The System Afthe Sceptical Modes in Sextus Empiricus

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The System Afthe Sceptical Modes in Sextus Empiricus The System afthe Sceptical Modes in Sextus Empiricus Nathan Powers The Pyrrhonian sceptic-ill-training learned the so-called 'modes', sche­ matized argument patterns on which sceptics relied in their suspen­ sions of judgment. Our richest source of information about these modes is Book One of Sextus Empiricus' Outlines of Flrvrnnnl Hupotup6seis: henceforth PH),! In recent decades, the several of mode that Sextus describes have been studied closely," There has, how­ ever, been little investigation of how Sextus himself, as a representa­ tive of the later Pyrrhonian tradition, takes the various sorts of modes he describes to be related to one another, In this paper I shall argue that, whatever the original purpose of each of mode may have been, Sextus does not simply catalogue them for posterity, he presents them as a loose system within which each sort of rnode has a specific function to fulfill in advancing the aims of scepticism. 1 Scepticism is defined at PH I 8 as 'an ability to set out oppositions among things which appear and are thought of in any way at all'; this ability 2'.1- abIes one to attain suspension of judgment, and suspension of leads to tranquility (ataraxia), The 'ability to set out oppositions' for Sextus con­ sists, at least in large part, in a command of the modes: PH I 350 All references to PH I are henceforth by section number only. I follow Mutschmarm-Mau's Teubner text (1958). Translations of Sextus are based on A'.1° nas & Barnes (2000), modified for accuracy where necessary. 2 For analysis of the ten modes of Aenesidemus, see Striker, Annas & Barnes (1985), and Hankinson Ch, 9. On the five modes of Agrippa, see Barnes (1990a) and Hankinson Ch, 10, On the eight 'refutational' modes of Aenesidemus, see Barnes (1990b) 2656-68 and Hankinson 213-17. APEIRON a journal for ancient philosophy and science 003-6390/2010/4304157-172003-6390/2010/4304 157-172 16.00 ©AGlOeJmlC© Academic Prj,cting and Publishing 158 Nathan PozversPowers I Sextus groups the sceptical modes into two categories: those 'through which suspension of judgment is brought about' (35), the presentation of which occupies the bulk of PH I (36-179); and those which 'refute and assert to be unsound every causal explanation' advanced by dog­ matists (180), a brief presentation of which immediately follows the others (180-6). For convenience, I'll call these two groups the sive' and the 'refutational' modes, respectively The suspensive modes themselves come in two kinds:3 the famous ten modes of Aenesidemus (36-163), and the five modes of Agrippa (164-77).4 I shall first consider how in Sextus' view the Agrippan and Aenesideman suspensive modes are related to one another, before turning to the relationship between the suspensive and refutational modes. It will be helpful to begin with a brief characterization of the modes of Agrippa. According to the first Agrippan mode Cfrom dispute [di­ aphonia],), the existence of a dispute that is undecided" warrants sus­ pension of judgment about the matter under dispute. exactly it should do so is a crux that I hope to shed some light on below.) The second Agrippan mode ('from regression') says that if some reason p is 3 This is a slight simplification of the situation as it stands in Sextus, because he offers a way of grouping the ten Aenesideman modes into three superordinate modes (38), or alternatively into just one overarching mode (39); it is clear that these alternative groupings would not significantly affect the content or function of the modes, and they may well have originated as mnemonic aids. More prob­ lematically, Sextus also presents an odd group of two modes immediately after his description of the Agrippan modes; but it seems fairly clear that these are intended as some sort of condensation of the Agrippan modes (Annas & Barnes [1985] 22, Barnes [1990a] 116-17). At any rate, the chief focus in my discussion of the suspen­ sive modes will be on the relationship between the Aenesideman and the Agrip­ pan modes. 4 Diogenes Laertius attributes the ten modes to Aenesidemus (9. 78; d. Sextus M 7. 345 and Eusebius, PE 14. 18. 11), and the five modes to the otherwise unknown 'Agrippa' (9. 88). In PH I, however, Sextus ascribes the former simply to 'the older sceptics' (36), and the latter simply to 'the more recent sceptics' (164). Our extant sources, it is worth noting, report the ten Aenesideman modes with considerable variation 1.'1 both order and content (see Annas & Barnes [1985J 29-30 for some remarks on differences in order, and their commentary passim for differences in content). This paper is focused on Pyrrhonian argumentation as Sextus presents it in PH. 5 anepikritos; the precise meaningm£:l'':\r\llr\CT of this term is considered below. The System of the Scepticallvlodes in Sextus Empiricus 159 brought forward in favor of a claim, p will fail to convince unless some other reason r is brought forward in support of it, and so on ad tum, The third mode ('from relativity') states that appearing to be the case appears so only relative to the observer and to the circum­ stances of observation, thus warranting no decisive statement about how observed objects (really) are. The fourth ('from that any reason p brought forth in favor of a claim will be if it is itself an unproved assertion, Lastly, the fifth ('from rules out considering a reason p to count in favor of a claim if p cannot convince without making appeal to the very claim which it is to support. Sextus explicitly conceives of the Agrippan modes as together with one another;6 collectively they frustrate any reasoned ap­ peal that a dogmatist might make to decide a dispute. Barnes has named this collective function of the Agrippan modes 'the net.,7 Briefly put, the Pyrrhonist keeps pushing for of ex­ planatory principles put forward by the dogmatist to settle matters of dispute. Since the sceptic won't at any point accept appeal to first primitive or self-evident) principles (fourth Agrippan mode) or allow explanantia and explananda to justify each other the dogmatist is forced into an infinite regress which is unacceptable. With no means available to settle the dispute, the dogma­ tist is forced to suspend judgment (first mode). Sextus says very little about how he takes the Agrippan modes to be related to the Aenesideman modes, His explicit comment is the following (177): 'They [the "more recent" sceptics] put five Agrip­ pan modes] forward not as rejecting the ten [Aenesideman] modes but in order to refute the rashness of the dogmatists in a more varied [or deeper?] manner (poiki16teron) and using both sets together (kai dia tauton sun ' 6 Or, to be exact, Sextus conceives of the first, second, fourth, and fifth modes as so functioning. The third mode ('from relativity') is not included in this scheme, and indeed its presence among the other Agrippan modes is somewhat anomalous (d. Barnes [1990a] 113; Hankinson 185). However, as Hankinson POh""lts out, the mode from relativity itself seems to be (at least in Sexhls' view) closely connected with the mode from dispute: if appearances were not relative to the per­ sons who have them, disputes would not arise about appearances {d. PH I 7 Sextus takes pains to elaborateela!bor'ate the sceptic's net at 170-7; see Barnes (1990a) Ch. 5. 160 Nathan Powers Considered on its own this statement can be interpreted in a weak way, as saying that the Aenesideman modes are one group of arguments that can be used to produce suspension of judgment, and the Agrippan modes are simply arguments of a different sort useful for producing the same end.8 But it can also be understood as stating a stronger connec­ tion between the two kinds of mode, namely that they work together in concert - dia tout8n sun ekeinois - to produce suspension of judgment. Turning to the Aenesideman modes, I think it can be shown that the stronger connection is indeed what Sextus has in mind. II Each of the Aenesideman modes is essentially an application of one under~g pattern of argument, which I shall call the 'Standard Argu­ ment.' We begin with a report of an appearance: (1) x appears to be F (in circumstance C1). Now, for every such report we shall be able to produce a conflicting report: (2) x appears to be G (in circumstance C2), where x, as it appears, cannot be both F and G. Broadly speaking, each of the Aenesideman modes is a resource for discovering new conflict­ ing reports. Now, (3) We cannot prefer appearances in C1 to those in C2, or vice-versa. So, (4) We cannot say whether x is (really) F or G. 8 It might be thought that poikiloteron points towards this weak interpretation, if one translates it as 'more varied'; taking it as 'more subtle' or 'deeper' implies a stron­ ger connection. Cf. Sextus PH II 21, where the context seems to require that poiki/os be translated 'deeply' or 'in detail', not 'in a varied way'. 9 I here report the consensus view: e.g., Striker; Annas & Barnes (1985) Ch. 3; Han­ kinson Ch. 9. The System of the Sceptical Modes in Sextus 161 And &is leads to our being rationally required to suspend as to the nature of x (with respect to F and G).lO The difficult step here is (3), because usually or a report of how x appears to us, and we shall always assumes) have a tendency to give special weight to reports of how things pear to ourselves.
Recommended publications
  • The Impact of Aenesidemus Upon Fichte and Schopenhauer
    Richard Fincham 97 Pli 10 (2000), 96-126. subject from both object and subject and is referred to both".4 Fichte shows that although this may suffice as the first principle of theoretical knowledge, it cannot be the first principle of all philosophy.s Therefore, for Fichte, principles of theoretical knowledge can only be satisfactorily grounded upon the self qua reflective consciousness of Kantian and Reinholdian transcendental idealism once the existence of such reflective The Impact of Aenesidemus upon Fichte and consciousness is itself grounded upon an absolute foundation. It is of Schopenhauer course in response to this perceived requirement that Fichte constructs a system of transcendental idealism which asserts that the self itself ­ conceived of as primordially an absolute self-reverting activity - should RICHARD FINCHAM be the absolute foundation of all philosophy. This article will show why it is that for Fichte, 'reflective consciousness', which for Kant was the ground of all explanation, becomes conceived of as itself requiring explanation. It will be argued Fichte's reconfiguration of Kantian transcendental idealism is motivated that this is due to an engagement with a sceptical attack upon the by an engagement with two specific 'commentaries' upon it. Firstly, transcendental idealism of Kant and Reinhold named after (and Fichte was clearly convinced by Reinhold's complaint that the Critique's supposedly expounded by) the neo-Pyrrhonean sceptic Aenesidemus, principles can only "become universally binding"l by being grounded [I which was published anonymously in 1792, but was later revealed to be upon a universally valid and indubitable "self-explanatory,,2 foundation, the work of G.
    [Show full text]
  • Kantian Psychologism
    Kantian Psychologism Kantiaans Psychologisme (met een samenvatting in het Nederlands) Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de door Peter Sperber Promotor: Prof.dr. P.G. Ziche Copromotor: Dr. D.K.W. van Miert Copyright © 2017 by Peter Sperber All rights reserved Cover art: Rabih Mroué Leap Year´s Diary, 2006-2016 Collage on paper 23 x 16,5 cm, framed Courtesy the artist & Sfeir-Semler Gallery, Hamburg / Beirut ISBN 978-94-028-0665-6 Printed by Ipskamp Printing To my parents, for everything Acknowledgments During the four years in which I wrote the present dissertation, I was very fortunate to have many people in my life who, directly or indirectly, contributed to my research in important ways. To begin, I am incredibly grateful to my supervisor, Paul Ziche. Not only did he hire me four years ago, without which there would not have been a dissertation in the first place, but during these years, Paul also turned out to be the most entrusting and supportive supervisor a doctoral candidate could wish for. Though I probably took the research project in a very different direction than he envisioned when he first wrote the funding proposal, he always made me feel like I had complete freedom in following my own research interests, which was incredibly motivating. Perhaps even more importantly, Paul was never narrowly focused on the research alone, but also encouraged me to develop myself more broadly, both as a scholar and as a person, and provided all the support that I could possibly have hoped for. Finally, it has been a pleasure to work with him academically.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Pyrrhonism As a Sect of Buddhism? a Case Study in the Methodology of Comparative Philosophy
    Comparative Philosophy Volume 9, No. 2 (2018): 1-40 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 / www.comparativephilosophy.org https://doi.org/10.31979/2151-6014(2018).090204 EARLY PYRRHONISM AS A SECT OF BUDDHISM? A CASE STUDY IN THE METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY MONTE RANSOME JOHNSON & BRETT SHULTS ABSTRACT: We offer a sceptical examination of a thesis recently advanced in a monograph published by Princeton University Press entitled Greek Buddha: Pyrrho’s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia. In this dense and probing work, Christopher I. Beckwith, a professor of Central Eurasian studies at Indiana University, Bloomington, argues that Pyrrho of Elis adopted a form of early Buddhism during his years in Bactria and Gandhāra, and that early Pyrrhonism must be understood as a sect of early Buddhism. In making his case Beckwith claims that virtually all scholars of Greek, Indian, and Chinese philosophy have been operating under flawed assumptions and with flawed methodologies, and so have failed to notice obvious and undeniable correspondences between the philosophical views of the Buddha and of Pyrrho. In this study we take Beckwith’s proposal and challenge seriously, and we examine his textual basis and techniques of translation, his methods of examining passages, his construal of problems and his reconstruction of arguments. We find that his presuppositions are contentious and doubtful, his own methods are extremely flawed, and that he draws unreasonable conclusions. Although the result of our study is almost entirely negative, we think it illustrates some important general points about the methodology of comparative philosophy. Keywords: adiaphora, anātman, anattā, ataraxia, Buddha, Buddhism, Democritus, Pāli, Pyrrho, Pyrrhonism, Scepticism, trilakṣaṇa 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of Pyrrho of Elis and the Pyrrhonian Praxis of Aporetic
    The Influence of Pyrrho of Elis and the Pyrrhonian Praxis of Aporetic Language by © Christopher Craig Dupuis A Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, Department of Philosophy Memorial University of Newfoundland May, 2014 St. John’s Newfoundland and Labrador 2 Table of Contents Abstract 4 Introduction and Overview 5 Chapter One 1 Pyrrho’s Aporetic Linguistic Praxis 12 1.1 Ataraxia in Epictetus and Epicurus 21 1.2 The Role of Epoche and Ataraxia in Pyrrho 23 1.3 Plato’s Socrates as Pyrrho’s Sage 43 1.4 Pyrrho and Plato’s Phaedo 45 1.5 Pyrrho, the Meno, and The Soul of The Hellenes 48 1.6 Appearances, Customs, and The Soul of the Sceptic 51 1.7 Pyrrho and Plato’s Theaetetus 55 1.8 Chapter One Conclusion 62 Chapter Two 2.1 Introduction: Academic Scepticism 64 2.2 Scepticism up to this Point 65 2.3 Arcesilaus And the Early Academic Sceptics 68 2.4 Carneades And the ‘New’ Academic Sceptics 81 2.5 Connecting with Pyrrho 91 Chapter Three 3.1 Introduction: Later Pyrrhonian Scepticism 95 3.2 Aenesidemus and the Revival of Pyrrhonism 97 3.3 Aenesidemus, Relativity, and Language Practice 107 3.4 Later Pyrrhonism: Sextus Empiricus 112 3.5 Outline of Sextus 118 3.6 Phantasiai 119 3.7 Apprehension 122 3.8 What the Sceptics Do 125 3.9 Ataraxia and Epoche 128 3.10 The Five Ways to Epoche 133 3 3.10.1 The First Trope: Diaphonia 136 3.10.2 The Second Trope: Infinite Regression 138 3.10.3 The Third Trope: Relativity 139 3.10.4 The Fourth
    [Show full text]
  • Agrippan Pyrrhonism and the Challenge of Disagreement
    Journal of Philosophical Research Volume 40 2015 pp. 23–39 AGRIPPAN PYRRHONISM AND THE CHALLENGE OF DISAGREEMENT DIEGO E. MACHUCA CONICET ABSTRACT: This paper argues for the following three claims. First, the Agrippan mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment. Second, the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Five Modes of Agrippa, which nonetheless does not prevent him from non-doxastically assenting to them. And third, some recent objec- tions to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement. I. INTRODUCTION The subject of this essay is the set of arguments known as the Five Modes of Agrippa, which are the most powerful weapons of the Pyrrhonian argumentative arsenal found in Sextus Empiricus’s extant works. My purpose is to offer an interpretation both of certain aspects of the challenge posed by these modes and of the Pyrrhonist’s attitude towards them. More precisely, I propose to show: (i) that the mode from disagreement does not play a secondary role in inducing suspension of judgment; (ii) that the Pyrrhonist is not committed to the criteria of justification underlying the Agrippan modes, which nonethe- less does not prevent him from assenting to them in a weak, non-doxastic way; and (iii) that some recent objections to Agrippan Pyrrhonism raised by analytic epistemologists and experimental philosophers fail to appreciate the Pyrrhonist’s ad hominem style of argumentation and the real challenge posed by the mode from disagreement.
    [Show full text]
  • Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius
    SAPERE Scripta Antiquitatis Posterioris ad Ethicam REligionemque pertinentia Schriften der späteren Antike zu ethischen und religiösen Fragen Herausgegeben von Rainer Hirsch-Luipold, Reinhard Feldmeier und Heinz-Günther Nesselrath unter der Mitarbeit von Natalia Pedrique und Andrea Villani Band XXV Pyrrhonian Skepticism in Diogenes Laertius Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary and Interpretative Essays by Katja Maria Vogt, Richard Bett, Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi, Christiana M. M. Olfert, Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley, and James Warren edited by Katja Maria Vogt Mohr Siebeck SAPERE is a Project of the Göttingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony. e-ISBN PDF 978-3-16-156430-7 ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5 The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Natio nal- bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http:// dnb.dnb.de. © 2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen, Germany. www.mohr.de This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This ap- plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro- cessing in electronic systems. This book was supervised by Heinz-Günther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani at the SAPERE Research Institute, Göttingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tübin- gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier. Printed in Germany. SAPERE Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (1st–4th centuries AD) have for a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called ‘classi- cal’ times.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E
    Philosophy Compass 6/4 (2011): 246–258, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00391.x Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E. Machuca* Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı´ficas y Te´cnicas Abstract Pyrrhonism was one of the two main ancient skeptical traditions. In this second paper of the three-part series devoted to ancient skepticism, I present and discuss some of the issues on Pyrrho- nian skepticism which have been the focus of much attention in the recent literature. The topics to be addressed concern the outlooks of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. In the first paper of this three-part series on ancient skepticism, I offered a general pre- sentation of the ancient skeptical traditions as well as an overview of recent translations and general studies. With this framework in place, the present paper deals with some vexed questions concerning the stances of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. For reasons of space, the discussion will be selective and it will not always be possible to go into detail about the issues tackled. 1. Pyrrho Most recent scholarship on Pyrrho of Elis (360–270 BC) continues to divide between two main interpretations of his outlook, which may be called ‘practical’ and ‘theoretical’. The first interpretation affirms that Pyrrho’s motivation was exclusively or mainly ethi- cal.1 This view finds support in some passages in Diogenes Laertius and particularly in Cicero, who does not refer to Pyrrho as a skeptic, but invariably portrays him as a moral- ist – as someone who considered virtue as the only good and who was admired for his lifestyle (Academica II 130; On Moral Ends III 11–2, IV 43, 49, 60; On Duties I 6).
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Scepticism by Harald Thorsrud Ancient Philosophies
    Ancient Scepticism by Harald Thorsrud Ancient Philosophies. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2009. Pp. vxi + 248. ISBN 978--0--520--26026--9.Paper $24.95 Reviewed by Katja Maria Vogt Columbia University [email protected] Harald Thorsrud’s introduction to ancient scepticism is written for an audience of undergraduate students and non-specialists who want a knowledgeable, trustworthy, detailed, and nevertheless accessible introduction. Thorsrud is so successful at this that, in effect, his book will also be valuable for graduate students and scholars. An introduction to ancient scepticism is no easy task—one must explain the arguments of a wide range of thinkers, whose names often mean next-to-nothing even to educated readers. First, there are the sceptical philosophers, among whom are Pyrrho, Arcesilaus, Carneades, Philo, Cicero, Aenesidemus, Agrippa, and Sextus Empiri- cus. Next, there are their contemporary interlocutors and opponents: various Stoics, Epicureans, Platonists, Peripatetics, and so on. Fi- nally, there are the doxographers and commentators through whose writings we have much of our information about ancient scepticism. Accordingly, an introduction to ancient scepticism must be informed by a nuanced understanding of large parts of classical philosophy, of the goals and idiosyncrasies of various lesser known authors, as well as of the longstanding history of some of the basic intuitions, often reaching back to Presocratic philosophy. A good introduction to ancient scepticism is, thus, a consider- able achievement. Every chapter in Thorsrud’s book displays the kind of nuance and judgment that can only come from detailed study of more than the immediately relevant writings of ancient scep- tics.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Skepticism: the Skeptical Academy Diego Machuca* Consejo Nacional De Investigaciones Cientı´ficas Y Te´Cnicas
    Philosophy Compass 6/4 (2011): 259–266, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00390.x Ancient Skepticism: The Skeptical Academy Diego Machuca* Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı´ficas y Te´cnicas Abstract Ancient philosophy knew two main skeptical traditions: the Pyrrhonian and the Academic. In this final paper of the three-part series devoted to ancient skepticism, I present some of the topics about Academic skepticism which have recently been much debated in the specialist literature. I will be concerned with the outlooks of Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Philo of Larissa. While the first article devoted to ancient skepticism provided an overview of the skeptical traditions and the second discussed certain vexed issues regarding Pyrrhonism, this third and final article will focus on some interpretative controversies concerning the thought of the main figures of the skeptical Academy: Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Philo of Larissa. 1. Arcesilaus Arcesilaus of Pitane (316⁄5–241 ⁄0 BC) was the scholarch who inaugurated the skeptical phase in the Academy. It is important to bear in mind that he did not regard his skepti- cism as a break from the philosophy of his predecessors, since he considered Socrates and Plato to be authentic skeptics. In this connection, note that Cicero presents Socrates as recognizing his almost total ignorance, and declares that in Plato’s dialogs there are argu- ments on both sides of an issue and nothing is affirmed to be certain but everything is under investigation (Academica I 44–6, II 74). Although Diogenes Laertius says that Arce- silaus argued both sides of a case (DL IV 28), it seems that the latter’s standard argumen- tative procedure was to argue against the theses stated by his interlocutors, a practice which accords well with Socrates’ elenctic method as depicted in Plato’s early dialogs.1 In any case, both argumentative practices result in a state of equipollence or equal force (isos- theneia), thereby inducing suspension of judgment (epoche).
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy: Theory and Practice
    Russian Academy of Sciences Institute of Philosophy Philosophy: Theory and Practice Moscow 2013 УДК 100 ББК 87 Р 57 Editors V. Sharova, E. Trufanova, A. Yakovleva Р 57 Philosophy: Theory and Practice / Russian Academy of Sciences, Institute of Philosophy; Ed.: V. Sharova, E. Trufanova, A. Yakovleva. – М. : ИФ РАН, 2013. – 268 p. ; 20 см. – 500 экз. – ISBN 978-5-9540-0258-4. This book is a collection of papers presented at the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy (4–10 August, 2013, Athens, Greece) by research fellows and affiliated students and postgraduates of the Institute of Philosophy of the Russian Academy of Sciences. The pa- pers represent a broad variety of philosophical subjects lying within such disciplines as epistemology, history of philosophy, philosophy of science, ethics, social and political philosophy, logic etc. ISBN 978-5-9540-0258-4 © Athors, 2013 © Institute of Philosophy RAS, 2013 CONTENTS Guseynov A. Philosophy as an Ethical Project .............................................................. 5 I. Epistemology and Logic Lektorskiy V. Rationality in Contemporary Culture .................................................... 22 Avtonomova N. Roman Jakobson’s Life in Language and the Epistemological Potential of His Idea of Structure ........................................ 28 Beskova I. Human Embodiment as a Complex Phenomenon ..................................... 32 Kanaev I. Awareness of the Body as a Form of Self-Consciousness .......................... 37 Kasavin I. Underdetermination of Knowledge by Context: A
    [Show full text]
  • Unmitigated Skepticism: the Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism
    UC San Diego UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Unmitigated Skepticism: The Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/6fk1n2b1 Author Wong, Andrew David Publication Date 2017 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, SAN DIEGO Unmitigated Skepticism: The Nature and Scope of Pyrrhonism A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Andrew David Wong Committee in charge: Professor Monte Johnson, Chair Professor Casey Perin, Co-Chair Professor Samuel Rickless Professor Donald Rutherford Professor Edward Watts 2017 © Andrew David Wong, 2017 All rights reserved. The Dissertation of Andrew David Wong is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: Co-Chair Chair University of California, San Diego 2017 iii DEDICATION To my mother and father iv EPIGRAPH By way of preface let us say that on none of the matters to be discussed do we affirm that things certainly are just as we say they are: rather, wereport descriptively on each item according to how it appears to us at the time. Sextus Empiricus v TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page ................................... iii Dedication ..................................... iv Epigraph ...................................... v Table of Contents ................................. viii List of Abbreviations ...............................
    [Show full text]
  • The Project Gutenberg Ebook of Sextus Empiricus and Greek
    Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism A Dissertation for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the University of Bern By Mary Mills Patrick Cambridge Deighton Bel & Co. 1899 2 Preface The following treatise on Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism has been prepared to supply a need much felt in the English language by students of Greek philosophy. For while other schools of Greek philosophy have been exhaustively and critically discussed by English scholars, there are few sources of information available to the student who wishes to make himself familiar with the teachings of Pyrrhonism. The aim has been, accordingly, to give a concise presentation of Pyrrhonism in relation to its historical development and the Scepticism of the Academy, with critical references to the French and German works existing on the subject. The time and manner of the connection of Sextus Empiricus with the Pyrrhonean School has also been discussed. In study of the works of Sextus, the Greek text of Immanuel Bekker, Berlin, 1842, has been used, with frequent consultation of the text of J.A. Fabricius, 1718, which was taken directly from the existing manuscripts of the works of Sextus. References to Diogenes Laertius and other ancient works have been carefully verified. The principal modern authors consulted are the following: Ritter, Geschichte der Philosophie, II. Auf., Hamburg, 1836-38. Zeller, Philosophie der Griechen, III. Auf., Leipzig, 1879-89. Lewes, History of Philosophy, Vol. I., London, 1866. Ueberweg, History of Philosophy, IV. ed., translated by Morris, 1871. Brochard, Les Sceptiques Grecs, Paris, 1877. Brochard, Pyrrhon et le Scepticism Primitive, No.
    [Show full text]