Copernicus As Natural Philosopher

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Copernicus As Natural Philosopher CHAPTER NINE COPERNICUS AS NATURAL PHILOSOPHER 1. Introduction When two of the leading experts on Copernicus characterized him as an Aristotelian, they were without doubt referring to his retention of celestial spheres as the movers of the planets and to his views in natu- ral philosophy.1 Although other experts have pointed to non-Aristote- lian sources of Copernicus’s account of motion and natural elemental motion, I have concluded that Copernicus also drew on schools and communities of the Aristotelian tradition. He combined them into an uneasy synthesis with all of the ambiguities and inconsistencies that one would expect. Teachers and students within the Aristotelian tradi- tion modifi ed Aristotelian doctrine, oft en interpreting it in ways that combined the fundamental principles of other authors and Judaic- Christian doctrines, and thereby created a synthesis that is diffi cult to 1 Rosen, Introduction to Letter, Complete Works, 3: 134, comments: “[F]amiliarity with Aristotle’s treatises does not of course make Copernicus an Aristotelian in the sense that he regarded the Stagirite as infallible. On the contrary, where he detected a fl aw in Aristotle, as in the Stagirite’s division of simple motion into three mutually exclusive types, he did not hesitate to correct it. But he did not undertake to over- throw Aristotelianism, as he did the Ptolemaic astronomy. On the other hand, what he believed was sound in both systems, he retained with gratitude and aff ection, an attitude which some of our contemporaries would do well to consider.” Compare with the assertion of Swerdlow, “Copernicus,” 162–168, esp. 164–165: “For these physical problems raised by the motions of the earth, which should also aff ect the motion of birds, clouds, and projectiles, Copernicus made what he considered to be a minimal alteration of Aristotelian natural motion of the elements, such that the natural motion of a spherical body, whatever its substance, is to rotate in place by virtue of its form alone. Th e daily rotation of the spherical earth together with the surrounding water and air is, therefore, entirely natural; projectiles, birds, and clouds are simply carried along with the rotating earth; and heaviness (gravitas), the descent of heavy bodies to their natural place, the surface of the earth, in straight lines, is due to a ‘natural inclination placed in the parts’ to come together to form a globe. In proposing this explanation, Copernicus did not intend to overthrow or displace Aristotelian physics but to adapt it to the motion of the earth, unlike Galileo Galilei (1564–1642), who later used much the same principles as Copernicus for a devastating attack on Aristotle. In fact, the objections to the motion of the earth were not completely answered until Isaac Newton (1642–1727).” 326 chapter nine reconcile with genuine Aristotelianism. Be that as it may, this was the Aristotelianism that Copernicus encountered, and it is far from clear how much he realized or, for that matter, even cared about the authen- ticity of classical authors’ views. Or, to put it diff erently, his concern, shared by the authors of the Aristotelian tradition, was to arrive at the truth, and to adopt Aristotelian views where they agreed and adapt his views where they did not.2 2. Copernicus’s Critique of Geocentrism In chapter four, I summarized the principal Aristotelian cosmologi- cal assumptions and conclusions relevant to Copernicus’s arguments. From the point of view of natural philosophy and physics in particu- lar, we have been conditioned to view Copernicus as having antici- pated the successful mechanical principles enunciated defi nitively by Newton some one hundred and forty-four years aft er the appear- ance of De revolutionibus. Despite the successful historical revision of Copernicus’s astronomical achievements as a conservative continu- ation and even fulfi llment of the goals of Ptolemaic astronomy, the topos of anticipation still dominates the standard representations of his vision of cosmology, natural philosophy, and physics.3 Even when some readers acknowledge the survival of Platonic and Aristotelian principles in Copernicus’s understanding of cosmology, they have still left the impression that he anticipated essentially anti- Aristotelian solutions to several problems and questions. Because of the success of the Newtonian program, such readings of Copernicus seem plausible.4 2 See chapter four on the Aristotelian tradition and on Aristotelian schools and sects. 3 An excellent example is Pedersen and Pihl, Early Physics, 317. Th is text provides one of the best accounts of ancient and early modern astronomy but reads Copernicus’s intentions about natural philosophy from the viewpoint of contemporaneous negative reactions by Aristotelians and from the viewpoint of later physical astronomy. In his text, Birth, chs. 1–3, Cohen adopts for pedagogical purposes a portrayal of Aristotelian dynamics that was so incompatible with the Copernican theory that a new theory had to be developed. My own earlier essays, for example, Goddu, “Dialectic,” 95–131, at 125–131, also portray Copernicus as having left the physical questions for a later day, thus suggesting that Copernicus anticipated a non-Aristotelian solution. 4 Exceptions are Moraux, “Copernic et Aristote,” 225–238, and Swerdlow, “Coper- nicus,” 163..
Recommended publications
  • Avoiding the Void: Avicenna on the Impossibility of Circular Motion in a Void*
    Created on 24 December 2006 at 20.51 hours page 1 Avoiding the Void: Avicenna on the Impossibility of Circular Motion in a Void* Jon McGinnis The topic of the void was of significant philosophical and scientific importance in the ancient and medieval world. Some, such as the atomists, maintained that the void was essential if one were to explain motion. Others, such as Aristotle, argued that the exis- tence of the void would absolutely preclude the possibility of motion. Moreover, there were disputes concerning even how to characterize the void. Thus the atomists claimed that interstitial voids were dispersed throughout every body and existed alongside bo- dies in an infinite space. Others, such as the Stoics, held that all bodies were localized in a plenum that was itself situated in an extra-cosmic, infinite void. Still others, such as the Neoplatonist John Philoponus, thought that the void was finite, and although as a matter of fact it is never devoid of a body, it at least is capable of existing independent of any body. The above roughly provides the gamut of positions concerning the void as it reached the medieval Arabic philosopher Avicenna ( 370–428/ 980–1037). In one form or another, Avicenna was aware of the various moves and counter-moves associated with the notion of the void. Like Aristotle, he maintained that the existence of the void would absolutely preclude the possibility of motion. His arguments in some cases simply rehearse those of Aristotle; in other places they expand on the thought of Aristotle in order to respond to new threats that arose after Aristotle’s own time; and in certain situations Avicenna constructs new arguments against the void used neither by Aristotle nor, from what we can gather, Aristotle’s later Greek commentators.
    [Show full text]
  • Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy Richard C
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by epublications@Marquette Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2004 Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. "Separate Material Intellect in Averroes' Mature Philosophy," in Words, Texts and Concepts Cruising the Mediterranean Sea. Eds. Gerhard Endress, Rud̈ iger Arnzen and J Thielmann. Leuven; Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2004: 289-309. Permalink. © 2004 Peeters Publishers. Used with permission. ORIENTALIA LOVANIENSIA ANALECTA ---139--- 'WORDS, TEXTS AND CONCEPTS CRUISING THE MEDITERRANEAN SEA Studies on the sources, contents and influences of Islamic civilization and Arabic philosophy and science Dedicated to Gerhard Endress on his sixty-fifth birthday edited by R. ARNZEN and J. THIELMANN UITGEVERIJ PEETERS en DEPARTEMENT OOSTERSE STUDIES LEUVEN - PARIS - DUDLEY, MA 2004 SEPARATE MATERIAL INTELLECT IN A VERROES' MATURE PHILOSOPHY Richard C. T AYLOR Marquette University, Milwaukee The doctrine of the material intellect promulgated by Averroes (i126- 1198) in his latest works is surely the teaching for which he has been most maligned both in the medieval era and in modern times. In medi­ eval times Duns Scotus spoke of "That accursed Averroes" whose "fan­ tastic conception, intelligible neither to himself nor to others, assumes the intellective part of man to be a sort
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics Richard C
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 10-1-1998 Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Journal of the History of Philosophy, Vol. 36, No. 4 (October, 1998): 507-523. DOI. Copyright © 1998 Journal of the History of Philosophy, Inc. This article first appeared in Journal of the History of Philosophy 36:4 (1998), 507-523. Reprinted with permission by The oJ hns Hopkins University Press. Averroes on Psychology and the Principles of Metaphysics I RICHARD C. TAYLOR FIRST TRANSLATED FROM Arabic into Latin in the early thirteenth century, the philosophical works of Averroes were initially respected as valuable aids to understanding the true philosophy of Aristotle. William of Auvergne, Bishop of Paris and author of a philosophically astute theological synthesis of Greek and Arabic thought with Christian doctrine, openly expressed his appreciation with praise for Averroes. But by the mid-thirteenth century many of Averroes' teachings were under attack with his conceptions of human nature and separate immaterial intellect the subject of sharply focussed and heated argumentative assaults by Aquinas, Albert and others3 Their arguments were not primarily theological but rather philosophical criticisms which charged that Averroes, Drafts of this paper were presented at a conference sponsored by the International Society for the History of Arabic and Islamic Science and Philosophy at the Smithsonian Institution in Washington, DC, March 28, 1996, and at the annual meeting of the Medieval Academy of America in Toronto, Canada, April 19, 1997. I benefited from discussions of this article with Alfred Ivry, my colleagues, David B.
    [Show full text]
  • A Cultural History of Physics
    Károly Simonyi A Cultural History of Physics Translated by David Kramer Originally published in Hungarian as A fizika kultûrtörténete, Fourth Edition, Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, 1998, and published in German as Kulturgeschichte der Physik, Third Edition, Verlag Harri Deutsch, Frankfurt am Main, 2001. First Hungarian edition 1978. CRC Press Taylor & Francis Group 6000 Broken Sound Parkway NW, Suite 300 Boca Raton, FL 33487-2742 © 2012 by Taylor & Francis Group, LLC CRC Press is an imprint of Taylor & Francis Group, an Informa business No claim to original U.S. Government works Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper Version Date: 20111110 International Standard Book Number: 978-1-56881-329-5 (Hardback) This book contains information obtained from authentic and highly regarded sources. Reasonable efforts have been made to publish reliable data and information, but the author and publisher cannot assume responsibility for the validity of all materials or the consequences of their use. The authors and publishers have attempted to trace the copyright holders of all material reproduced in this publication and apologize to copyright holders if permission to publish in this form has not been obtained. If any copyright material has not been acknowl- edged please write and let us know so we may rectify in any future reprint. Except as permitted under U.S. Copyright Law, no part of this book may be reprinted, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system, without written permission from the publishers.
    [Show full text]
  • Avicenna's Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon Mcginnis University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 1-2015 A Small Discovery: Avicenna's Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon McGinnis University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/philosophy-faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation McGinnis, J. "A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia." Journal of the History of Philosophy, vol. 53 no. 1, 2015, pp. 1-24. Project MUSE, doi:10.1353/hph.2015.0002 http://irl.umsl.edu/philosophy-faculty/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon McGinnis Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 53, Number 1, January 2015, pp. 1-24 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2015.0002 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/566924 Access provided by Missouri @ St Louis, Univ of (17 Feb 2017 19:06 GMT) A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia JON MCGINNIS* ABSTRACT There has been a long-held misconception among historians of philosophy and science that apart from brief comments in Aristotle and Averroes, the theory of minima naturalia had to await Latin Schoolmen for its full articulation. Recently scholars have shown that far from sporadic comments on minima naturalia, Averroes in fact had a fully developed and well-integrated theory of them.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Physics
    Published in modified form in: K. Lee Lerner & Brenda W. Lerner (Hg.): Scientific Thought in Context , Detroit: Gale, 2008, Vol. 2, pp. 759-768 Copyright © 2006 by Joachim Schummer Aristotelian Physics by Joachim Schummer 1. Introduction No other philosopher had such a deep and long-standing impact on Western science as Aristotle. In the fourth century BC he developed a fully comprehensive worldview that would with only few modifications stand for about two thousand years. Rather than just collecting isolated facts, he posed fundamental questions about nature and about the methods to study nature. Physics in the Aristotelian sense included the fundamental understanding of matter, change, causality, time, and space, which needed to be consistent with logic and experience. From that he derived a cosmology that allowed him to explain all phenomena, from everyday life to astronomy including both natural phenomena and technology. Aristotle (384-322) lived in a time period of extreme political turbulences that deeply shaped his biography. When the 17-year old Macedonian moved to Athens to enroll at the famous Academy of Plato, the state of Athens had lost its former political hegemony, but still had an international reputation in education. Ten years later the King of Macedonia, Philip, began to conquer the Greek states, which resulted in growing anti-Macedonian sentiments in Athens. When his patron Plato died in 347 and Athens declared war against Macedonia, there was no way for Aristotle to stay longer in Athens. He escaped to Asia Minor before Philip employed him to tutor his aspiring son Alexander. This Alexander would soon conquer the by then largest empire, ranging from Greece eastwards to India and southwards to Egypt.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and Aristotelianism
    Aristotle and Medieval Universities Rob Iliffe Introduction • This lecture deals with the science (natural philosophy) of Aristotle and Plato, Greeks who lived nearly 2500 years ago. • Their legacy lasted in Western philosophy for 2000+ years • We will look at the other-worldly, largely mathematical philosophy of Plato and the ‘empirical’, observational science of Aristotle. • Concludes with discussion of role of Aristotelian philosophy in medieval and early modern European universities. Plato (427-347 BCE) • Student of Socrates and teacher of Aristotle; founded Academy in Athens. • Early dialogues concerned life and teachings of Socrates. • Key later works were the utopian (or dystopian) Republic, and the creation myth Timaeus. • Key idea was of ‘Forms’ or ‘ideas’ (e.g. in Phaedo) – • these are perfect exemplars of characteristics such as beauty, virtue and justice (and of course, love), • which supposedly exist in some reality lying beyond the senses. • We can only perceive these dimly, as if we are in a Cave able only to see the shadows of the brightly lit Forms Roman bust of Plato, copy of original made for Athenian Academy (c. 370 BCE) The Significance of Mathematics • Plato influenced by the numerical philosophy of Pythagoras • In the Republic he was highly dismissive of the Arts, esp. poetry, which was to be banned for provoking unnatural emotions. • Instead one should study arithmetic, plane and solid geometry, astronomy and harmonics – which aim at what is eternal. • After this one should study philosophy. • But key claim was that mathematics is both beautiful and useful for training the mind, hence necessary for the education of the soldier-philosophers who were guardians of the Republic.
    [Show full text]
  • Infinities As Natural Places
    Infinities as natural places Juliano C. S. Neves∗ Universidade Estadual de Campinas (UNICAMP), Instituto de Matemática, Estatística e Computação Científica, Campinas, SP, Brazil Abstract It is shown that a notion of natural place is possible within modern physics. For Aristotle, the elements—the primary components of the world—follow to their natural places in the absence of forces. On the other hand, in general relativity, the so-called Carter-Penrose diagrams offer a notion of end for objects along the geodesics. Then, the notion of natural place in Aristotelian physics has an analog in the notion of conformal infinities in general relativity. Keywords: Aristotle, Natural Places, General Relativity, Carter-Penrose Diagrams 1 Introduction Alongside Plato’s works, Aristotle’s philosophy is the most influential philosophical system created in ancient Greece. The master of the Lyceum built seminal works in all areas of knowledge. In natural sciences, Aristotelian physics was “ruled out” only in modernity, or modern era, by Newtonian physics. The main difference between Newtonian and Aristotelian physics may be found in the cause of the motion of bodies. For Aristotle (1922b, 319b30), change in general (spatial, qualitative, quantitative, and substantial) is produced by causes.1 There are four types of cause for the Greek philosopher: material, formal, efficient, and final. In Aristotle, the motion of bodies is always described by a final cause. The final cause arXiv:1803.07995v2 [physics.hist-ph] 21 Jul 2018 provides a purpose for the motion. On the other hand, in Newtonian physics, the notion of final cause for the motion of bodies is rejected.2 Newton’s laws do not adopt final causes to describe falling bodies or planets around the sun.
    [Show full text]
  • An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Matter in the Context of Change
    ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE AN EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE By HORATIO ION BOT, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in Parital Fulfilment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts McMaster University (c) Copyright by Horatio Ion Bot, April 1992 MASTER OF ARTS (1992) McMASTER UNNERSITY (Philosophy) Hamilton, Ontario TITLE: An Examination of Aristotle's Concept of Matter in the Context of Change AUTHOR: Horatio I. Bot, B.A. (University of Toronto) SUPERVISIOR: Professor C. Georgiadis NUMBEROFPAGES: v, 108 ii ABSTRACT The concept of matter is discussed by Aristotle in the context of investigations dealing with the issues of causality, substance, and change. The following inquiry focusses on the discussion of matter in the context of change by analysing the two accounts of change that Aristotle gives in the first book of the Physics and the ninth book of the Metaphysics, respectively. The two schemas of change are outlined and the development of the concept of matter is followed from the hypokeimenon of accidental change, to the primary matter of elemental change, to the matter that underlies substantial change and finally to the potential of the second model of change. iii '' ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This paper was written with the help and the seemingly endless patience and good humour of Professor Constantine Georgiadis and with the support and occasional threats of Donna Lim. iv TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 1: The Problem. • . 1 CHAPTER 2: Substrate as Matter . 23 CHAPTER 3: Prime Matter and Substantial Change .
    [Show full text]
  • Where Is the Heaven? the Story of an Aristotelian Problem and Its Presentation in Jewish Medieval Sources
    Julia SCHWARTZMANN WHERE IS THE HEAVEN? THE STORY OF AN ARISTOTELIAN PROBLEM AND ITS PRESENTATION IN JEWISH MEDIEVAL SOURCES Introduction It is well known that Aristotle's concept of place is one of the fundamen- tal principles of his natural philosophy, and especially, of his mechanics. Although the existence of place is, according to him, an obvious fact, he takes pains in the first chapters of the Physics IV to prove it once again. Only after that he elaborates about the nature of place and its definition. Subsequently, he defines place as “the primary motionless boundary of that which contains"1. By establishing in the Physics IV an unbreakable bond between place and motion and by introducing the notion of natural places, Aristotle opens the way to his concept of the physical world as an autonomous self-energizing organism. It is not incidental that the investigation of the nature of place, crucial for the understanding of the Aristotelian theory of motion, is followed in the next chapters by a methodical refutation of the void. It is not incidental either, that those, who like Philoponus or Rabbi Hisdai Crescas opposed Aristotle's concept of the world, rejected both his definition of place and the bond between place and motion. In order to refute Aristotle's mechanics they had to minimize the importance of place and to reinstate the legitimacy of the void2. It seems that the definition of place as “the primary motionless boundary of that which contains" fits quite well the notion of place within the world, and especially, that of bodies having a rectilinear motion.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Antecedents of Leibniz's Principles
    Some Antecedents of Leibniz’s Principles by Martinho Antônio Bittencourt de Castro A thesis submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of History and Philosophy University of New South Wales Sydney, Australia April 2008 2 Declaration I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgement is made in the thesis. Any contribution made to the research by others, with whom I have worked at UNSW or elsewhere, is explicitly acknowledged in the thesis. I also declare that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work, except to the extent that assistance from others in the project's design and conception or in style, presentation and linguistic expression is acknowledged. Date: 12 June 2008 3 Abstract Leibniz considered that scepticism and confusion engendered by the disputes of different sects or schools of metaphysics were obstacles to the progress of knowledge in philosophy. His solution was to adopt an eclectic method with the aim of uncovering the truth hidden beneath the dispute of schools. Leibniz’s project was, having in mind the eclectic method, to synthesise a union between old pre-modern philosophy, based on formal and final causes, and new modern philosophy which gave preference to efficient causes. The result of his efforts is summarised in the Monadology.
    [Show full text]
  • The Elements of Avicenna's Physics Greek Sources And
    The Elements of Avicenna’s Physics Greek Sources and Arabic Innovations Andreas Lammer München 15. März 2016 The Elements of Avicenna’s Physics Greek Sources and Arabic Innovations Inaugural-Dissertation zur Erlangung des Doktorgrades der Philosophie an der Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München vorgelegt von Andreas Lammer aus Würzburg am 15. März 2016 Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Peter Adamson Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Dag Nikolaus Hasse Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 27. Juni 2016 Contents Preface vii Introduction 1 1 The Arabic Fate of Aristotle’s Physics 9 1.1 Transmission and Translation . 10 1.2 The Commentators on the Aristotelian Text . 17 1.3 Avicenna’s Copy of the Physics ....................... 29 2 The Methodology of Teaching and Learning 35 2.1 The Method of Physics . 35 2.2 Method and Principles between Physics and Metaphysics . 72 3 The Subject-Matter of Physics 97 3.1 Body, Substance, and Corporeality . 100 3.2 Matter and Form as Common Principles . 138 3.3 Change and an Additional Principle . 183 4 Nature and Power 195 4.1 Nature, and Soul, in the Greek Philosophical Tradition . 196 4.2 Avicenna’s Commentary on Physics II.1, 192b20–23 . 207 4.3 Avicenna, and Philoponus, on Inclination . 222 4.4 Bad Readings of Aristotle . 233 4.5 Avicenna’s Account of Nature and its Relation to Soul . 260 5 Place, Space, and Void 285 5.1 A Troubled Account of Place . 287 5.2 Clarifying Aristotle’s Troubled Account of Place . 303 5.3 Eliminating Void and Space . 343 v vi Contents 6 Time and Temporality in the Physical World 397 6.1 A New Approach to an Old Definition .
    [Show full text]