The Development of Theory of Mind According to False Belief Performance of Children Ages 3 to 5

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Development of Theory of Mind According to False Belief Performance of Children Ages 3 to 5 Kuram ve Uygulamada Eğitim Bilimleri • Educational Sciences: Theory & Practice - 11(4) • Autumn • 1821-1826 ©2011 Eğitim Danışmanlığı ve Araştırmaları İletişim Hizmetleri Tic. Ltd. Şti. The Development of Theory of Mind According to False Belief Performance of Children Ages 3 to 5 Bahar KEÇELİ KAYSILI a Funda ACARLAR Ankara University Ankara University Abstract This study has examined the role of age in the false belief understanding in typically developing children and to determine if the different type of false belief tasks affects performance on false belief. The survey research de- sign was used. False belief understanding was measured in 72 children between the ages of 3.00 to 5.11 year old. The sample consisted of 12 children in each age group and age groups were divided into six month period. Four false belief tasks were conducted. The findings of this study indicated that the false belief understanding of Turkish speaking children between the ages of 3.0 to 5.11 year old had some similarities as well as some dif- ferences to children speaking other than Turkish. 3 year old children seemed to have developed an understan- ding of the own false belief before they developed a clear understanding of others’ false belief. It was clear that the rapid change of understanding false belief seemed to have appeared at 4.6 year old. Key Words Theory of Mind, False Belief, Mind Reading. Theory of mind refers to an understanding of men- use of mental state words and pretend play (Miller, tal states such as belief, desire and knowledge that 2006). Between 3 and 5 years of age, important de- enables us to explain and predict others’ behavior velopmental changes in theory of mind take place (Wellman & Estes, 1986). In brief, theory of mind (de Villiers & Pyers, 2002; Flavell, Everett, Croft, is to be able to reflect on the contents of one’s own & Flavell, 1981; Wellman, Cross, & Watson, 2001; and other minds (Baron-Cohen, 2000). Develop- Youngblade & Dunn, 1995). Two year old children mental evidence suggests that such thinking is not might understand desires, perception, and emo- automatic for young children, who must develop a tions (Bartsch & Wellman, 1995; Wellman, Philips, number of skills in order to reach the adult level & Rodriguez, 2000). Children at three years can of competence in understanding of mental states. distinguish between the mental and physical Precursors of theory of mind include joint atten- worlds and from three years of age children can tion, appreciation of intentionality, recognition grasp the subjectivity of thoughts (Flavell, Flavell, that different people have different perspectives, Green, & Moses, 1990; Watson, Gelman, & Well- man, 1998; Wellman & Estes, 1986). Three and four year olds also distinguish thinking from do- a Bahar KEÇELİ KAYSILI is currently a lecturer and ing (Flavell, Green & Flavell, 1995). Mental states a doctorate student at the Department of Special are not only non-physical; they also provide the Education, Her research interests include teac- causes and explanations for persons’ actions and hing language and communication to children experiences (Wellman & Lagattuta, 2000). Most with autism and developmental relationships subsequent research on the development of theory between language and theory of mind. Corres- pondence: Bahar Keçeli Kaysılı, Ankara Univer- of mind has concerned false beliefs between 3 and sity, Faculty of Educational Sciences, Department 5 years of age, and their role in the prediction or of Special Education, Ankara/Turkey. E-mail: explanation of behavior, and in attempts to manip- [email protected] Phone: +90 312 ulate behavior. Wimmer and Perner (1983) showed 363 33 50/3014. 1821 EDUCATIONAL SCIENCES: THEORY & PRACTICE that a full-fledged TOM doesn’t develop before the Without doubt, there is a relation between lan- age of 3/4. They set up a series of experimental tests guage and false belief understanding. There are in order to check whether children between 3 and three possibilities about this relation: theory of 5 years of age were able to attribute a false belief mind depends on language; or language depends to someone else. Comprehending false belief is on theory of mind; or both depend on a third fac- the clearest sign of understanding a critical aspect tor (Astington & Jenkins, 1999). Granti (2004) of the mind: its subjectivity and its susceptibility suggested that Turkish speaking children start to to manipulation by information (Dennett, 1978; establish some understanding about other minds Wimmer & Perner, 1983). starting around 3 years of age. Children’s perfor- mance revealed highest level of understanding for Widely used versions of first order false belief tasks the verb sanmak “think with implication of false are the appearance reality distinction, the unex- belief” as compared to other mental verbs, but pected contents false belief and change in location understanding of mental verbs did not precede tasks. They are called first-order tests because they false belief understanding. Aksu-Koç, Aydın, Avcı, only involve inferring one person’s mental state. Sefer and Yaşa (2005), suggested that a sig¬nificant According to Wellman et al. (2001) study allowed interaction effect between age and type of task an estimate of the probability of passing the false showing that 4 year-olds scored higher than 3 year- belief task at various ages: At 2.5 years, children olds on false belief tasks but no age effect found were less than likely to pass false belief tasks; at 3 on appearance-reality tasks. Shatz, Diesendruck, years 8 months, children were 50% correct; and at Martinez-Beck and Akar, (2003), investigated 4 years 8 months children were about 75% correct. whether differences in the lexical explicitness with Younger children (3 years and 5 months or young- which languages express false belief influence chil- er) either fail or perform at chance levels, whereas dren’s performance on standard false belief tasks. older children pass the task, giving an adult like Bayramoğlu and Hohenberger (2007) investigated answer at better than chance levels (Flavell, 1999; the theory of mind development of 4 and 5 year old Moses & Flavell, 1990; Wimmer & Perner, 1983). Turkish preschoolers. The results indicated that a Individual differences in children’s theory of mind main effect of age was found. Researchers suggest have been proposed by Bartsch and Estes (1996). that 4 year old children can predict the actions of These are individual differences in antecedent someone with a false belief and there are measur- causes, individual differences in the consequences able individual differences in the mind reading of arriving early or late to a theory of mind, the abilities of young children (Wellman et al., 2001). possibility of qualitative differences in theory of Therefore, it is important to conduct studies in mind across individuals (family variables, other languages other than English. It would certainly cognitive and language abilities and various social add weight to findings about mind reading abili- outcome measures). Children in different countries ties of young children if they are replicated. Also it performed differently in the false belief tasks: At 44 is important to determine the relationship between months, American children were 50% correct, Aus- false belief understanding and other areas like lan- tralians were 69% correct and Japanese were 40% guage, cognitive constructs and social outcomes.In correct (Wellman et al., 2001). Nevertheless, within Turkey there are several studies investigated theory each country the age profile had a similar shape, of mind performances of children between 3 to 5 with poor performance in younger children and years old (Aksu-Koç et al., 2005; Granti, 2004). In better performance in older children. The research these studies standard false belief tasks were ad- literature suggests that there are measurable indi- ministered. Also in this study standard false belief vidual differences in the mind reading abilities of tasks (appearance-reality and unexpected content young children (Lewis & Osborne, 1990; Slaughter and three versions of change in location) were ad- & Gopnik, 1996), and that these individual differ- ministered. ences are correlated with variables like family vari- The aim of the present study was to examine the ables, other cognitive constructs like language and role of age in the false belief understanding in various social outcome measures (Hughes, 1998; Turkish speaking children and to determine if the Jenkins & Astington, 2000; Ruffman, Perner, & Par- different type of false belief tasks affects perform- kin, 1999; Slaughter & Repacholi, 2003; Yağmurlu, ance on false belief. Kazak-Berument, & Çelimli, 2005). 1822 KEÇELİ KAYSILI, ACARLAR / The Development of Theory of Mind According to False Belief Performance of Children... Method rally specific and syntactically straightforward enable most 3 year olds to attribute false beliefs of Model others. Therefore questions were posed with tem- While conducting the research, which was aimed poral markers and with specific false belief verb to determine the role of age in the false belief un- form “san” (What will X think (san) is inside the derstanding in Turkish speaking children and to box before I opened it?). A score of 0 to 3 was given determine if the different type of false belief tasks for the unexpected content task. affects performance on false belief, the survey Three “change in location” false belief tasks (Baron- research design was
Recommended publications
  • Mind Body Problem and Brandom's Analytic Pragmatism
    The Mind-Body Problem and Brandom’s Analytic Pragmatism François-Igor Pris [email protected] Erfurt University (Nordhäuserstraße 63, 99089 Erfurt, Germany) Abstract. I propose to solve the hard problem in the philosophy of mind by means of Brandom‟s notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. The explanatory gap between a phenomenal concept and the corresponding theoretical concept is a gap in the pragmatically mediated semantic relation between them. It is closed if we do not neglect the pragmatics. 1 Introduction In the second section, I will formulate the hard problem. In the third section, I will describe a pragmatic approach to the problem and propose to replace the classical non-normative physicalism/naturalism with a normative physicalism/naturalism of Wittgensteinian language games. In subsection 3.1, I will give a definition of a normative naturalism. In subsection 3.2, I will make some suggestions concerning an analytic interpretation of the second philosophy of Wittgenstein. In the fourth section, I will propose a solution to the hard problem within Brandom‟s analytic pragmatism by using the notion of the pragmatically mediated semantic relation. In the fifth section, I will make some suggestions about possible combinatorics related to pragmatically mediated semantic relations. In the sixth section, I will consider pragmatic and discursive versions of the mind-body identity M=B. In the last section, I will conclude that the explanatory gap is a gap in a pragmatically mediated semantic relation between B and M. It is closed if we do not neglect pragmatics. 2 The Hard Problem The hard problem in the philosophy of mind can be formulated as follows.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking About False Belief: It’S Not Just What Children Say, but How Long It Takes Them to Say It
    Cognition 116 (2010) 297–301 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Brief article Thinking about false belief: It’s not just what children say, but how long it takes them to say it Cristina M. Atance a,*, Daniel M. Bernstein b,c, Andrew N. Meltzoff c a School of Psychology, University of Ottawa, 200 Lees Avenue, Room E228, Ottawa, Ontario, Canada K1N 6N5 b Kwantlen Polytechnic University, 12666, 72nd Avenue, Surrey, BC, Canada V3W 2MB c Institute for Learning and Brain Sciences, University of Washington, CHDD Building, Room 373, Box 357920, Seattle, WA 98195, USA article info abstract Article history: We examined 240 children’s (3.5-, 4.5-, and 5.5-year-olds) latency to respond to questions Received 29 January 2009 on a battery of false-belief tasks. Response latencies exhibited a significant cross-over Revised 22 March 2010 interaction as a function of age and response type (correct vs. incorrect). 3.5-year-olds’ Accepted 4 May 2010 incorrect latencies were faster than their correct latencies, whereas the opposite pattern emerged for 4.5- and 5.5-year-olds. Although these results are most consistent with con- ceptual change theories of false-belief reasoning, no extant theory fully accounts for our Keywords: data pattern. We argue that response latency data provide new information about under- Theory of mind lying cognitive processes in theory of mind reasoning, and can shed light on concept acqui- False-belief reasoning Conceptual development sition more broadly. Response latencies Ó 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to Our Second Lecture on Personhood and Identity
    PHI 110 Lecture 2 1 Welcome to our second lecture on personhood and identity. We’re going to begin today what will be two lectures on Rene Descartes’ thoughts on this subject. The position that is attributed to him is known as mind/body dualism. Sometimes it’s simply called the dualism for short. We need to be careful, however, because the word dualism covers a number of different philosophical positions, not always dualisms of mind and body. In other words, there are other forms of dualism that historically have been expressed. And so I will refer to his position as mind/body dualism or as Cartesian dualism as it’s sometimes also called. I said last time that Descartes is not going to talk primarily about persons. He’s going to talk about minds as opposed to bodies. But I think that as we start getting into his view, you will see where his notion of personhood arises. Clearly, Descartes is going to identify the person, the self, with the mind as opposed to with the body. This is something that I hoped you picked up in your reading and certainly that you will pick up once you read the material again after the lecture. Since I’ve already introduced Descartes’ position, let’s define it and then I’ll say a few things about Descartes himself to give you a little bit of a sense of the man and of his times. The position mind/body that’s known as mind/body dualism is defined as follows: It’s the view that the body is a physical substance — a machine, if you will — while the mind is a non-physical thinking entity which inhabits the body and is responsible for its voluntary movements.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind As Inverse Reinforcement Learning. Current
    Available online at www.sciencedirect.com ScienceDirect Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement learning 1,2 Julian Jara-Ettinger We review the idea that Theory of Mind—our ability to reason think or want based on how they behave. Research in about other people’s mental states—can be formalized as cognitive science suggests that we infer mental states by inverse reinforcement learning. Under this framework, thinking of other people as utility maximizers: constantly expectations about how mental states produce behavior are acting to maximize the rewards they obtain while mini- captured in a reinforcement learning (RL) model. Predicting mizing the costs that they incur [3–5]. Using this assump- other people’s actions is achieved by simulating a RL model tion, even children can infer other people’s preferences with the hypothesized beliefs and desires, while mental-state [6,7], knowledge [8,9], and moral standing [10–12]. inference is achieved by inverting this model. Although many advances in inverse reinforcement learning (IRL) did not have Theory of mind as inverse reinforcement human Theory of Mind in mind, here we focus on what they learning reveal when conceptualized as cognitive theories. We discuss Computationally, our intuitions about how other minds landmark successes of IRL, and key challenges in building work can be formalized using frameworks developed in a human-like Theory of Mind. classical area of AI: model-based reinforcement learning 1 Addresses (hereafter reinforcement learning or RL) . RL problems 1 Department of Psychology, Yale University, New Haven, CT, United focus on how to combine a world model with a reward States function to produce a sequence of actions, called a policy, 2 Department of Computer Science, Yale University, New Haven, CT, that maximizes agents’ rewards while minimizing their United States costs.
    [Show full text]
  • A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the Conscious Self and Its Treatment
    Article A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the Conscious Self and Its Treatment Fredric Schiffer Developmental Biopsychiatry Research Program, Department of Psychiatry, McLean Hospital, Harvard Medical School, Belmont, MA 02478, USA; [email protected]; Tel.: +1-617-969-1188 Abstract: In this paper I will address questions about will, agency, choice, consciousness, relevant brain regions, impacts of disorders, and their therapeutics, and I will do this by referring to my theory, Dual-brain Psychology, which posits that within most of us there exist two mental agencies with different experiences, wills, choices, and behaviors. Each of these agencies is associated as a trait with one brain hemisphere (either left or right) and its composite regions. One of these agencies is more adversely affected by past traumas, and is more immature and more symptomatic, while the other is more mature and healthier. The theory has extensive experimental support through 17 peer-reviewed publications with clinical and non-clinical research. I will discuss how this theory relates to the questions about the nature of agency and I will also discuss my published theory on the physical nature of subjective experience and its relation to the brain, and how that theory interacts with Dual-Brain Psychology, leading to further insights into our human nature and its betterment. Keywords: consciousness; subjective experience; self; psychopathology; treatment; transcranial near infrared light; biophotomodulation Citation: Schiffer, F. A Dual Mind Approach to Understanding the 1. Introduction Conscious Self and Its Treatment. Dual-brain Psychology comes out of my early clinical experiences in which I observed NeuroSci 2021, 2, 224–234.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development
    Top Lang Disorders Vol. 34, No. 4, pp. 313–328 Copyright c 2014 Wolters Kluwer Health | Lippincott Williams & Wilkins The Role of Language in Theory of Mind Development Jill G. de Villiers and Peter A. de Villiers Various arguments are reviewed about the claim that language development is critically connected to the development of theory of mind. The different theories of how language could help in this process of development are explored. A brief account is provided of the controversy over the capacities of infants to read others’ false beliefs. Then the empirical literature on the steps in theory of mind development is summarized, considering studies on both typically developing and various language-delayed children. Suggestions are made for intervention by speech language pathologists to enhance the child’s access to understanding the minds of others. Key words: conversation, false beliefs, false complements, language, narrative, theory of mind N THIS ARTICLE, we review arguments on interactions between language and ToM I and evidence for the claim that children’s in both typically developing and language- language acquisition is crucially connected to delayed children. We end with suggestions their development of a theory of mind (ToM). for using language interventions to facilitate Theory of mind refers to the child’s ability to children’s understanding of their own mental understand that other people have minds, and states as well as the minds of others. those minds contain beliefs, knowledge, de- sires, and emotions that may be different from THEORIES OF THE RELATIONSHIP those of the child. If the child can figure out BETWEEN LANGUAGE AND ToM those contents, then other people’s behavior will begin to make sense and, therefore, be Many writers have made a convincing case predictable and explainable.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory?
    Consciousness and Theory of Mind: a Common Theory? Keywords: Consciousness, Higher-Order Theories, Theory of Mind, Mind-reading, Metacognition. 1 Introduction Many of our mental states are phenomenally conscious. It feels a certain way, or to borrow Nagel's expression, there is something it is like to be in these states. Examples of phenomenally conscious states are those one undergoes while looking at the ocean or at a red apple, drinking a glass of scotch or a tomato juice, smelling coee or the perfume of a lover, listening to the radio or a symphonic concert, or feeling pain or hunger. A theory of consciousness has to explain the distinctive properties that phe- nomenally conscious states have and other kind of states lack. Higher-Order Representational (HOR) theories1 attempt to provide such an explanation. Ac- coding to these theories, phenomenally conscious states are those that are the objects of some kind of higher-order process or representation. There is some- thing higher-order, a meta-state, in the case of phenomenal conscious mental states, which is lacking in the case of other kind of states. According to these theories, consciousness depends on our Theory of Mind. A Theory of Mind, henceforth ToM, is the ability of humans to identify their own mental states and attribute mental states dierent from their owns to others. Such an ability can, at least conceptually, be decomposed into another two: mindreading and metacognition. Human beings are able to entertain representations of other people men- tal states thanks to the mindreading ability. We attribute beliefs, perceptions, feelings or desires to other people and predict and explain their behaviour ac- cordingly.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot
    Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot Brian Scassellati MIT Artificial Intelligence Lab 545 Technology Square – Room 938 Cambridge, MA 02139 USA [email protected] http://www.ai.mit.edu/people/scaz/ Abstract. If we are to build human-like robots that can interact naturally with people, our robots must know not only about the properties of objects but also the properties of animate agents in the world. One of the fundamental social skills for humans is the attribution of beliefs, goals, and desires to other people. This set of skills has often been called a “theory of mind.” This paper presents the theories of Leslie [27] and Baron-Cohen [2] on the development of theory of mind in human children and discusses the potential application of both of these theories to building robots with similar capabilities. Initial implementation details and basic skills (such as finding faces and eyes and distinguishing animate from inanimate stimuli) are introduced. I further speculate on the usefulness of a robotic implementation in evaluating and comparing these two models. 1 Introduction Human social dynamics rely upon the ability to correctly attribute beliefs, goals, and percepts to other people. This set of metarepresentational abilities, which have been collectively called a “theory of mind” or the ability to “mentalize”, allows us to understand the actions and expressions of others within an intentional or goal-directed framework (what Dennett [15] has called the intentional stance). The recognition that other individuals have knowl- edge, perceptions, and intentions that differ from our own is a critical step in a child’s development and is believed to be instrumental in self-recognition, in providing a perceptual grounding during language learning, and possibly in the development of imaginative and creative play [9].
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia
    Mind Perception Daniel R. Ames Malia F. Mason Columbia University To appear in The Sage Handbook of Social Cognition, S. Fiske and N. Macrae (Eds.) Please do not cite or circulate without permission Contact: Daniel Ames Columbia Business School 707 Uris Hall 3022 Broadway New York, NY 10027 [email protected] 2 What will they think of next? The contemporary colloquial meaning of this phrase often stems from wonder over some new technological marvel, but we use it here in a wholly literal sense as our starting point. For millions of years, members of our evolving species have gazed at one another and wondered: what are they thinking right now … and what will they think of next? The interest people take in each other’s minds is more than idle curiosity. Two of the defining features of our species are our behavioral flexibility—an enormously wide repertoire of actions with an exquisitely complicated and sometimes non-obvious connection to immediate contexts— and our tendency to live together. As a result, people spend a terrific amount of time in close company with conspecifics doing potentially surprising and bewildering things. Most of us resist giving up on human society and embracing the life of a hermit. Instead, most perceivers proceed quite happily to explain and predict others’ actions by invoking invisible qualities such as beliefs, desires, intentions, and feelings and ascribing them without conclusive proof to others. People cannot read one another’s minds. And yet somehow, many times each day, most people encounter other individuals and “go mental,” as it were, adopting what is sometimes called an intentional stance, treating the individuals around them as if they were guided by unseen and unseeable mental states (Dennett, 1987).
    [Show full text]
  • Machine Theory of Mind
    Machine Theory of Mind Neil C. Rabinowitz∗ Frank Perbet H. Francis Song DeepMind DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Chiyuan Zhang S. M. Ali Eslami Matthew Botvinick Google Brain DeepMind DeepMind [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract 1. Introduction Theory of mind (ToM; Premack & Woodruff, For all the excitement surrounding deep learning and deep 1978) broadly refers to humans’ ability to rep- reinforcement learning at present, there is a concern from resent the mental states of others, including their some quarters that our understanding of these systems is desires, beliefs, and intentions. We propose to lagging behind. Neural networks are regularly described train a machine to build such models too. We de- as opaque, uninterpretable black-boxes. Even if we have sign a Theory of Mind neural network – a ToM- a complete description of their weights, it’s hard to get a net – which uses meta-learning to build models handle on what patterns they’re exploiting, and where they of the agents it encounters, from observations might go wrong. As artificial agents enter the human world, of their behaviour alone. Through this process, the demand that we be able to understand them is growing it acquires a strong prior model for agents’ be- louder. haviour, as well as the ability to bootstrap to Let us stop and ask: what does it actually mean to “un- richer predictions about agents’ characteristics derstand” another agent? As humans, we face this chal- and mental states using only a small number of lenge every day, as we engage with other humans whose behavioural observations.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind by Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 From
    Theory of Mind By Margaret Alic Updated on Dec 23, 2009 from http://www.education.com/reference/article/theory-of-mind/ Theory of mind (ToM) is the intuitive understanding of one's own and other people's minds or mental states— including thoughts, beliefs, perceptions, knowledge, intentions, desires, and emotions—and of how those mental states influence behavior. Sometimes called intuitive psychology, folk psychology, or even mind-reading, ToM is an innate human ability. The understanding that others have mental states different from one's own makes it possible to infer what others are thinking and to predict their behavior. This ability to recognize one's own state of mind and those of others is central to human consciousness. The study of ToM and identification of the skills comprising ToM is a rapidly changing the field of developmental psychology. THE THEORY OF TOM The word theory in ToM refers to a person's tacit belief rather than to theory in the scientific sense. However, ToM is similar to a scientific theory in that it enables one to interpret and predict another's actions by evaluating their thoughts, beliefs, desires, or emotions. ToM also qualifies as a theory in the sense that the representations of reality generated by ToM are not directly observable. The ability to develop a ToM is a cognitive ability that develops by degrees from infancy through childhood and adolescence on into adulthood. It forms a basis for a child's acquisition of language and the development of appropriate social behavior and skills. ToM includes the ability to understand that the representations generated in one's mind do not necessarily reflect the real world and that other people may hold different representations.
    [Show full text]