The Importance of Aristotle to Design Thinking James Wang

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Importance of Aristotle to Design Thinking James Wang The Importance of Aristotle to Design Thinking James Wang Introduction The importance of Aristotle to the teaching and practice of design is that recourse to his theories of reason, imagination, and practical intellect allow us to justify design activity in two fundamental ways. First, according to Aristotle’s concept of technē as knowing by making, design should be regarded as a rational activity in and of itself. Although design is intricately linked to technology, and technology is, by definition, utilitarian, design is still first and foremost a matter of working with formal causes to transform them into final causes. In this respect, designers need not allow their activity to be appropriated by social activists, or even worse, by consumers. Moreover, Aristotle offers a cogent account of the way that imagination supports, assists, and even enables reason in the working of both the theoretical intellect and the practical intellect. This realization does much to validate imagination as a concept worthy of attention in academic research and discourse. The second way that Aristotle’s theories justify design activity is by defending the puzzling reluctance of many designers to commit themselves fully to the service of communitarian ethics in regard to social justice and environmental sustainability. According to Aristotle’s theory of the practical intellect, makers—those who work with technē—are concerned only with the excellence of mak- ing, in contrast with doers—those who work prudentially to estab- lish justice and who are very concerned about public values and social effects. The critics of design want designers to be doers, too; but because designers are essentially makers, transforming them- selves into public servants is often difficult, if not impossible. Two Problems A recurring issue of design theory, in regard to both pedagogy and practice, is the problem of understanding the epistemology of design. Design is generally believed to be an activity that involves creativity. Further, creativity is believed to operate through imagi- nation. The trouble is that scholars have never been totally con- vincing in their attempts to account for either imagination in particular or creativity in general. In this regard, design theory © 2013 Massachusetts Institute of Technology 4 DesignIssues: Volume 29, Number 2 Spring 2013 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DESI_a_00206 by guest on 01 October 2021 parallels art theory, or aesthetics—a branch of philosophy that is notoriously contentious. Architects, for example, have long regarded their work as a form of art, while design engineers tend to disparage such a claim and insist that design is a rational activity more than it is an imaginative activity. Nonetheless, at a crucial point in the design process, whether a building or an industrial product is being developed, creativity happens, and the project moves on to completion (or it does not happen, and the project is eventually scrapped). A theoretical understanding of design as an intellectual activity, therefore, would seem to be most welcome and useful. A second problem currently troublesome in the discipline of design is its response to the arguments of various proponents of communitarian ethics; Linda Groat, for example, argues that designers should operate with much a greater cultural sensitivity and a firmer commitment to ecological sustainability.1 The fact is that, although design faculties and student bodies have been agreeable in principle to operating with such progressive social values and goals in mind, in actual practice they have not always been as forthcoming as the activists for social justice would like.2 Why? The answer clearly is not as simple as suggesting that architects and design engineers lack a proper social conscience. The reason that designers sometimes seem to be lukewarm about the social impact of their work resides more in the intellectual realm than in the moral one. Something in creativity itself appears to be intrinsically resistant to thinking in terms of social effects. If this source of resistance could be identified, design teachers and practitioners would, again, very likely welcome and use this information. One Solution A better understanding of both these conundrums may be located in the writings of the earliest philosophers in ancient Greece— particularly in the teachings of Aristotle. This connection should not be as surprising as it first may sound. Alfred North White- head’s famous dictum that all Western civilization is a series of footnotes to Plato and Aristotle remains true, even in the Digital Age. Of primary interest to design theory and pedagogy is Aristo- tle’s definition of design implicit in his concept of technē. This term 1 Linda Groat, “The Architect as Artist or is also the source of our word “technology,” which is significant Scientist? A Modest Proposal for the Architect-as-Cultivator,” in Culture – because design is usually understood as the essence of technologi- Meaning – Architecture, ed. K. D. Moore cal invention. Moreover, Aristotle’s concept of technē is the source (Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, of what we call “art, after ars” which is Medieval Latin’s translation 2000), 129. of Aristotle’s term. At its core, technē means “making,” but it also 2 For example, J. Kabo and C. Baillie, means “knowing,” thus relating the term to the Latin term scientia “Seeing Through the Lens of Social or “science.” Ultimately, technē means “knowing by making,” and Justice: A Threshold for Engineering,” European Journal of Engineering Aristotle contrasts technē with epistēmē or “knowing by thinking” Education 34, no. 4 (2009): 317. DesignIssues: Volume 29, Number 2 Spring 2013 5 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DESI_a_00206 by guest on 01 October 2021 (i.e., thinking rationally). The difference is that technē can know only contingent reality because it is limited to sensation, memory, and imagination; whereas, epistēmē can know necessary reality, because it is only limited by the universal and eternal rules of logic.3 For Aristotle, making is less important than theorizing. This belief would eventually be overturned in the modern world, explicitly by elevating imagination to an eminence superior to rea- son. The modern revolution in the conception of imagination is based on the argument of the great poets of the Romantic Age, along with the philosophers Kant and Nietzsche, that imagination is a mental power that allows humans to apprehend reality directly, without the aid of reason. Nevertheless, Aristotle also has a lot to say about imagination, or what he calls fantasia, and it is the contention of this paper that Aristotle’s commentary on imagina- tion goes a long way toward accounting for design creativity. The problem of explaining the epistemology of design in such a way as to at least partially de-mystify it, and thereby make it more acceptable to the rationalist pedagogical paradigm of the university, presents a difficult task to anyone who believes in the importance of knowing by making—whether one is concerned with art or with technology. A few years ago, Donald Schön, stand- ing on the shoulders of John Dewey, did much to validate creativ- ity as a legitimate academic enterprise with his advancement of the concept of “reflection-in-action,” based on a confidence in the tacit knowledge of knowing by doing.4 But Schön did not investigate the nature of imagination as the core activity of creativity, thus leaving “designerly thinking,” as Nigel Cross calls it, still in the dark.5 This 3 Aristotle, Metaphysics, 981a24–981b9. same darkness is where Stefani Ledewitz says that designers must 4 Donald Schön, The Reflective Practi- “leap” to be creative.6 Nonetheless, remembering Aristotle’s teach- tioner: How Professionals Think in Action ing does shine some light on the way that imagination works with (New York: Basic Books, 1983); “The Architectural Studio as an Exemplar of reason in the design process, making creativity more accessible to Education for Reflection-in-Action,” rational investigation and therefore more respectable academically. Journal of Architectural Education 38, The problem of persuading design teachers, students, and no. 1 (1984): 2-9; Educating the Reflective practitioners to include cultural sensitivity and environmental Practitioner (New York: Basic Books, concern—in fact, to be good communitarian ethicists—as part of 1987); and “Designing: Rules, Types and Words,” Design Studies 9, no. 3 (1988): their thinking in the design process would appear to be an entirely 181-90. John Dewey’s works include practical matter. In a sense, we might say that designers simply Experience and Nature (New York: need to be re-educated, so that architects will not be so dreamy Dover, 1929); Art as Experience (New and engineers will not be so focused on solving problems, and York: Perigree, 1934); and Experience and both will learn to be more socially conscious. And yet attempts Education (New York: Collier/McMillan, to achieve such changes have often failed. Part of the problem in 1938). 5 Nigel Cross, “Designerly Ways of the university is the difficulty of introducing more humanities Knowing: Design Discipline Versus courses into an already packed curriculum. The better strategy Design Science,” Design Issues 17, might be to try to understand why designers are the way they are no. 3 (2001): 50. and why they act the way they act. In other words, rather than first 6 Stephani Ledewitz, “Models of Design trying to convince designers to work with an awareness of com- in Studio Teaching,” Journal of Architectural Education 38, no. 2 munitarian ethics, we might start by trying to understand their (1985): 5. apparent reluctance to do so, and even their intransigence, despite 6 DesignIssues: Volume 29, Number 2 Spring 2013 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/DESI_a_00206 by guest on 01 October 2021 their agreement with the call for change.
Recommended publications
  • 2. Aristotle's Concept of the State
    Page No.13 2. Aristotle's concept of the state Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Full Member International Association of Greek Philosophy University of Athens, Greece ORCID iD: http://orcid.org/0000-0001-5950-7146 URL: http://worldphilosophynetwork.weebly.com E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract: In contrast to a little bit utopian standpoint offered by Plato in his teachings about the state or politeia where rulers aren`t “in love with power but in virtue”, Aristotle's teaching on the same subject seems very realistic and pragmatic. In his most important writing in this field called "Politics", Aristotle classified authority in the form of two main parts: the correct authority and moose authority. In this sense, correct forms of government are 1.basileus, 2.aristocracy and 3.politeia. These forms of government are based on the common good. Bad or moose forms of government are those that are based on the property of an individual or small governmental structures and they are: 1.tiranny, 2.oligarchy and 3.democracy. Also, Aristotle's political thinking is not separate from the ethical principles so he states that the government should be reflected in the true virtue that is "law" or the "golden mean". Keywords: Government; stat; , virtue; democracy; authority; politeia; golden mean. Vol. 4 No. 4 (2016) Issue- December ISSN 2347-6869 (E) & ISSN 2347-2146 (P) Aristotle's concept of the state by Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Page no. 13-20 Page No.14 Aristotle's concept of the state 1.1. Aristotle`s “Politics” Politics in its defined form becomes affirmed by the ancient Greek world.
    [Show full text]
  • Radin Centre for the Study of Religion University of Toronto [email protected]
    Long Commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle. Written by Averroes (Ibn Rushd) of Cordoba. Translated and with introduction and notes by Richard C. Taylor, with Therese-Anne Druart, subeditor. New Haven CT: Yale University Press, 2009. 498 pages. ISBN: 978-0-0300-11668-7. $85.00 US, $97.95 CDN. Born in Andalusia in 1126, Averroes (or Ibn Rushd) is generally considered one of the most influential Arabic classical philosophers, and his impact on Western thought, through the interpretations of Thomas Aquinas, Duns Scotus, and others, can hardly be overestimated. Although Averroes wrote extensively in the fields of religious law (Bidayat al-Mujtahid wa Nihayat al-Muqtasad), philosophy (The Incoherence of the Incoherence) and their relationship (Decisive Treatise), his nickname, the Great Commentator, is a result of Averroes’ prolific commentaries on Greek philosophy, and particularly the works of Aristotle. The date of completion of Averroes’ Long Commentary is, although debatable, usually given at around 1186 C.E., and while its chronological relationship to the Short and Middle Commentaries (and therefore status as Averroes’ ‘final opinion’ on the De Anima) is debatable, the Long Commentary certainly presents Averroes’ most detailed examination of the De Anima. In form, it is basically a line-by-line exegesis, with Averroes reproducing Aristotle’s work and then proceeding to provide explanation, extension, and interpretation. Averroes’ Long Commentary is key to tracing how Averroes interpreted Aristotle’s work on the soul and how his own concept of the soul developed from his reading of Aristotle. The current translation of Averroes’ Long Commentary on the De Anima of Aristotle by Richard C.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death
    The University of Akron IdeaExchange@UAkron Williams Honors College, Honors Research The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors Projects College Spring 2020 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death Christopher Choma [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects Part of the Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, European History Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Please take a moment to share how this work helps you through this survey. Your feedback will be important as we plan further development of our repository. Recommended Citation Choma, Christopher, "St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death" (2020). Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects. 1048. https://ideaexchange.uakron.edu/honors_research_projects/1048 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by The Dr. Gary B. and Pamela S. Williams Honors College at IdeaExchange@UAkron, the institutional repository of The University of Akron in Akron, Ohio, USA. It has been accepted for inclusion in Williams Honors College, Honors Research Projects by an authorized administrator of IdeaExchange@UAkron. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. 1 St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas on the Mind, Body, and Life After Death By: Christopher Choma Sponsored by: Dr. Joseph Li Vecchi Readers: Dr. Howard Ducharme Dr. Nathan Blackerby 2 Table of Contents Introduction p. 4 Section One: Three General Views of Human Nature p.
    [Show full text]
  • BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS I
    i / REF1,l!;CTit.>NS ON ECONOMIC PROBLEMS / BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS ii ~FLECTIONS ON ECONO:MIC PROBLEMS 1 BY PLA'I'O, ARISTOTLE, JJJD AQUINAS, By EUGENE LAIDIBEL ,,SWEARINGEN Bachelor of Science Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical Collage Stillwater, Oklahoma 1941 Submitted to the Depertmeut of Economics Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical College In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF SCIENCE 1948 iii f.. 'I. I ···· i·: ,\ H.: :. :· ··: ! • • ~ ' , ~ • • !·:.· : i_ ·, 1r 1i1. cr~~rJ3t L l: i{ ,\ I~ Y , '•T •)() 1 0 ,1 8 API-'HOV~D BY: .J ,.· 1.., J l.;"t .. ---- -··- - ·- ______.,.. I 7 -.. JI J ~ L / \ l v·~~ u ' ~) (;_,LA { 7 {- ' r ~ (\.7 __\ _. ...A'_ ..;f_ ../-_" ...._!)_.... ..." ___ ......._ ·;...;;; ··-----/ 1--.,i-----' ~-.._.._ :_..(__,,---- ....... Member of the Report Committee 1..j lj:,;7 (\ - . "'·- -· _ .,. ·--'--C. r, .~-}, .~- Q_ · -~ Q.- 1Head of the Department . · ~ Dean of the Graduate School 502 04 0 .~ -,. iv . r l Preface The purpose and plan of this report are set out in the Introduction. Here, I only wish to express my gratitude to Professor Russell H. Baugh who has helped me greatly in the preparation of this report by discussing the various subjects as they were in the process of being prepared. I am very much indebted to Dr. Harold D. Hantz for his commentaries on the report and for the inspiration which his classes in Philosophy have furnished me as I attempted to correlate some of the material found in these two fields, Ecor!.Omics and Philosophy. I should like also to acknowledge that I owe my first introduction into the relationships of Economics and Philosophy to Dean Raymond Thomas, and his com~ents on this report have been of great value.
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 4-12-2006 Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Neste, Berit Van, "Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea" (2006). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3782 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea by Berit Van Neste A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Religious Studies College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: James F. Strange, Ph.D. Paul G. Schneider, Ph.D. Michael J. Decker, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 12, 2006 Keywords: theology, philosophy, politics, patristic, medieval © Copyright 2006 , Berit Van Neste For Elizabeth and Calista Table of Contents Abstract ii Chapter 1 1 Introduction 1 Cicero’s Influence on Augustine 7 Chapter 2 13 Justice 13 Natural and Temporal Law 19 Commonwealth 34 Chapter 3 49 Just War 49 Chapter 4 60 Conclusion 60 References 64 i Cicero and St.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value
    Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Korsgaard, Christine. 1986. Aristotle and Kant on the source of value. Ethics 96(3): 486-505. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/292771 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3164347 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value* ChristineM. Korsgaard THREE KINDS OF VALUE THEORY In this paper I discuss what I will call a "rationalist" account of the goodness of ends. I begin by contrasting the rationalist account to two others, "subjectivism' and "objectivism.' Subjectivism identifies good ends with or by reference to some psychological state. It includes the various forms of hedonism as well as theories according to which what is good is any object of interest or desire. Objectivism may be represented by the theory of G. E. Moore. According to Moore, to say that something is good as an end is to attribute a property, intrinsic goodness, to it. Intrinsic goodness is an objective, nonrelational property of the object, a value a thing has independently of anyone's desires, interests, or pleasures. The attraction of subjectivist views is that they acknowledge the connection of the good to human interests and desires.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates, Plato and Aristotle 2 Greek Philosophers Developed Ideas That Are Still Used Today
    Name Period Date Socrates, Plato and Aristotle 2 Greek Philosophers Developed Ideas that Are Still Used Today Directions : • Scan the article by reading the bold headings, looking at the images and reading the captions. • Then turn the bold headings for each section into questions (see the example on the first section). • Then, read the article, circling words you don’t know and defining them in terms you understand… in the margin. • After that, reread the article and highlight the sentence in each section that answers the questions you created. • On a separate sheet of paper, answer the questions at the end of the article in complete sentences (embed the question). Highlight (in a second color) where you found answers to item #s 1 and 2. The Origins of Western Thought What were the origins of Western thought? People who live in Europe and the Americas owe a great deal to the ancient Greeks…even the way they think about the world was shaped by these ancient people. Greek thinkers of that time believed the human mind could understand everything. Such people were and are called philosophers. The word philosophy comes from the Greek word for “love of wisdom.” The work of these early thinkers laid the foundations for such areas of study as mathematics, science, history, and political science. Many of these philosophers were also teachers. One of the earliest and greatest of the teacher-philosophers was Socrates. The Ideas of Socrates Socrates was a sculptor who lived in Athens. His true love was not carving stone but instead shaping minds.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Curriculum in Arabic and Hebrew
    1 The Aristotelian Curriculum (Excluding Mathematics) In Arabic and Hebrew (occasionally also Greek, Syriac, Persian, Latin) Handout for “Aristotle in the Middle Ages,” James Robinson, U. Chicago, Winter 2013 General background: Christina d’Ascona, “Greek Sources in Arabic and Islamic Philosophy,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy Online: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-greek/ M. Zonta, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on Judaic Thought,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-judaic/ Dag Hasse, “The Influence of Arabic and Islamic Philosophy on the Latin West,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-influence/ Tony Street, “Arabic and Islamic Philosophy of Language and Logic,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-language/ J. McGinnis, “Arabic and Islamic Natural Philosophy and Natural Science,” Stanford Encyc. of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-natural/ Alfred Ivry, “Arabic and Islamic Psychology and Philosophy of Mind,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-mind/ Amos Bertolacci, “Arabic and Islamic Metaphysics,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/arabic-islamic-metaphysics/ Useful Resources: Arist. semitico-latinus: http://www.brill.com/publications/aristoteles-semitico-latinus Online dictionary of Arabic philosophical terms: http://www.arabic-philosophy.com/dict Hans Daiber
    [Show full text]
  • AVERROES on CHANCE Introduction After Discussing
    CHAPTER FOUR AVERROES ON CHANCE Introduction After discussing chance and determinism in Avicenna, we now turn to Averroes’ views. His theory of chance, like that of Avicenna, is based on Aristotle’s discussion in Physics II (195b31–200b8) and is expounded in his commentaries. Averroes thus explains chance in his three commentaries on the Physics, short, middle and long, but obviously his most detailed discussion is to be found in his Long Commentary on the Physics, since his long commentaries contain point for point analyses of Aristotle’s text. This commentary shall consti- tute the starting point for my study of Averroes’ views on chance. Passages from other works by the Commentator (as Averroes was known in medieval Latin philosophical circles) both commentaries and his original works, will complement this study. Following the order of Aristotle’s text, the Andalusian philosopher first considers and refutes his predecessors’ positions and then pre- sents his own solution. In discussing the meaning of chance for Aristotle, Averroes, as is his wont, discusses the views not only of Aristotle’s predecessors such as the Presocratics but also those of late Aristotelians and of Avicenna. Reversing the order of his argument, I shall start with his own position before presenting his criticism of his predecessors and drawing a comparison between his and Avicenna’s position. In view of the fact that Averroes’ commentaries were meant to expound and elucidate Aristotle’s philosophy, question arises whether his exposition reflects the true meaning of his text. However in gen- eral the issue of Aristotle’s own views and whether Averroes expo- sitions truly reflect those of Aristotle cannot be here discussed at length, because what Aristotle exactly meant has itself been the object of controversy and has engaged the interpretive efforts of commen- tators and scholars for centuries if not millennia.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroës:Middle Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima. a Critical
    Averroës: Middle Commentary on Aristotle’s De anima. A Critical Edition of the Arabic Text with English Translation, Notes, and Introduction by Alfred L. Ivry Greco-Arabic Sciences and Philosophy. Provo, UT: Brigham Young University Press, 2002. Pp. xxxi + 285. ISBN 0–8425–2473–8. Cloth $34.95 Reviewed by Ruth Glasner Hebrew University, Mount Scopus [email protected] Averroes (Ibn Rushd), ‘the commentator’, wrote short, middle, and long commentaries on Aristotle’s texts—short and middle on almost all the treatises and long on five (viz Posterior Analytics, Physics, De caelo, De anima, and Metaphysics). The De anima was undoubtedly one of the most influential texts in the Middle Ages. Of Averroes’ three commentaries on this text, we have a relatively new edition of the short commentary by Salvador Gomez Nogales from 1985, a critical edition of the Latin translation of the long commentary by F. Stuart Crawford from 1953 (the Arabic is no longer extant), and now the long-awaited, annotated, critical edition with an English translation of the middle commentary by Alfred L. Ivry. Professor Ivry is certainly the best qualified scholar to undertake this task and the result, as far as I can judge, leaves nothing to be desired. His edition and translation set the highest standard and can serve as a model for anyone who works on a medieval text. The notes reflect Ivry’s wide and deep erudition in Greek, Arabic, and Hebrew philosophy; and they provide everything that the reader expects to find in notes and much more. The book includes an Arabic-Hebrew- Greek-Latin glossary, a very rich bibliography, and good indices.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Augustine on Time
    International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Vol. 6, No. 6; June 2016 St. Augustine on Time William Alexander Hernandez University of Houston 4800 Calhoun Rd. Houston, TX 77004 United States Abstract In Book XI of the Confessions (397), St. Augustine explores the nature of time. John L. Morrison argues that in Book XI of the Confessions, St. Augustine puts forth a subjective account of time. On this view, time exists within the human mind. I am in considerable agreement with Morrison’s interpretation of the Confession XI. However, I will argue that in On Genesis (388-389), Augustine develops an objective account of time. This means that time is a creature of God and so exists before human consciousness. It seems that Augustine has two accounts of time, one objective and the other subjective. Key Words: Time, God, Augustine, Creation, Phenomenon of Human Consciousness. Introduction In On Genesis (389) and in Book XI of The Confessions (397), St. Augustine explores the nature of time. Augustine writes, “What then is time? If no one asks me, I know; if I want to explain it to a questioner, I do not know” (Augustine 2006, p. 242). Time is a concept that we appear to understand, but once we endeavor to explain time itself, it gives rise to paradoxes. Augustine’s exploration of time is part of his larger reflections on God’s creation of the universe1. Augustine examines time in the context of scriptural interpretation of Genesis and other books of the Old Testament. Consequently, Augustine’s account of time is influenced by the Bible.
    [Show full text]
  • (1) Kant and Aristotle: Actions Versus Character
    24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy Prof. Rae Langton V. Kant Lecture 20. Comparing Kant and Aristotle (1) Kant and Aristotle: actions versus character The Categorical Imperative (cast in the Formula of Universal Law) appears to be a test for the moral rightness of actions, which seems to indicate that actions are centre stage, for Kant, and that their rightness can be discovered by application of a principle. Aristotle offers no such test, and his interest is in character, including the virtues of good companionship, and aesthetic appreciation, as much as those of honesty and the rest. In so far as there is a any test for whether an action is right, it is given by asking whether a virtuous person would do it. (2) Kant and Aristotle: actions vs. emotions [Virtue] is concerned with feelings and actions, and these admit of excess, deficiency and an intermediate condition. We can be afraid, e.g., or be confident, or have appetites, or get angry, or feel pity....but [having these feelings] at the right times, about the right things, towards the right people, for the right end, and in the right way, is the intermediate and best condition, and this is proper to virtue. Similarly, actions also admit of excess, deficiency and the intermediate condition. (Nichomachean Ethics 1106b) The virtuous agent’s emotions need to be appropriate, and need to be in harmony with their actions. For Kant, it is no part of virtue, or right action, that you have certain emotions or feelings: his main interest in emotions is in their capacity to get in the way of right action, and he tends to assume that emotions will tend to conflict with duty.
    [Show full text]