Conceptual Barriers to a Unified Theory of Physics 1 Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Conceptual Barriers to a Unified Theory of Physics 1 Introduction Conceptual barriers to a unified theory of physics Dennis Crossley∗ Dept. of Physics, University of Wisconsin-Sheboygan, Sheboygan, WI 53081 August 31, 2012 Abstract The twin pillars of twentieth-century physics, quantum theory and general relativity, have conceptual errors in their foundations, which are at the heart of the repeated failures to combine these into a single unified theory of physics. The problem with quantum theory is related to the use of the point-particle model, and the problem with general relativity follows from a misinterpretation of the significance of the equivalence principle. Correcting these conceptual errors leads to a new model of matter called the space wave model which is outlined here. The new perspective gained by space wave theory also makes it clear that there are conceptual errors in the two main thrusts of twenty-first- century theoretical physics, string theory and loop quantum gravity. The string model is no more satisfactory than the point-particle model and the notion that space must be quantized is, frankly, nonsensical. In this paper I examine all of these conceptual errors and suggest how to correct them so that we can once again make progress toward a unified theory of physics. 1 Introduction { the challenge of the unification program The goal of theoretical physics is to construct a single unified description of fundamental particles and their interactions, but flaws in the foundations of physics have prevented physi- cists from achieving this goal. In this essay I examine conceptual errors that have led to this impasse and propose alternatives which break this impasse and let us once again move forward toward the goal of a unified theory of physics. The history of theoretical physics in the twentieth century is characterized by two suc- cesses and one frustrating failure. The successes are, of course, relativity theory[1] and quantum theory[2]. The failure is the inability to combine these two theories into a single unified theory of physics. Built upon the foundations of quantum theory, the standard model of particle physics gives us a model of the elementary particles and their interactions (ex- cluding gravity)[3]. Built upon the foundations of special relativity, Einstein's general theory of relativity gives us a model of the gravitational interaction but says nothing about ele- mentary particles[4]. These two theories use profoundly different concepts and methods and all attempts to construct a unified theory by forming a direct link between them have been unsuccessful. As we will see below, the difficulty lies deeper than merely an incompatibility of the methods of these two theories; the fundamental concepts on which these theories are constructed contain inconsistencies which preclude their successful unification. ∗[email protected] 1 Early efforts, by Einstein and others, to construct a unified theory of physics involved attempts to incorporate the electromagnetic field into the formalism of general relativity[5]. The goal of this early work was a unified field theory, built on the foundation of general relativity, describing the gravitational and electromagnetic interactions of matter in a unified mathematical formalism. With the discovery of the nuclear interactions, it became acknowl- edged that the goal of the unified field theory program was too limited. With no apparent way of incorporating the nuclear interactions into the geometric approach of general relativity, this approach was abandoned. Subsequent efforts have, instead, taken quantum field theory as the foundation. With the successes of gauge theories to describe both the electromagnetic and the nuclear interactions[6], some efforts have been made to incorporate gravity into this formalism by expanding the gauge group to include the gauge group of general relativity[7]. As we enter the twenty-first century, these unification efforts have morphed into the programs of string theory[8] and loop quantum gravity[9]. String theory attempts to adapt quantum field theory using one-dimensional strings instead of point particles, while loop quantum gravity attempts to incorporate quantum concepts directly into general relativity. But neither of these programs addresses the conceptual problems underlying quantum theory and relativity theory upon which they are built, and therefore have little more chance of success than their twentieth-century predecessors. Thus, all efforts to date to construct a unified theory of physics have taken general rela- tivity and quantum field theory, and the conceptual foundations upon which they are built, and have attempted to combine them in some way, using one or the other as a foundation. But a critical examination of the conceptual foundations of these theories exposes a funda- mental error in the conceptual foundations of each of them, and it becomes clear that neither general relativity nor quantum field theory nor their extensions in the form of string theory and loop quantum gravity are adequate foundations upon which to build a unified theory of all interactions. Both general relativity and quantum field theory appear to be \correct" theories in the sense that they both give correct predictions for the behavior of matter, but correct predic- tions, though necessary, is not a sufficient criterion for choosing a final theory. In the context of the unification program, we must also consider the generalizability of a theory, and on this criterion both general relativity and quantum field theory fail. We begin our search for a new foundation for fundamental physics with a critical analysis of the fundamental concepts upon which our current theories are built. 2 Barrier #1: the particle model The particle concept[10] has proven to be extremely useful in virtually all areas of classical physics, regardless of the intrinsic size of the object being modeled. For example, objects as large as the Sun and the Earth are adequately modeled as point particles in Newtonian 2 gravity theory, and elementary particles can be modeled as point particles in Maxwell's elec- tromagnetic theory (as long as the interaction distances are not too small). The point particle concept reaches beyond its range of applicability, however, when it is applied to the micro- scopic domain to describe fundamental particles. It is the adherence to the particle model which has necessitated the introduction of probability into quantum mechanics. Likewise, the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, which makes sense in the wave context in terms of Fourier transforms, becomes probabilistic nonsense in the particle context. The point-particle con- cept cannot account for the existence of intrinsic properties like spin and gauge degrees of freedom, both of which require internal structure, nor can it account for the existence of particle interactions (forces)[11]. The wave nature of fundamental particles becomes apparent when interaction distances become small. Quantum theory accounts for the wave nature of fundamental particles by simply tacking it onto the particle concept, resulting in a rather schizophrenic juxtaposition known as wave/particle duality. While wave/particle duality has brought us closer to a complete understanding of fundamental particles, it has brought us only half-way. Quantum theorists, building upon the legacy of classical physics, kept the point particle concept central and attempted to graft the newly discovered wave properties of matter onto it. They were naturally led to ask the wrong question: How can a particle have wave-like properties? The answer is, of course, that it can't, so elementary particles must be strange objects, they concluded, which sometimes behave like particles and sometimes like waves. This dominance of the particle concept on our thinking has been a subtle but insurmountable barrier to the unification of theoretical physics. To get beyond barrier #1, we need to abandon the notion that the particle concept is fundamental and instead embrace the wave nature. There are strong reasons for believing that the wave properties of matter are more fundamental than the particle properties. This leads to a reversal of our logic. If we say that waves exist and that somehow (not so mysteriously) they have particle properties associated with them, the whole situation becomes much clearer. In the language of wave-particle duality we are then led to ask the right question: How can a wave have particle-like properties? This rephrasing may seem simple, but the consequences of it are profound since the question now has an answer: Waves can have particle-like properties by being localized in space. Such localized waves are commonly referred to as solitons and are familiar in a variety of contexts. This soliton model contains the key to a new approach to understanding fundamental particles and their interactions, but by itself is not the complete answer. Many questions present themselves, perhaps the most important of which is: What is the \medium" in which these localized waves propagate? I offer a surprisingly simple answer to this question in section 4, but first we must adjust our approach to gravitation theory so that it can be made compatible with the wave model of fundamental particles. 3 3 Barrier #2: the equivalence principle What's wrong with curved space? The weak equivalence principle of general relativity states that gravity can be described either by a nonzero gravitational interaction in Euclidean space or by curved (Riemannian) space with the gravitational interaction identically zero. Gen- eral relativity is based on the second formulation. The first formulation, which I will refer to as “flat gravity" is, unfortunately, a theory that does not exist. I am not referring to Newtonian gravity, which is a quasi-static theory comparable to Coulomb's law in electro- magnetic theory, but rather to a theory which includes the finite propagation velocity of the gravitational interaction, comparable to Maxwell's theory. Some work in this direction was being done around the same time that Einstein developed general relativity but was put aside with Einstein's \successful" formulation of gravity in terms of geometry.
Recommended publications
  • General Relativity and Cosmology: Unsolved Questions and Future Directions
    Article General Relativity and Cosmology: Unsolved Questions and Future Directions Ivan Debono 1,∗,† and George F. Smoot 1,2,3,† 1 Paris Centre for Cosmological Physics, APC, AstroParticule et Cosmologie, Université Paris Diderot, CNRS/IN2P3, CEA/lrfu, Observatoire de Paris, Sorbonne Paris Cité, 10, rue Alice Domon et Léonie Duquet, 75205 Paris CEDEX 13, France; [email protected] 2 Physics Department and Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory, University of California, Berkeley, 94720 CA, USA 3 Helmut and Anna Pao Sohmen Professor-at-Large, Hong Kong University of Science and Technology, Clear Water Bay, Kowloon, 999077 Hong Kong, China * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +33-1-57276991 † These authors contributed equally to this work. Academic Editors: Lorenzo Iorio and Elias C. Vagenas Received: 21 August 2016; Accepted: 14 September 2016; Published: 28 September 2016 Abstract: For the last 100 years, General Relativity (GR) has taken over the gravitational theory mantle held by Newtonian Gravity for the previous 200 years. This article reviews the status of GR in terms of its self-consistency, completeness, and the evidence provided by observations, which have allowed GR to remain the champion of gravitational theories against several other classes of competing theories. We pay particular attention to the role of GR and gravity in cosmology, one of the areas in which one gravity dominates and new phenomena and effects challenge the orthodoxy. We also review other areas where there are likely conflicts pointing to the need to replace or revise GR to represent correctly observations and consistent theoretical framework. Observations have long been key both to the theoretical liveliness and viability of GR.
    [Show full text]
  • (TEGR) As a Gauge Theory: Translation Or Cartan Connection? M Fontanini, E
    Teleparallel gravity (TEGR) as a gauge theory: Translation or Cartan connection? M Fontanini, E. Huguet, M. Le Delliou To cite this version: M Fontanini, E. Huguet, M. Le Delliou. Teleparallel gravity (TEGR) as a gauge theory: Transla- tion or Cartan connection?. Physical Review D, American Physical Society, 2019, 99, pp.064006. 10.1103/PhysRevD.99.064006. hal-01915045 HAL Id: hal-01915045 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01915045 Submitted on 7 Nov 2018 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Teleparallel gravity (TEGR) as a gauge theory: Translation or Cartan connection? M. Fontanini1, E. Huguet1, and M. Le Delliou2 1 - Universit´eParis Diderot-Paris 7, APC-Astroparticule et Cosmologie (UMR-CNRS 7164), Batiment Condorcet, 10 rue Alice Domon et L´eonieDuquet, F-75205 Paris Cedex 13, France.∗ and 2 - Institute of Theoretical Physics, Physics Department, Lanzhou University, No.222, South Tianshui Road, Lanzhou, Gansu 730000, P R China y (Dated: November 7, 2018) In this paper we question the status of TEGR, the Teleparallel Equivalent of General Relativity, as a gauge theory of translations. We observe that TEGR (in its usual translation-gauge view) does not seem to realize the generally admitted requirements for a gauge theory for some symmetry group G: namely it does not present a mathematical structure underlying the theory which relates to a principal G-bundle and the choice of a connection on it (the gauge field).
    [Show full text]
  • On the Goldstonic Gravitation Theory
    Pramina-J. Phys., Voi. 29, No. 1, July 1987, pp. 21-37. © Printed in India. On the Goldstonic gravitation theory D IVANENKO and G SARDANASHVILY Physics Faculty, Moscow University, 117234, Moscow, USSR Abstract. The physical specificity of gravity as a Goldstone-typ¢ field responsible for spontaneous breaking of space-time symmetries is investigated and extended up to supcrgrav- ity. Problems of the Higgs gravitation vacuum and its matter sources are discussed. A particular"dislocation" structure of a space-time due to Poincar6 translation gauge fields and the corresponding modification of Newton's gravitational potential are predicted. Keywords. Gauge theory; gravity; supergravity; Goldstone field. PACS Nos 04.50; 11.15 1. Introduction The geometric nature of gravity as a metric field was established by Einstein's general relativity which we take as the base of gravitation theory. The physical specificity of gravity as the Goldstone-type field is now clarified by means of gauge approach to gravitation theory (Sardanashvily 1980; Ivanenko and Sardanashvily 1983; Ivanenko et al 1985). At present, gauge theory is well known to provide the theoretical base of most part of current unification attempts in particle physics. Apparently, a necessary step for including gravity in the unified gauge picture of, fundamental interactions consists in constructing a comprehensive gauge gravitation theory itself. We share the opinion of many authors that a gauge gravitation theory must contain Einstein's general relativity as the particular case. However, the main dilemma that one faces is that Einstein's gravitational field is a metric (or tetrad) field, whereas gauge potentials are connections on fibre bundles.
    [Show full text]
  • Spacetime Geometric Structures and the Search for a Quantum Theory of Gravity
    Spacetime geometric structures and the search for a Quantum Theory of Gravity Mihaela Iftime Abstract. One of the biggest challenges to theoretical physics of our time is to ¯nd a background-independent quantum theory of gravity. Today one encounters a profusion of di®erent attempts at quantization, but no fully accepted - or acceptable, theory of quantum gravity. Any such approach requires a response to a question that lies at the heart of this problem. \How shall we resolve the tension between the background de- pendence of all hitherto-successful quantum theories, both non-relativistic quantum mechanics and special-relativistic quantum ¯eld theory, and the background independence of classical general relativity?" (see [28]) The need for a background-independent quantization procedure forms the starting point of my approach. In this paper I shall present a gauge-natural formulation of general relativity, and provide some insights into the struc- ture of the space of geometries, which plays an important role in the construction of a non-perturbative quantum gravity using a path integral approach, as well as in string theory (see e.g., [2, 18, 31]) M.S.C. 2000: 53-XX, 83-XX. Key words: Di®erential geometry, Relativity and gravitational theory. 1 Historical-Physical Motivation The most succesful among all gravitational theories is Einstein's theory of general relativity. In general relativity the ¯eld equations 1 are described in purely geometric terms: the space-time is a fairly smooth manifold M of dim n = 4 with a normal hyperbolic Riemannian structure { Lorentzian metric tensor g transforms at each point to the flat Minkowski metric ´ = diag(1; 1; 1; ¡1), and its timelike and null geodesics represent the paths of freely falling particles and light rays.
    [Show full text]
  • The Gauge Condition in Gravitation Theory with a Background Metric
    The gauge condition in gravitation theory with a background metric G. A. Sardanashvily Department of Theoretical Physics, Moscow State University, 117234 Moscow, Russia E-mail: [email protected] URL: http://webcenter.ru/∼sardan/ Abstract. In gravitation theory with a background metric, a gravitational field is described by a two-tensor field. The energy-momentum conservation law imposes a gauge condition on this field. Gravitation theory in the presence of a background metric remains under considera- tion. In particular, there are two variants of gauge gravitation theory [9, 10, 12]. The first of them leads to the metric-affine gravitation theory, while the second one (hence- forth BMT) deals with a background pseudo-Riemannian metric gµν and a non-degenerate µ (1,1)-tensor field q ν, regarded as a gravitational field. A Lagrangian of BMT is of the form LBMT = ǫLq + LAM + Lm, (1) µ where Lq is a Lagrangian of a tensor gravitational field q ν in the presence of a background µν µν metric g , LAM is a Lagrangian of the metric-affine theory where a metric g is replaced with an effective metric µν µ ν αβ g = q αq βg , (2) e and Lm is a matter field Lagrangian depending on an effective metric g and a general linear connection K (see, e.g., [5]). Note that, strictly speaking, g (2)e is not a metric, but there exists a metric whose coefficients equal gµν (2). Therefore,e one usually assumes that Lq depends on q only via an effective metriceg. arXiv:gr-qc/0301066v1 19 Jan 2003 A glance at the expression (1) shows that thee matter field equation in BMT is that of affine-metric theory where a metric g is replaced with an effective metric g.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Physics of Elementary Particles
    INTRODUCTION TO PHYSICS OF ELEMENTARY PARTICLES INTRODUCTION TO PHYSICS OF ELEMENTARY PARTICLES O.M. BOYARKIN Nova Science Publishers, Inc. New York c 2007 by Nova Science Publishers, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means: electronic, electrostatic, magnetic, tape, mechanical photocopying, recording or otherwise without the written permission of the Publisher. For permission to use material from this book please contact us: Telephone 631-231-7269; Fax 631-231-8175 Web Site: http://www.novapublishers.com NOTICE TO THE READER The Publisher has taken reasonable care in the preparation of this book, but makes no expressed or implied warranty of any kind and assumes no responsibility for any errors or omissions. No liability is assumed for incidental or consequential damages in connection with or arising out of information contained in this book. The Publisher shall not be liable for any special, consequential, or exemplary damages resulting, in whole or in part, from the readers’ use of, or reliance upon, this material. Independent verification should be sought for any data, advice or recommendations contained in this book. In addition, no responsibility is assumed by the publisher for any injury and/or damage to persons or property arising from any methods, products, instructions, ideas or otherwise contained in this publication. This publication is designed to provide accurate and authoritative information with regard to the subject matter cover herein. It is sold with the clear understanding that the Publisher is not engaged in rendering legal or any other professional services.
    [Show full text]
  • Scalar Fields in Particle Physics
    UNIVERSIDADE DE LISBOA INSTITUTO SUPERIOR TÉCNICO Scalar Fields in Particle Physics Leonardo Antunes Pedro Supervisor: Doctor Gustavo da Fonseca Castelo Branco Thesis approved in public session to obtain the PhD Degree in Physics Jury final classification: Pass With Merit Jury Chairperson: Chairman of the IST Scientific Board Members of the Committee: arXiv:1608.01928v1 [hep-ph] 5 Aug 2016 Doctor Francisco José Botella Olcina Doctor Gustavo da Fonseca Castelo Branco Doctor Jorge Manuel Rodrigues Crispim Romão Doctor Maria Margarida Nesbitt Rebelo da Silva Doctor Paulo André de Paiva Parada Doctor David Emanuel da Costa 2015 UNIVERSIDADE DE LISBOA INSTITUTO SUPERIOR TÉCNICO Scalar Fields in Particle Physics Leonardo Antunes Pedro Supervisor: Doctor Gustavo da Fonseca Castelo Branco Thesis approved in public session to obtain the PhD Degree in Physics Jury final classification: Pass With Merit Jury Chairperson: Chairman of the IST Scientific Board Members of the Committee: Doctor Francisco José Botella Olcina, Full Professor, Instituto de Física Corpuscular, Universitat de València, Spain Doctor Gustavo da Fonseca Castelo Branco, Full Professor, Instituto Superior Técnico, Universidade de Lisboa Doctor Jorge Manuel Rodrigues Crispim Romão, Full Professor, Instituto Superior Técnico, Universidade de Lisboa Doctor Maria Margarida Nesbitt Rebelo da Silva, Principal Researcher, Instituto Superior Técnico, Universidade de Lisboa Doctor Paulo André de Paiva Parada, Assistant Professor, Faculdade de Ciências, Universidade da Beira Interior Doctor David Emanuel da Costa, Assistant Researcher, Instituto Superior Técnico, Universidade de Lisboa Funding Institutions Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia 2015 | Campos escalares em Física de Partículas Leonardo Antunes Pedro Doutoramento em Física Orientador Doutor Gustavo da Fonseca Castelo Branco Resumo Alargar o sector escalar ajuda a estudar o mecanismo de Higgs e alguns problemas do Modelo Padrão.
    [Show full text]
  • General Relativity and Cosmology: Unsolved Questions and Future Directions
    Article General Relativity and Cosmology: Unsolved Questions and Future Directions Ivan Debono 1,∗,† and George F. Smoot 1,2,3,† 1 Paris Centre for Cosmological Physics, APC, AstroParticule et Cosmologie, Université Paris Diderot, CNRS/IN2P3, CEA/lrfu, Observatoire de Paris, Sorbonne Paris Cité, 10, rue Alice Domon et Léonie Duquet, 75205 Paris CEDEX 13, France 2 Physics Department and Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory, University of California, Berkeley, 94720 CA, USA; [email protected] 3 Helmut and Anna Pao Sohmen Professor-at-Large, Hong Kong University of Science and Technology, Clear Water Bay, Kowloon, 999077 Hong Kong, China * Correspondence: [email protected]; Tel.: +33-1-57276991 † These authors contributed equally to this work. Academic Editors: Lorenzo Iorio and Elias C. Vagenas Received: 21 August 2016; Accepted: 14 September 2016; Published: 28 September 2016 Abstract: For the last 100 years, General Relativity (GR) has taken over the gravitational theory mantle held by Newtonian Gravity for the previous 200 years. This article reviews the status of GR in terms of its self-consistency, completeness, and the evidence provided by observations, which have allowed GR to remain the champion of gravitational theories against several other classes of competing theories. We pay particular attention to the role of GR and gravity in cosmology, one of the areas in which one gravity dominates and new phenomena and effects challenge the orthodoxy. We also review other areas where there are likely conflicts pointing to the need to replace or revise GR to represent correctly observations and consistent theoretical framework. Observations have long been key both to the theoretical liveliness and viability of GR.
    [Show full text]
  • Weak Space-Time Curvature Effects for Lepton Electric Charge Swap at High Energy Scale Elias Koorambas
    Weak Space-Time Curvature Effects for Lepton Electric Charge Swap at High Energy Scale Elias Koorambas To cite this version: Elias Koorambas. Weak Space-Time Curvature Effects for Lepton Electric Charge Swap atHigh Energy Scale. Journal of Magnetohydrodynamics, Plasma, and Space Research , NOVA SCIENCE PUBLISHERS, INC., 2015, 20 (3), pp.333-354. hal-01205635 HAL Id: hal-01205635 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01205635 Submitted on 25 Sep 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution - NonCommercial| 4.0 International License Chapter WEAK SPACE-TIME CURVATURE EFFECTS FOR LEPTON ELECTRIC CHARGE SWAP AT HIGH ENERGY SCALE E. Koorambas Ampelokipi, Athens, Greece ABSTRACT We investigate the nature of a new kind of space-time curvature effects, produced by electric charge swap (ECS) transformations between families of leptons in the six- dimensional space time, We find that lepton ECS-transformations form the proper + Lorentz group SO (1,3)(ECS). We show that Einstein-type theory of weak space-time ECS- curvature effects can be formulated from the SL(2,C)(ECS) gauge group by using ECS- tetrad formalism. The latter yields to massless electrically charged spin-2 (ECS-graviton), which mediates the ECS exchange interaction between families of leptons.
    [Show full text]
  • A Black Hole Solution of Higher-Dimensional Weyl-Yang
    A BLACK HOLE SOLUTION OF HIGHER-DIMENSIONAL WEYL YANG KALUZA KLEIN THEORY − − − Halil Kuyrukcu Physics Department, Zonguldak B¨ulent Ecevit University, Zonguldak, 67100, Turkey E-mail: [email protected] Abstract. We consider the Weyl Yang gauge theory of gravitation in a (4 + 3)- − dimensional curved space-time within the scenario of the non-Abelian Kaluza Klein − theory for the source and torsion-free limits. The explicit forms of the field equations containing a new spin current term and the energy-momentum tensors in the usual four dimensions are obtained through the well-known dimensional reduction procedure. In this limit, these field equations admit (anti-)dyon and magnetic (anti-)monopole solutions as well as non-Einsteinian solutions in the presence of a generalized Wu Yang − ansatz and some specific warping functions when the extra dimensions associated with the round and squashed three-sphere S3 are, respectively, included. The (anti- )dyonic solution has similar properties to those of the Reissner Nordstr¨om de Sitter − − black holes of the Einstein Yang Mills system. However, the cosmological constant − − naturally appears in this approach, and it associates with the constant warping function as well as the three-sphere radius. It is demonstrated that not only the squashing parameter ℓ behaves as the constant charge but also its sign can determine whether the solution is a dyon/monopole or an antidyon/antimonopole. It is also shown by using the power series method that the existence of nonconstant warping function is essential for finding new exact Schwarzschild-like solutions in the considered model. arXiv:1602.02418v2 [gr-qc] 23 Sep 2021 PACS numbers: 04.50.Cd, 04.50.Kd, 04.20.Jb, 04.70.Bw Keywords: Modified theories of gravity, kaluza-klein theories, exact solutions, classical black holes 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Gauge Gravitation Theory from the Geometric Viewpoint
    GAUGE GRAVITATION THEORY FROM THE GEOMETRIC VIEWPOINT G.SARDANASHVILY Department of Theoretical Physics, Moscow State University This is the Preface to the special issue of International Journal of Geometric Methods in Modern Physics 3, N.1 (2006) dedicated to the 50th anniversary of gauge gravitation theory. It addresses the geometry underlying gauge gravitation theories, their higher-dimensional, super- gauge, and non-commutative extensions. At present, Yang–Mills gauge theory provides a universal description of the fundamental electroweak and strong interactions. Gauge gravitation theory from the very beginning [1] aims to extend this description to gravity. It started with gauge models of the Lorentz, Poincar´egroups and general covariant transformations [2–4]. At present, gauge gravity is mainly supergravity, higher-dimensional, non-commutative and quantum gravity [5–8]. This Preface can not pretend for any comprehensive analysis of gauge gravitation theories, but addresses only the geometry underlying them. We apologize in advance for that the list of references is far from to be complete. The first gauge model of gravity was suggested by Utiyama [1] in 1956 just two years after birth of the gauge theory itself. Utiyama was first who generalized the original gauge model of Yang and Mills for SU(2) to an arbitrary symmetry Lie group and, in particular, to the Lorentz group in order to describe gravity. However, he met the problem of treating arXiv:gr-qc/0512115v2 9 Feb 2006 general covariant transformations and a pseudo-Riemannian metric (a tetrad field) which had no partner in Yang–Mills gauge theory. In a general setting, fiber bundles provide the adequate geometric formulation of classical field theory where classical fields on a smooth manifold X are represented by sections of fiber bundles over X.
    [Show full text]
  • Gauge Gravitation Theory. What Is the Geometry of the World?
    GAUGE GRAVITATION THEORY. WHAT IS GEOMETRY OF THE WORLD? Gennadi A Sardanashvily Department of Theoretical Physics, Physics Faculty, Moscow State University, 117234 Moscow, Russia E-mail: [email protected] When joined the unified gauge picture of fundamental interactions, the gravitation theory leads to geometry of a space-time which is far from simplicity of pseudo-Riemannian geometry of Einstein’s General Relativity. This is geometry of the affine-metric composite dislocated manifolds. The goal is modification of the familiar equations of a gravitational field and entirely the new equations of its deviations. In the present brief, we do not detail the mathematics, but discuss the reasons why it is just this geometry. The major physical underlying reason lies in spontaneous symmetry breaking when the fermion matter admits only the Lorentz subgroup of world symmetries of the geometric arena. I. Gauge theory is well-known to call into play the differential geometric methods in order to describe interaction of fields possessing a certain symmetry group. Moreover, it is this geometric approach phrased in terms of fibred manifolds which provides the adequate mathematical formulation of classical field theory. Note that the conventional gauge principle of gauge invariance of Lagrangian densities losts its validity since symmetries of realistic field models are almost always broken. We follow the geometric modification of the gauge principle which is formulated as follows. Classical fields can be identified with sections of fibred manifolds arXiv:gr-qc/9410045v1 30 Oct 1994 π : Y X (1) → whose n-dimensional base X is treated a parameter space, in particular, a world manifold.
    [Show full text]