever!" After Hall's paper, my answerremains pretty much the same. But the main attackon putty-claytakes the form of a severe critique of the majorempirical work in this area, which is that of Bischoff.As a preliminaryto that attack, our author argues that, when investmentis 110 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 expressedas a functionof a distributedlag on income, estimatesof the parametersof the functionmay be biased.We all knowthat, whenthere is simultaneity,this problemdoes exist to some degree. With this background,Hall goes into a rathertechnical and lengthy discussionof resultsof a Bischoff-typeequation fitted by him using actual investment,ignoring several other existingputty-clay equations based on new ordersand hence less subjectto simultaneitybias (for example,that of Ando, Modigliani,Rasche, and Turnovskyin International Economic Review, in June 1974). He arguesthat his Bischoff-typeequation implies either an unrealisticallyhigh rate of depreciationor else that net invest- ment dependson the level andnot merelyon the rateof changeof (desired) output.From thishe concludesthat the equationmust be subjectto bias so severe as to make it of little relevance,except possiblyfor furtherstudy. My interpretationof his resultsis ratherdifferent: the coefficientsof his equationimply merelythat the acceleratoreffect-the cumulatedre- sponse of net investmentto a step changein output-is somewhaton the low side comparedwith the long-runresponse of gross investmentto a constantlevel of output,which represents, of course,replacement invest- ment. Thisconclusion turns out to hold also for the equationsof Ando and his associates,mentioned above, though in lesserdegree. As notedby Hall, the two responsescan be reconciledby assuminga sufficientlyhigh rate of depreciation.But even for Ando and his colleagues,the requiredrate is above 7 percentper quarter,which is not very realistic.One must agree, therefore,that the estimatedcoefficients are likely to be somewhatbiased. However, Hall concludes, without apparentjustification, that the bias consistsin an overestimateof the (long-run) responseto the level of out- put. My own calculations,on the other hand, suggestthat this long-run response is broadly consistentwith a reasonabledepreciation rate and the average capital-outputratio; the bias is, instead, in the estimated acceleratorresponse which is somewhatlow. Thereis no reasonto believe that this bias is particularlyrelated to simultaneity-especially when the dependentvariable is new orders.A more likely majorexplanation is at- tenuation due to errors of measurement,including misspecifications of some of the independentvariables. This is but a smallblemish for a rather complex, highly nonlinear,equation that otherwisemakes a lot of sense, especiallywhen even Hall's resultsprovide strong confirmation that the patternof responseto output and to the interestrate are quite different, which is the differentialimplication of the putty-claymodel. Robert E. Hall 111 It is, therefore,good that in table 1 Hall has providedestimates of the differentialpolicy implications of putty-clayas well as putty-putty,though in my view the relevanceof this table is most doubtful.In the firstplace, Hall's estimatesof the putty-clayresponse are ratherarbitrary. The esti- matesof Ando and his associatessuggest a sloweraccelerator response in the first year, especially after allowing for the lag of deliveriesbehind orders.Hall's assumptionof one-eighthresponse to interestrates is no- whereexplained, but seemshigh. Under putty-clay, the responseis related basically to the depreciationrate, and for total investmentthat rate is likely to be ratherless than one-tenth.But the main factor that puts the resultsof table 1 beyond the pale, in my view, is the combinationof the following assumptions,which are questionableindividually but plainly incredibletaken together. The firstis the crucialassumption-designed to insurea very steep LM curveand defendedmost unconvincinglyin an ap- pendix-that the demandfor money is extremelyinterest inelastic, and hence short-terminterest rates are extremelyvolatile; a 1 percentchange in the money supplyis assumedto reducethe short-termrate by roughly 25 percent,while a 1 percentrise in real income increasesit by over 15 percent! These estimates are many times larger than those implied by Goldfeld'smoney-demand equations or, even more by the MPS's.All of the extremeresults of table 1, especiallywith respect to changesin M1,be- come readilyunderstandable when one recognizesthat this first assump- tion is combinedwith two more: (1) that investmentdecisions respond exclusivelyto that volatile short-termrate-specifically the rate on four- to six-month commercialpaper; and (2) that through putty-putty,a changeof 100 basis points in that rate will producepromptly investment of $84 billion (in 1972 prices)! No wonder that, for most of the cases considered,a change in M1 producesan ultra-monetaristfirst-year effect close to, or even largerthan, the currentvelocity of circulation,whereas fiscal policy can hardlyget off the ground. Finally, let me mention one generalcomplaint about the relevanceof the comparisonsbetween fiscal and monetarypolicy presentedin table 1, even if I thoughtthe entriesin the table had any empiricalrelevance. I submit that wheneverwe look at the effects of stimulativechanges in taxes and governmentexpenditures, what must be kept constantis the in- terest rate, not the money supply.Why would anyone want to keep the money supplyconstant if the objectiveis to stimulatethe economy?And 112 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 this shouldhold with specialforce for those who believe in the potencyof money. Only if the governmentis tryingto increaseits expenditureat the expense of investmentshould it keep the money supply constant.But if it is trying to increaseincome-and not to reduce investmentor to in- creaseinterest rates (for balance-of-payment reasons, say) -then it would just wastepart of its effortby keepingthe money supplyconstant. In the present state of the economy, for instance, we ought to have expansionarymonetary policy and expansionaryfiscal policy, and stop the nonsenseabout the fear of inflationbeing linkedto monetarygrowth. If inflationis the main worry,we shouldnot want any stimulation.If we want stimulation,we shoulduse monetarypolicy to reinforceand not to offsetfiscal policy. By the time I was throughwith the paper,I actuallyfelt relieved.I had been exposed to the most seriousand brilliantattack I could imagineon severalissues on which I have strongconvictions, like the importanceof the long rate, putty-clay,a first-yearfiscal multiplierin excess of one. I was glad to see that my views came out basicallyunscathed by this paper.

WilliamBrainard: I want to commenton JamesTobin's theory of invest- ment which Hall describesas a major competitorto Jorgenson'stheo- retical framework,and to offer some observationsabout the Jorgenson- Hall theory. One major featureof Tobin's approachis its stress on the differencebetween the requiredreturn to capitaland the returnon finan- cial assets.The reasonsinclude differences in maturity,but perhapsmore important,encompass differences in various types of risk-of , of default,of changingdemand and technology. In order to understandthe mechanismby which monetarypolicy or other financialevents affect investmentit would be desirableto have a directmeasure of the requiredrate on capital.Such measuresare difficult to come by preciselybecause the distinctiveuncertainties on capitalmen- tioned abovemake it hardto identifyits expectedprofitability. Empirical work by Tobin and myself and by Modigliani,as well as evidenceon the historicalreturn to investment,suggests that the requiredrate on capital is not only substantiallyhigher than the requiredrates on bills or bonds, but is far fromperfectly correlated with them. Tobin'sq model of investment,empirically implemented by John Cic- colo of Boston College, shortcutsthe need for a separatecalculation of expectedprofitability and the requiredrate. Althoughvariations in q re- Robert E. Hall 113 flect changesboth in the requiredrate of returnand in the market'scal- culationof marginalprofitability, their separate identification isn't needed if firms are behavingin accordancewith the q model. Firms will invest when the securitiesmarket places a high value on investmentrelative to its cost. The financialmarkets do the job of calculatingfor them. Why don't firmsadjust their capital stock instantaneouslyto maintain the equilibriumvalue of q? This is analogousto the classicquestion of why investmentdemand should remain finite with changesin the interestrate. Tobin'sview, in commonwith that of many otherwriters, is that costs of adjustmentof the capitalstock, both to the firmand to the economy,are importantelements in the explanation.Hall is right,however, in suggest- ing that adjustmentcosts are not a necessaryfeature of the q model. One could accept that model withoutbelieving that the adjustmentcosts are important,or believe the costs are importantwithout accepting a formu- lation that works through the financial market's of capital goods. In principle,in a competitiveworld, increasingcosts and capacity limitationsin the constructionand capital-goodsindustries show up as a rising supply price of capital goods, and do not enter the investment- demandequation. To make sense of many macro models one has to as- sume that such supply considerationsare unimportant,or that they are implicitlyincorporated in the investment"demand" equation or schedule. Hall objectsto inclusionof supplyconsiderations in the aggregate-demand equation,but does not claim that they are unimportantto understanding the level of investment.He owes us either an explicitjustification for ex- cluding flow considerationsfrom the supply side, or a capital-goods supply equationin his model. Indeed, if because of costs of adjustment internalto the firmor some other reason firmsneed to predictthe price of capital goods, the supply side is relevantto investmentdemand. For example,if firmsare awarethat the supplyprice is a functionof operating rates in the capital-goodsindustry, then they are likely to view the exist- ing relativeprices of capitalgoods as unusuallyhigh (low) when operat- ing ratesof thatindustry are extremelyhigh (low). Hall follows Jorgensonin buildingthe theory of investmentaround the concept of the service price of capital.According to Hall, it is quite unambiguousthat the service price should be based on the short-term rate of interest.In the absenceof marketsfor used capitalgoods a crucial elementin the argumentis that firmsnever have to worry about getting stuck with excess capital;they are assumedalways to want more capital 114 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 tomorrowanyway. At the aggregatelevel that has been true since the ,but aggregationconceals the variationof experience amongfirms. It seemsfair to say that any firmthat goes bankrupt,or finds itself boardingup windows,should have been worryingabout that possibil- ity whenit undertookinvestment. The problemfor the firmis exacerbated by the heterogeneityof capital goods. A firm that is buying new trucks may have too many machinetools. If I ever find a corporationthat be- haves in the Jorgenson-Hallfashion, looking only one year aheadin mak- ing twenty-yearinvestments and respondingonly to the currentbill rate, I'll sell short. Aggregation,of course, can conceal-even mitigate-a multitudeof sins,but I see no reasonto believe that the -maximizing behaviorof a firm assumedto have the characteristicsof the aggregate should be a good approximationof the aggregatebehavior of individual firms which face imperfectcapital-goods markets and invest in specific typesof capital. - Hall and Jorgensongive the impressionthat it is straightforwardto constructa theoryof investmentaround the concept of a serviceprice of capitalwhich also includesa distributedlag of investmentin responseto its determinants.In fact, it is quite a trick.It is difficultif not impossible to find conditionsthat justifythe use of the serviceprice of capitalbased on the short rate and yet allow for the many circumstancesthat prevent the firm from continuouslyequating the actual to the desired stock of capital.Hall follows Jorgensonin assumingthat the processof designing, ordering,and installingcapital follows a fixed time schedule.In my view, adjustmentcosts are the explanationof the impliedlags, ratherthan an alternativeexplanation, as Hall states.In a theoreticalinvestigation I am reluctantto treat the lags as entirelymechanical rather than the conse- quence of an economiccalculation. Assuming they are mechanical,how- ever, why doesn't the Jorgenson-Hallfirm manipulateorders to keep capitalprecisely on target (assumingthat some capitalis deliveredin the periodorders are placed) or on the expectedtarget only the minimumlag away?Hall gets out of that bind by assumingthat capital with short de- livery lags cannot substitutefor capitalwith longer deliverylags. Types of capital are now definedby their deliverylag! How is it that capital goods that cannotsubstitute for each other duringthe investmentprocess end up as homogeneouscapital in a Cobb-Douglasproduction function? If each lag does referto a distincttype of capitaland productionprocess, why is capitalof differenttypes purchasedin fixedproportions? Why isn't Robert E. Hall 115 the firm able to place separate orders for each type? Why, therefore, doesn'tthe "lagdistribution" reflect the time patternof expectedneeds for capital of varioustypes ratherthan the mechanicaldelivery schedule? If capitalgoods are complements,how can the deliveryof capitalwith the shortestlag affectoutput and "its"quasi-rent prior to the deliveryof com- plementarycapital with longer lags? Hall assertsthat his most sluggishinvestment response in table 1, which assumesone-eighth of the long-runresponse in the firstyear, is consistent with Ciccolo'sempirical estimates of the q model.Hall's derivationof the relationshipbetween I and q involves a numberof assumptionsand ap- proximationsthat preventone from havingmuch confidencein the asser- tion. Hall ignores the lag of approximatelythree quartersin Ciccolo's investmentequation. In calculatingq he does not discountexcess quasi- rents,even thoughsome of them are far in the future.This tends to mini- mize the apparentdiscrepancy between the desired and actual capital associatedwith a given q. He calculatesquasi-rents separately on capital of "differentlags," even thoughhe uses the characteristicsof the aggre- gate productionfunction to estimate the quasi-rentsof each type, and thensimply adds them up. It seems difficultto reconcile the observed deviations of q from its equilibriumvalue with the view that these deviationssimply reflect the ex- cess quasi-rentsthat accruewhile deliverytakes place. Since 1960, q has rangedfrom 0.75 to 1.36 accordingto the Councilof EconomicAdvisers (up to 1.67 accordingto Ciccolo). The inconsistencyof fluctuationsof this magnitudeand Hall's view can be seen by taking a set of extreme assumptions,all tendingto minimizethe amountof investmentrequired to restoreequilibrium. Supposequasi-rents are not discounted,and that the marketassumes that currentquasi-rents go on forever.Then a changein requiredrate that increasesq from 1 to 1.3 implies (for the Cobb-Douglas) that desired capital is 30 percent greaterthan actual. If complete adjustmenttook place in ten years, and the investmentwas spreadout evenly ratherthan bunchedat the beginning,as assumedby Hall, this wouldimply increasing investmentby about4.2 percentof GNP for each of the ten years (assum- ing Hall's barelycredible capital-output ratio of 1.4)! In fact, of course, Ciccolo's investmentequation implies substantially less investmentin the firstyear than is given by this calculation;and the increasein desiredcapital implied by an increasein q of 30 percent,tak- 116 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 ing account of discountingand the eliminationof excess quasi-rentsas investmenttakes place, is muchgreater than 30 percent--probablysome- thing on the orderof 60 to 90 percent.The fractionof the long-runre- sponse in the first year impliedby Ciccolo's equationis more like one- thirty-secondthan the one-eighthused in Hall's table 1, even ignoringthe lags in Ciccolo'sequation. Hall stressesthe fact that in his model, no matterhow muchhe waters downhis beliefs aboutthe responseof investmentto interestrates, he gets a small expendituremultiplier and a large money multiplier.This is hardlysurprising given the assumedinelasticity of the demandfor money and the use of the bill rate in both the demand-for-moneyand investment equations.Hall's interest elasticity of the demandfor money is essentially an averageof zero and Goldfeld'sestimate, and I assumeothers will take him to task for the cavalierestimation of this crucialparameter. Of equal importanceis his relianceon a single shortrate to equilibratethe model. As my commentsabove indicate,I do not believe there are strongtheo- retical or empiricalreasons for using the short rate in the investment equation.Hall concedesthe importanceof lags in the deliveryof capital goods, and that by itself is enoughto rule out a very shortrate. On Hall's assumptionthat the mean deliverylag is about two years, the current three-monthbill rate is surely a poor approximationof what he should be interestedin, even in termsof his own model. The expectedshort rate implicitin borrowinglong now, and lendinglong a year from now, is far from perfectlycorrelated with the bill rate, and even advocates of the expectationstheory allow for a risk premiumthat makeslong rateshigher than short rates. That concession alone changes the relevant elasticity calculation.If a short rate were to be used, I would not want to use the bill rate or the short rate implicitin the returnon other financialassets, but the short-termrequired rate on capital,which is not likely to be highly correlatedwith them. If for eitherrisk or maturityreasons, capital is not a perfectsubstitute for bills, there will be slippagebetween the federal funds or bill rates, whichare directlyaffected by monetarypolicy, and the requiredrate rele- vant to the IS curve.The greaterthis slippage,the less direct and potent is the influenceof the FederalReserve on investment,and the less gov- ernmentexpenditures will crowdout privateinvestment. I hastento add that using the requiredrate on capital,or some other stock-marketvari- Robert E. Hall 117 able, in the demand-for-moneyequation would not be the solution.The erroris in believingthat the rates relevantto these two marketsare tied tightlyand mechanicallytogether in eitherthe short or the long run.

RobertE. Hall: After a very determinedeffort to explainwhy my IS curve is so flat,I learnthat what is reallythe matter-in the view of my critics- is that my LM curve is too steep! Much of the criticismof the paper re- lates not so much to its conclusionsabout the investmentequation but to the way that equationis embeddedin a model of the rest of the economy. Withinthe realmof the investmentequation itself, some of my discus- sants are worriedthat the entiretheoretical apparatus requires the belief that investmentundertaken today will not be so largeas to push expected investmentnext year to zero. None of the marginalconditions that are crucial in my restatementof investmenttheory are relevant if planned futureinvestment is zero. This is the sense in which the nonnegativityof gross investmentis a qualificationof the theory.Though I defendthe use of a theory that ignoresthe constraintonly as an approximation,I think it is a prettygood approximation.The key issue is not whetherinvestors find themselves regrettingpast investment,but whether they ever find theirplanning process constrained by the belief that they will need more capitalthis year than next year. Reductionsin demandare almost always unpleasantsurprises. ChristopherSims raised the point that the use of a service price of capitalrequires that stringentcapital-aggregation conditions hold. Again, I defend the use of a service price as a good approximationto a world in which the conditions do not actuallyhold. Sims' criticismwould be much more convincingif he could give a practicalexample of a case in whichthe formulaseriously misled an . WilliamBrainard pointed out that investorspresumably discount the future excess rents in forming their values of q, and that this would lengthen the implied distributionof delivery lags. He is right, but the magnitudeof the bias is small, and I would guess that it is dominatedby the bias in the oppositedirection caused by measurementerrors. and I have discussed the evidence on Bischoff's putty-clayinvestment function to the point of complete agreementon the facts, particularlythat there is an importantdiscrepancy between the short-runand long-run responses of investmentto changes in output. 118 Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 Modigliani defends Bischoff's equation as a workable approximation, while I am concernedabout its value as a measureof the importanceof the putty-clayphenomenon. Everyreader of the paperseems to have a differentreason for thinking thatthe long-terminterest rate belongs in the investmentequation in place of or alongsidethe shortrate. WilliamBrainard pointed out that the logic of my model requiresthat the term of the relevantinterest rate be about as long as the deliverylag, not necessarilythe same term as is generally used in money-demandfunctions. He also criticizes the expectations theoryof the termstructure on which my derivationrests. I would reiter- ate that that theory,in turn,rests on the explicithypothesis that shortand long assets are perfect substitutes.This is good theory, even if the hy- pothesisis wrong.Franco Modigliani argued that the putty-clayhypothe- sis completelyinvalidates my demonstrationthat only the shortrate should matter.The paper concedes this as a matterof exact theory,but claims that the formulabased on the shortrate is a workableapproximation. His statementthat putty-claymakes the long rate alone the relevantinterest rate for investmentis unconvincingto me. Investorsface the same issue of optimal schedulingof investmentunder putty-clay as under putty- putty.Working through the schedulingproblem will give the same condi- tions as appearin my derivation.Then it is just a questionof developing a usefulapproximation. Modigliani and Stephen Goldfeld (in his remarksrecorded below) raise questionsabout the money-demandfunction that I use to close the model in order to work out the implicationsof alternativeinvestment functions.Most of the disagreementrelates to my inclusionof a time trend in the money-demandequation, which Goldfeld attacksas unwarranted by theory.I don'tknow why theoryrules out an upwardtrend in the pro- ductivityof the use of money;it seems to me that technicalchange is just as importanthere as anywhere.In any case, arguingthat the coefficient on the time trendshould be zero puts the econometricianin a bind when it turnsout to be significantlydifferent from zero. The rest of the disagree- ment comes from the fairlylong distributedlag on income that Goldfeld finds.Why do people take so long to adjust?We disagreeleast about the magnitudeof the interest-ratecoefficient in the money-demandfunction itself. Obviously,my own work in this area is very casual. One of the majorlessons I have learnedfrom the discussionis the need for a thor- Robert E. Hall 119 ough empiricalinvestigation of aggregateasset supplies and demands, includingmoney.

GeneralDiscussion

StephenGoldfeld expressedhis dissatisfactionwith the LM curve de- veloped in the appendix,which is a criticalingredient in Hall's calcula- tions. He arguedthat the inclusionof a time trendin the money-demand functionwas not consistentwith theory, accordingto which the trend in income and in interestrates should explain the trend in velocity. - feld stressedthat, despiteHall's "markup"of the interestelasticity in the regressionequation, Hall's LM curve was dramaticallysteeper than the one implied by Goldfeld's results. In particular,Hall's estimatesimply that a 1 percentincrease in GNP, given M1,raises interest rates by about 17 percent,or about 85 basis points at his illustrative5 percentinterest rate.In contrast,Goldfeld's equations imply a rise of only 15 basis points if both interestrates are allowedto adjust,or 50 basis points if the time depositrate is held constant.To Goldfeld,the estimatesof 15 to 50 basis pointsprovided a plausiblebound for the steepnessof the LM curve, and Hall'scurve clearly lies outsidethis range. A numberof participantsstressed both the importanceand the im- plausibilityof the assumptionin the Jorgenson-Hallmodel that no in- vestoris everstuck with excessivestocks of anycapital good. In theirview, the focus on short-terminterest rates and near-termprofitability in Hall's paperrested on that assumption.John Shoven pointed out that the overall investmentfunction is an aggregationof microdemands for capitalgoods; the aggregationmakes clear the importanceof the compositionof aggre- gate demand,the compositionof the existingcapital stock, and the vari- ation in rates of depreciationacross sectors of the economy.When these variousmicroeconomic factors are recognized, the probabilityseems over- whelmingthat at least some firmswill be constrainedby the zero floor on gross investment.Benjamin Friedman argued that the mere concernby investorsthat they mightbe stuckwith excessiveamounts of capitalgoods is enoughto invalidatethe Hall view. He stressedthe transactionscosts involvedin acquiringand financingcapital goods, as well as the heteroge- neity of capital goods that Brainardhad noted. These elements make 120 BrookingsPapers on Economic Activity, 1:1977 liquidityimportant to a firmand give it cause for concernabout the com- position of its assets and liabilities.Firms have choices in financingin- vestmentamong long debt, short debt, and equities,and a furtherchoice on the timingof fundingout fixed-investmentprojects. Friedman agreed with Hall that any theory of investmentdemand has to simplify these complexdecisions. But he disagreedwith Hall's strategyof simplification by focusingon the short-terminterest rate; in his view, the andequity yield would be the preferredplace to start. All of this, Friedmancon- tended,bore on whathe consideredto be a key questionneglected in Hall's analysis: What is the proper discount rate to apply to expected future returnsfrom the acquisitionof a capitalgood, given that ownershipof the capitalasset has implicationsfor the structureof the firm'sliabilities? MartinFeldstein reminded the groupthat the Hall-Jorgensonconcept of the rentalprice or cost of capitalis an amalgam,reflecting the interest rate on , the -priceratio on equities, and a variety of tax variablesas well. Indeed,Feldstein recalled, in some of theirinitial work the interestrate was assumedconstant, and yet the cost of capitalvaried a good deal because of changesin the tax laws. Feldstein saw no theo- retical presumptionthat investmentwould respond with equal speed or magnitudeto changes in all componentsof the cost of capital. For example,a changein interestrates and a changein tax depreciationrules mighthave the same impacton the cost of capital,and yet have different impacts on the optimal replacementdecision and hence on scrapping capital goods. Feldstein suspected that, even in a putty-clay world, changesin the cost of capitalthat affectoptimal replacement may lead to especiallyrapid responses of grossinvestment. Feldstein also commented that, even if one grantedthat desiredgross investmentis alwayspositive, the exclusivefocus on short-runcalculations would not be justifiedin a putty-claytechnology. If an investingfirm locks itself into a particular capital-laborratio, it must worry about the cost of capitalin the future; for one thing, its competitorswill be makinginvestments in the future based on capitalcosts that prevailat the time. Pentti Kouri contrastedthe standardKeynesian theory of investment that he accepted with Hall's formulation.In the standardtheory, the capitalstock is fixedin the shortrun, while the valuationof capitalis vari- able; the latter is determinedby capitalizingexpected returns on invest- ment goods at prevailinginterest rates. The values attachedto capital assets, in turn, determinethe output of new investmentgoods, given the Robert E. Hall 121 productioncosts or supplyprice of capital goods. In the long run, how- ever, the price of capitalbecomes essentially constant, matching long-run productioncosts; meanwhile, the stock of capitalbecomes a variableand is determinedby the demandfor capital services.As Kouri interpreted them, Jorgensonand Hall really offer a theoryof the demandfor capital services,which is thus a theoryof long-runcapital stock, but not a theory of investment.Tobin, on the otherhand, offersa short-runtheory of how capitalassets are evaluatedand thus of how investmentis motivated. In this framework,Kouri saw the short-terminterest rate as the key to investmentdecisions only in the unrealisticcase in whichthe capitalstock is completely adjustable-essentially, a liquid asset. In that world, de- mand and supply for capital servicesare always in balance and there is no problemin determininginvestment. MartinNeil Baily approvedof Hall'smethodology of focusingon basic issues ratherthan attemptingto distill point estimatesfrom time-series regressions.But Baily sharedKouri's concern about the distinctionbe- tween capital stock and capitalservices. In particular,he felt that hours of capitalservices rather than capitalstock should enterinto the produc- tion function. The decision to use capital for more hours was different from a substitutionin techniquethat altered capital-laborproportions per hourof work. EdwardGramlich and LawrenceKlein arguedthat Hall's fiscal multi- plierswere biaseddownward. Gramlich suggested, first, that the marginal propensityto consume over a full year may be significantlylarger than the 0.36 figureused by Hall. Second,he felt that a macro model should allow for an inventoryaccelerator that is distinctfrom and more rapid than a generalinvestment accelerator. Klein underlinedthe critical role of strong inventoryresponses in Americanbusiness cycles. He regarded a figureof roughly 1?/2 for the expendituremultiplier over a one-year period as a well-establishedeconometric finding. Replying to Gramlich's firstpoint, Hall foundit hardto see how the MPC out of GNP could much exceed 0.36. Even if the short-runMPC out of disposableincome were close to one, which few economistsbelieve, the response of disposable incometo changesin GNP is sharplylimited by taxes and otherinfluences to a value of aroundone-half. His parameteris the productof these two.