<<

Is Equality Passe? Homo Recipro cans and the Future of

Egalitarian Politics



Samuel Bowles and Herb ert Gintis

Department of

University of Massachusetts

Amherst, Massachusetts, 01003

Octob er 19, 1998

A man ought to b e a friend to his friend and repay gift with gift.

People should meet smiles with smiles and lies with treachery.

From The Edda, a 13th century collection of Norse epic verse.



1 Is Equality Passe?

We think not. The welfare state is in trouble not b ecause sel shness is ram-

pant (it is not), but b ecause many egalitarian programs no longer evoke, and

sometimes now o end, deeply held notions of fairness, encompassing b oth

recipro city and generosity, but stopping far short of unconditional altruism

towards the less well o . Recasting egalitarianism to tap these sentiments

should b e high on the agenda of those who worry ab out the toll b eing

taken bypoverty, inequality, and insecurity in the United States and in the

world.

The United States public remains deeply committed to helping those in

need. In 1991 and ABC/WP p oll found that twice as many were \willing

to pay higher taxes" to \reduce poverty" as were opp osed. In 1995 61%

expressed willingness to pay more taxes to \provide job training and public

service jobs for p eople on welfare so that they can get o welfare." (Weaver,

Shapiro and Jacobs 1995). Almost three quarters of those surveyed by Time



To b e the basis of a symp osium in the Boston Review,Fall 1998. Our Recasting Egal-

itarianism: New Rules for Markets, States, and Communities (London: Verso, 1998) de-

velops these ideas in greater depth. Wewould like to thank Chris Bo ehm, Rob Boyd, Josh

Cohen, SteveFarkas, Ernst Fehr, Christina Fong, Nancy Folbre, Kristin Hawkes, Martin

Gilens, Rob ert Shapiro, Elisab eth Wo o d and Erik Wright for help, and the MacArthur

foundation for nancial supp ort. 1

Is EqualityPasse? 2

Magazine in 1991 agreed (more than half of them \completely") with the

statement: \The government should guarantee every citizen enough to eat

and a place to sleep."

Many however think that p olicies to pursue these ob jectives are either

ine ective or unfair. In a 1995 CBS/NYT survey, for example, 89% sup-

p orted a mandated work requirement for those on welfare. It is thus not

surprising that egalitarian programs have b een cut even as increases in mea-

sured inequality of b efore tax and transfer income have taken place. For the

most part voters have resp onded with approval rather than resistance.

Egalitarians now defend their programs on moral and empirical grounds

that many,even among the less well o , nd uncomp elling. In the face of a

hostile public, many egalitarians have b ecome soured on what they consider

to b e a sel sh electorate that identi es with materialistic middle-class values

and is indi erent to the plight of the less fortunate.

We b elieve this p essimism is fundamentally misdirected. It misunder-

stands not only the reasons for opp osition to egalitarian programs, but the

powerful sentiments supp orting them. It is not self interest that opp oses the

welfare state, nor is it unconditional generosity that supp orts it. We will

show that there is a solid foundation for co op eration and sharing in two basic

human motives which we term strong reciprocity and basic needs generos-

ity, that hostility to contemp orary forms of egalitarianism is not evidence

against that deep foundation, but evidence for it, and that new egalitarian

initiatives are fully compatible with that foundation.

Understanding the predicament of egalitarian p olitics to daythus requires

a reconsideration of , the unremittingly sel sh prototyp e

whose aso cial prop ensities have provided the starting p oint for delib erations

on constitutions and p olicies from Thomas Hobb es to the current debate on

welfare reform. We do not wish to replace the textb o ok Homo, however,

with a cardb oard-cutout altruist, an equally one-dimensional actor uncon-

ditionally willing to make p ersonally costly contributions to others. While

these motives are much admired by many advo cates of the welfare state,

we doubt that unconditional altruism explains its success, nor do es its ab-

sence explain our current malaise. In exp eriments and surveys p eople are

not stingy, but their generosity is conditional. Moreover, they distinguish

among the go o ds and services to b e distributed, favoring those which meet

basic needs, and among the recipients themselves, favoring those thought

to be \deserving." Strong recipro city, along with basic needs generosity,

not unconditional altruism, b etter explains the that undergird

egalitarian p olitics. By strong recipro citywe mean a prop ensity to cooper-

ate and share with others similarly disp osed, even at p ersonal cost, and a Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 3

willingness to punish those who violate co op erative and other so cial norms,

even when punishing is p ersonally costly. We call a p erson acting this way

Homo reciprocans. cares ab out the well-b eing of others

and ab out the pro cesses determining outcomes|whether they are fair, for

example, or violate a so cial norm. He di ers in this from the self-regarding

and outcome oriented Homo economicus. We see Homo reciprocans at work

in Chicago's neighb orho o ds, in a recent study (Sampson, Raudenbush and

Earls 1997) that do cumented a widespread willingness to intervene with co-

residents to discourage truancy, public disorders and antiso cial b ehaviors,

as well as the dramatic impact of this \collective ecacy" on community

safety and amenities.

Homo reciprocans is not committed to the abstract goal of equal out-

comes, but rather to a rough balancing out of burdens and rewards. In earlier

times|when, for example, an individual's conventional claim on material

resources was conditioned by noble birth or divine origin|what counted

as \balancing out" might entail highly unequal comfort and wealth. But,

as we will see, in the absence of sp eci c counter-claims, mo dern forms of

recipro city often take equal division as a reference p oint.

We do not wish to banish Homo economicus,however. The evidence we

intro duce shows that a substantial fraction of individuals consistently follow

self-regarding precepts. Moreover most individuals app ear to draw up on a

rep ertoire of contrasting b ehaviors: whether one acts sel shly or generously

dep ends as much on the situation as the p erson. The fact that Homo eco-

nomicus is alive and well (if often in the minority) is good news, not bad,

as p eople often rely on aso cial individualism to undermine so cially harm-

ful forms of ranging from price- xing to ethnic violence. Pure

altruists also doubtless exist and make imp ortant contributions to so cial

life. In short, egalitarian p olicy-making, no less than the grand pro jects of

constitutional design, risk irrelevance if they ignore the irreducible hetero-

geneity of human motivations. The problem of institutional design is not,

as the classical economists thought, that sel sh individuals be induced to

interact in ways pro ducing desirable aggregate outcomes, but rather that a

mix of motives|sel sh, recipro cal, altruistic and spiteful|interact in ways

that prevent the sel sh from exploiting the generous and hence unraveling

co op eration when it is b ene cial.

The strong recipro city of Homo reciprocans go es considerably beyond

those co op erative b ehaviors that can b e fully accounted for in terms of the

self-regarding, outcome oriented motives that are the de ning characteris-

tics of Homo economicus. We call these self-interested forms of co op era-

tion `weak recipro city.' Examples include exchange and co op eration Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 4

enforced by tit-for-tat b ehavior|what biologists call `recipro cal altruism.'

Such actions are costly to the giver but in fact are self-interested b ecause

they involve future repayment. Strong recipro city, like the biologists' con-

cept of altruism, imp oses costs on Homo reciprocans without prosp ect of

repayment. Yet unlike the vernacular usage of altruism, it is neither uncon-

ditional nor necessarily motivated by go o d will towards the recipient.

Students of cultural and biological evolution have long wondered how

individually costly but so cially b ene cial traits, such as altruism, might

evolve in comp etition with genetically and economically rewarded sel sh

traits. Like altruism toward strangers, strong recipro citythus represents an

evolutionary puzzle, one that we will seek to unravel. But rst we will show

that Homo reciprocans is indeed among the dramatis personae in to day's

p olitical arena, and most likely has b een for the last hundred thousand years.

2 The Legacy of a Hundred Thousand Years of Sharing

Other than unconditional altruism, there are two distinct reasons why p eo-

ple might supp ort egalitarian p olicies. First, many egalitarian programs are

forms of so cial insurance that will b e supp orted even by those who b elieve

they will probably pay in more than their exp ected claims over a lifetime.

Included among these are unemployment and health insurance, and more

broadly, the various so cial programs that soften the blows during the ro cky

p erio ds that p eople exp erience in the course of their lives. Even the se-

curely rich supp ort amelioration of the conditions of the p o or on prudential

grounds. The insurance motive is consistent with conventional notions of

self-interest, considering that p eople are broadly prudent and risk-averse.

The second reason for supp ort of egalitarian programs, by contrast, is

not fundamentally self-regarding: egalitarianism is often based on a com-

1

mitment to what we have termed strong reciprocity.' It will come as no

surprise that p eople are considerably more generous than the mo del in eco-

nomics textb o oks allows. More remarkable, however, is that they are equally

unsel sh in seeking to punish, often at great cost to themselves, those who

have done harm to them and others. Programs designed to tap these other-

regarding motives may succeed where others that o end underlying motiva-

tional structures have b een abandoned.

Both historical and contemp orary exp erimental evidence supp ort this

p osition. Consider rst the historical evidence In his Injustice: the So-

1

Ernst Fehr, whose exp erimental work is describ ed b elow, call this `recipro cal fairness.'

See Fehr and Gachter (1998b). Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 5

cial Bases of Obedience and Revolt, Barrington Mo ore, Jr. (1978)

sought to discern if there might be common motivational bases|\general

conceptions of unfair and unjust b ehavior" (21)|for the moral outrage fu-

eling struggles for justice that have recurred throughout human history.

\There are grounds," he concludes from his wide-ranging investigation,

for susp ecting that the welter of moral co des may conceal a cer-

tain unity of original form...a general ground plan, a conception

of what so cial relationships oughttobe. It is a conception that

by no means excludes hierarchy and authority, where exceptional

qualities and defects can b e the source of enormous admiration

and awe. At the same time, it is one where services and favors,

trust and a ection, in the course of mutual exchanges, are ideally

exp ected to nd some rough balancing out. (4-5,509)

Mo ore termed the general ground plan he uncovered \the concept of reci-

pro city|or b etter, mutual obligation, a term that do es not imply equalityof

burdens or obligations..." (506) In like manner James Scott (1976) analyzed

agrarian revolts, identifying violations of the \norm of recipro city" as one

the essential triggers of insurrectionary motivations. We do not think that

Scott's or Mo ore's assessments are idiosyncratic.

One is tempted to consider strong recipro city a late arrival in so cial

evolution, p ossibly one whose provenance is to be found in Enlightenment

individualism, or later in the era of lib eral demo cratic or so cialist so cieties|

a set of b eliefs whose repro duction is secured by the delib erate inculcation

of mo dern concepts of distributive justice through scho oling and other in-

tentional means. However, this account do es not square with overwhelming

evidence of the distant etiology of strong recipro city.

Christopher Bo ehm, a primatologist at USC, concluded on the basis of

an encyclop edic survey that (1993):226

. . . with the advent of anatomically mo dern who contin-

ued to live in small groups and had not yet domesticated plants

and animals, it is very likely that all human so cieties practiced

egalitarian b ehavior and that most of the time they did so very

successfully. One main conclusion, then, is that intentional lev-

eling linked to an egalitarian ethos is an immediate and probably

an extremely widespread cause of human so cieties' failing to de-

velop authoritative or co ercive leadership.

Anthrop ologist Bruce Knauft of Emory University (1991):393,395 adds: Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 6

In all ethnographically known simple so cieties, co op erative shar-

ing of provisions is extended to mates, o spring, and many oth-

ers within the band. .. .Archeological evidence suggests that

widespread networks facilitating di use access to and transfer of

resources and information have b een pronounced at least since

the Upp er Paleolithic. . . The strong internalization of a sharing

ethic is in many resp ects the sine qua non of culture in these

so cieties.

Far from a mere moment in the history of anatomically mo dern humans,

the p erio d describ ed by Knauft and Bo ehm spans something like 100,000

years b efore the present to the advent and spread of agriculture 12,000 years

ago, or p erhaps ninety p ercent of the time wehave existed on the planet.

One group of contemp orary foragers, the Ache of Eastern Paraguay,have

b een particularly closely studied, and the amounts and nutritional values of

food acquired and consumed by memb ers of the group measured (Kaplan,

2

Hill, Hawkes and Hurtado 1984). Sharing is so widespread, the researchers

found, that on average three quarters of what anyone eats was acquired by

someone outside the consumer's nuclear family, and even more remarkable,

in the case of meat and honey, the main go o ds foraged by men:

women, children and adult siblings of the accquirer receive no

more. . . from their husbands, fathers and brothers resp ectively

than would b e exp ected bychance, and men eat from their own

kills a go o d deal less than would b e exp ected bychance.

The Ache are probably unusually egalitarian, and there is evidence that

hunting prowess is rewarded, if not with more food, then with enhanced

so cial esteem and increased mating success. Nevertheless it is typical in

foraging so cieties that families with less successful hunters, and indeed those

unable to hunt, are nonetheless adequately provisioned by the group.

The resulting egalitarian distribution of resources is not the unintended

bypro duct of an ecological or other constraint; rather it is delib erately

sought. Using data from forty-eight simple so cieties, Bo ehm (1993):239

concluded that

2

Our assessment of the generality of fo o d sharing in foraging bands is based on our read-

ing of Wo o dburn (1982), Bo ehm (1982), Bo ehm (1993), Blurton-Jones (1987), Cashdan

(1980), Knauft (1991), Hawkes (1992), Hawkes (1993), Kaplan and Hill (1985b), Kaplan

and Hill (1985a), Kaplan et al. (1984), Lee (1979), Wo o dburn and Barnard (1988), Endi-

cott (1988), Balikci (1970), Kent (1989), Damas (1972), Wenzel (1995), Knauft (1989). Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 7

. . . these so cieties may be considered to be intentional commu-

nities, groups of p eople that make up their minds ab out the

amount of hierarchy they wish to live with and then see to it

that the program is followed. (239)

He found evidence that the following constrained p otentially arrogant mem-

b ers of the group: public opinion, criticism and ridicule, disob edience, os-

tracism and assassination.

It seems likely then, that most of human history has b een characterized

by what James Wo o dburn (1982):431 calls \p olitically assertive egalitari-

anism." The mo dern welfare state is thus but an example of a ubiquitous

so cial form. Sharing , from families to extended gift giving, to

barn raisings and tithing, to egalitarian division rules for the catch of the

hunt, have cropp ed up in human history with such regularity and under

such diverse circumstances that one is tempted to place them among Talcott

Parsons' (1964) evolutionary universals : so cial institutions that confer such

extensive b ene ts up on their users that they regularly reapp ear in course of

history in otherwise diverse so cieties.

Karl Polanyi's (1944) account of the reaction to the human costs of

Nineteenth Century laissez-faire capitalism and the eventual emergence of

mo dern protections of the weak from the vicissitudes of the market, as well

as the sharing of the national pro duct, records just one of thousands of cases

of the indep endent emergence of institutions of this typ e. The evolutionary

viability of sharing institutions and of the motivations that supp ort them

counsels against those who have written o egalitarianism as an idea whose

3

time has come and gone.

Our suggestion that these distantly originating b ehaviors may be im-

p ortant in uences on contemp orary b ehavior is not an ethical endorsement

of them or the so cieties from which they originated|indeed some of the

baser human motives, such as the desire for revenge, are examples of strong

recipro city. Rather it is a hyp othesis that if true has signi cant b earing on

present day egalitarianism, b ecause it can help us understand the pattern

of public approval and disapproval of welfare state initiatives. Is it true?

3

On the structural basis of pro-so cial norms in a game-theoretic framework, see Bowles

and Gintis (1998b). On the relationship of market institutions to the development of

culture, see Bowles (1998). On the evolution of strong recipro city, see Bowles and Gintis

(1998a). This and other of our unpublished pap er can b e easily downloaded from the web

site www-unix.oit.umass.edu/~gintis. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 8

3 Homo Reciprocans

An impressive body of exp erimental evidence, much of it deployed in the

rst instance to validate the mo del of the sel sh purveyor of market ratio-

nality, Homo economicus, in fact has served to undermine this mo del. In its

place this body of evidence suggests a new persona. A convenient starting

p oint in tracing the birth of Homo reciprocans is a tournament involving

di ering strategies of the play in the prisoner's dilemma game undertaken

4

two decades ago by Rob ert Axelro d at the University of Michigan. The

prisoner's dilemma requires each of two players to cho ose simultaneously

one of two actions, `co op erate' or `defect.' The payo s are such that b oth

players do b etter by co op erating than by defecting, but whatever one player

do es, the other player do es b etter by defecting (for example, the payo to

mutual co op eration is 10 for each, the payo to mutual defecting is 5 for

each, but the payo to defecting when the other player co op erates is 15 for

the defector and 0 for the co op erator). The iterated prisoner's dilemma is

simply rep eated play of the well known game with \winners" b eing those

with high cumulative scores over however many rounds are played.

Axelro d asked a number of game theorists, economists, p olitical scien-

tists, so ciologists, and psychologists to submit computer programs giving

complete strategies for playing the game. successive rounds of which were

rep eated with the same partner. Each program was pitted against every

other program, as well as itself and a program that randomly chose to co-

op erate and defect. Surprisingly, the winner among the fourteen strategies

submitted was the simplest, called `tit-for-tat' (submitted by game theorist

Anatol Rapp op ort). Tit-for-tat co op erates on the rst round, and then do es

whatever its partner did on the previous round.

Following up on this result, Axelro d held a second tournament in which

a larger number of participants, including the original contributors, were

told of the success of tit-for-tat and asked to submit another program for

playing the iterated prisoner's dilemma. Knowing that tit-for-tat was the

to b eat did not help the players: once again Rapp op ort submitted

tit-for-tat, and once again, it won.

Sp eculating on the strong showing of tit-for-tat, Axelro d noted that this

strategy for co op eration has three attributes that are essential for successful

co op eration. The rst is that tit-for-tat is nice : it b egins by co op erating, and

it is never the rst to defect. Second, tit-for-tat is punishing : it retaliates

4

See Axelro d and Hamilton (1981) and Axelro d (1984) for details and theoretical

development. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 9

relentlessly against defection. Finally, tit-for-tat is forgiving : as so on as a

defecting partner returns to co op erating, tit-for-tat returns to co op erating.

Homo economicus would readily embrace tit-for-tat, of course, at least if

there were enough other tit-for-tatters around and there were a reasonable

chance that one would interact rep eatedly with the same p erson. Under

these conditions tit-for-tat will b e the self-interested strategy to follow, and

thus is an example of recipro cal altruism rather than strong recipro city. But

for reasons that will b ecome clear immediately,we think that the ubiquity

of tit-for-tat sentiments among p eople (rather than computer programs) is

more aptly explained by strong recipro city motives that violate the tenets

of economic man.

There have b een many exp eriments with human sub jects involving the

iterated prisoner's dilemma. If Axelro d's tournaments showed that nice

guys nish rst, the exp eriments reveal that there are lots of nice guys, even

among the economics ma jors who show up for exp erimental games.

1. The simplest, but still quite revealing, lab oratory exp eriment is the `dic-

tator game,' in which one of two players, the ` prop oser,' is given a sum

of money (typically $10), is asked to cho ose any part of the sum to give

to the second player (the two players are mutually anonymous), and is

p ermitted to keep the rest. Homo economicus gives nothing in this situ-

ation, whereas in actual exp erimental situations, a ma jority of prop osers

give p ositive amounts, typically ranging from 20% to 60% of the total

5

(Forsythe, Horowitz, Savin and Sefton 1994).

2. The commonly observed rejection of substantial p ositive o ers in what

are called ultimatum games is our second piece of exp erimental evi-

dence. Exp erimental proto cols di er, but the general structure of the

is simple. Sub jects are paired, one is the resp onder, the

other the prop oser. The prop oser is provisionally awarded an amount

(`the pie'|typically $10) to be divided between prop oser and resp on-

der. The prop oser o ers a certain p ortion of the pie to the resp onder. If

the resp onder accepts, the resp onder gets the prop osed p ortion, and the

prop oser keeps the rest. If the resp onder rejects the o er b oth get noth-

5

As in other exp erimental situations, a signi cant minority(between 25% and 42% in

the Forsythe et al. exp eriments) b ehave self-interestedly and give nothing. Moreover, in a

double-anonymous study (Ho man, McCab e, Shachat and Smith 1994), where not even

the exp erimenter knows the b ehavior of the prop oser, the fraction of prop osers who gave

nothing increased to two-thirds. This accords with our notion that strong recipro cityisa

conditional b ehavior, in this case weakening in the face of high levels of so cial anonymity. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 10

6

ing. In exp eriments conducted in the United States, Slovakia, Japan,

Israel, Slovenia, Germany, Russia, and Indonesia the vast ma jority of

prop osers o er between 40% and 50% of the pie, and o ers lower than

30% of the pie are often rejected (Fehr and Schmidt 1997). These re-

sults have o ccurred in exp eriments with stakes as high as three months'

7

earnings.

When asked why they o er more than one cent, prop osers commonly

say that they are afraid that resp ondents will consider low o ers unfair

and reject them as a way to punish prop oser's unwillingness to share.

When resp ondents reject o ers, they give virtually the same reasons for

their actions. The prop osers' actions might b e explained by sel shness

but the resp ondents' cannot. Because these b ehaviors o ccur in single-

shot interactions and on the last round of multi-round interactions, they

cannot be accounted for by the resp onder's attempt to mo dify subse-

quent b ehavior of the prop oser. Punishment per se is the most likely

motive. As evidence for this interpretation, we note that the rejection of

p ositive o ers is substantially less when the game is altered so that rejec-

tion do es not punish the prop oser (Abbink, Bolton, Sadrieh and Tang

1996). Moreover the fact that o ers generated by a computer rather

than another p erson are signi cantly less likely to b e rejected suggests

that those rejecting low o ers at a cost to themselves are reacting to vi-

olations of fairness norms rather than simply rejecting disadvantageous

o ers (Blount 1995). See also Bolton and Zwick (1995) and Suleiman

(1996). Thus the ultimatum game exp eriments provide evidence for our

view that strong recipro city is a common .

3. More directly analogous to strong recipro city in groups however, are

ndings in what are called n-player public goods exp eriments. The

following is a common variant. Ten players are given $1 in each of ten

rounds. On each round, each player can contribute any p ortion of the

$1 (anonymously) to a `common p o ol.' The exp erimenter divides the

amount in the common pool by two, and gives each player that much

money. If all ten players are co op erative, on each round each puts $1

in the p o ol, the exp erimenter divides the $10 in the pool by two, and

gives each player $5. After ten rounds of this, each sub ject has $50. By

b eing sel sh, however, each player can do b etter as long as the others are

6

See Guth,  Schmittb erger and Schwarz (1982), Forsythe et al. (1994), Camerer and

Thaler (1995) and Roth (1995).

7

See Cameron (1995) on exp eriments in Indonesia and Fehr and Tougareva (1995) on

exp eriments in Russia. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 11

co op erating. By keeping the $1, the player ends up with \his" $10, plus

receives $45 as his share of the p o ol, for a total of $55. If all b ehave this

way,however, each receives only $10. Thus this is an `iterated prisoner's

dilemma' in which self-regarding players contribute nothing.

In fact, however, only a small fraction of players contribute nothing to

the common p o ol. Rather, in the early stages of the game, p eople gen-

erally contribute half their money to the p o ol. In the later stages of the

game, contributions decay until at the end, they are contributing very

little. Prop onents of the Homo economicus mo del initially suggested

that the reason for decay of public contribution is that participants re-

ally do not understand the game at rst, and as they b egin to learn it,

they b egin to realize the sup eriority of the free-riding strategy. However,

there is considerable evidence that this interpretation is incorrect. For

instance, Andreoni (1988) nds that when the whole pro cess is rep eated

with the same sub jects, the initial levels of co op eration are restored, but

once again co op eration decays as the game progresses.

James Andreoni (1995), an economist at the University of Wisconsin,

suggests a Homo reciprocans explanation for the decay of co op eration: pub-

lic-spirited contributors want to retaliate against free-riders and the only

way available to them in the game is by not contributing themselves. In-

deed, if players are p ermitted to retaliate directly against non-contributors,

but at a cost to themselves, as in the exp eriments of Ernst Fehr and Si-

mon Gachter, economists at the UniversityofZurich, they do so (Fehr and

Gachter 1998a). In this situation, contributions rise in subsequent rounds to

near the maximal level. Moreover punishment levels are undiminished in the

nal rounds, suggesting that disciplining norm violators is an end in itself

and hence will b e exhibited even when there is no prosp ect of mo difying the

subsequent b ehavior of the shirker or p otential future shirkers.

Such exp eriments show that agents are willing to incur a cost to punish

those whom they p erceive to have treated them, or a group to which they

8

b elong badly. Also in everyday life, we see p eople consumed with the desire

for revenge against those who have harmed them or their families, even where

no material gain can b e exp ected (Nisb ett and Cohen 1996, Bo ehm 1984).

Moreover strong recipro city co exists with simple generosity and compas-

sion in many, p erhaps most p eople. Evidence for this comes not only from

8

See Ostrom, Walker and Gardner (1992) on common p o ol resources, Fehr, Gachter

and Kirchsteiger (1997) on eciency wages, and Fehr and Gachter (1998a) on public

go o ds. Coleman (1988) develops the parallel p oint that free riding in so cial networks can

be avoided if network memb ers provide p ositive rewards for co op erating. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 12

dictator games, as we have seen, but also from an ingenious set of exp er-

iments devised by p olitical scientists Jo e Opp enheimer and Norm Frohlich

(1992). Twenty-eight groups of sub jects engaged in individual work tasks

and decided on a principle of redistribution within the group of the rewards

asso ciated with successful p erformance of the tasks. At the conclusion of

the exp eriment, the exp erimenters distributed cash rewards to the sub jects

according to their pro ductivity and the rules of redistribution selected by the

group, so the stakes were real. As the sub jects decided on the redistribution

rule b efore knowing how well they would p erform on the task, the exp eri-

ment would seem to elicit the sub jects' abstract notions of just reward, a

kind of exp erimental instance of the Rawlsian veil of ignorance.

By far the most p opular principle of distribution was a minimal o or

to b e granted to every memb er of the group irresp ective of the individual's

pro ductivity in the task. Sub jects elected to nance the o or by a tax on

the individual earnings of the more pro ductive memb ers. High levels of

supp ort for the o or principle were expressed by the high pro ductivity (and

hence highly taxed) memb ers, and their level of satisfaction with the o or

principle increased with rep eated play. Of course the rules selected by the

group re ect recipro cityaswell as generosity, as the principle of individual

reward prop ortional to pro ductivitywas only mo di ed, not annulled by the

tax. When these rules were imp osed on the groups by the exp erimenters

rather than chosen by the groups, the o or principle remained p opular, but

less so.

These results show clearly that p eople are not generally the self-inter-

ested actors of traditional economics, since they value treating others fairly,

and will incur p ersonal costs to do so. Nor are p eople the unconditional

altruists of utopian thought, since they want to hurt free-riders and other

norm-violators. These exp eriments also show that strong recipro cityisnot

simply a mechanism for norm-enforcement, but also often includes a pow-

erful concept of fairness or sharing |the notion that all else equal, there

should b e a rough balance of rights and obligations in so cial exchange. Pro-

p osers in the treat sharing as a go o d in itself, and resp ondents

in the ultimatum game retaliate not against the violation of norms in the

abstract, but against norms of equal sharing in particular.

A remarkable asp ect of these exp eriments|and one very germane to

our concern with egalitarian p olicy|is the degree to which b ehaviors are

a ected by the exp erimentally contrived so cial relationship between play-

ers. Communication among participants prior to the game, or exp erimental

conditions that reduce the sub jective `so cial distance' among participants, Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 13

9

lead to higher and more sustained levels of generosity and co op eration.

For example, fraternity brothers at UCLA were asked to rank outcomes

in a prisoner's dilemma situation given that they were interacting with a

fellow fraternity brother, a memb er of another (unnamed) fraternity, a non-

fraternity student at UCLA, a student from USC and an ocer from the

UCLA Police Department. They showed a strong for mutual co-

op eration over defection against one's partner when playing with fraternity

brothers, with the rankings reversing with increasing so cial distance|they

were as willing to exploit the USC students as the UCLA p olice! (Kollo ck

1997).

People care ab out who they give to: Eckel and Grossman (1997) found

that prop osers in a dictator game gave more when the recipient was \the

Red Cross" rather than another exp erimental sub ject. Finally, when the

right to be prop oser in the ultimatum game is earned by b eing a winner

in a trivia quiz rather than by lot, prop osers o ered less, and resp ondents

accepted lower o ers (Ho man et al. 1994). It app ears that minor manipula-

tions of the so cial context of interactions may supp ort signi cant b ehavioral

di erences.

In all of the exp eriments a signi cant fraction of sub jects (ab out a quar-

ter, typically) conform to the self-interested preferences of Homo economi-

cus, and it is often the self-serving b ehavior of this minority that, when it

go es unpunished, unravels initial generosity and co op eration.

These exp eriments also indicate that strong recipro city spans all the

10

so cieties studied, though in somewhat varying strength and content.

The following ve generalizations sum up the relevance of these exp er-

iments to the problem of designing and sustaining programs to promote

economic security and eliminate poverty. First, p eople exhibit signi cant

levels of generosity, even towards strangers. Second, p eople share more of

what they acquire by chance rather than by p ersonal e ort. Third, p eople

contribute to public go o ds and co op erate to collective endeavors, and con-

sider it unfair to free-ride on the contributions and e orts of others. Fourth,

9

For the communication result, see Isaac and Walker (1988), and for the so cial distance

result, see Kollo ck (1997) and Ho man, McCab e and Smith (1996).

10

The only known exception to this statement concerns exp eriments run by the UCLA

anthrop ologist Jo e Henrich, a memb er of our research group who works with the Machi-

guenga Indians, a famously individualistic indigenous group living in a remote region of

the Peruvian Amazon. In the ultimatum game, he found o ers to be small, and even

small o ers were typically accepted. In the public go o ds game, contributions to the public

accountwere very low. We b elieve the most likely explanation of this result is a p eculiarity

of the sub jects: their basic so cial unit consists of closely-related kin, with extra-kin so cial

relationships b eing muchweaker than typical even of simple so cieties. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 14

p eople punish free riders at substantial costs to themselves, even when they

cannot reasonably exp ect future p ersonal gain therefrom.

It would not b e dicult to design a system of income security and eco-

nomic opp ortunity that would tap rather than o end the motivations ex-

pressed in these rst four generalizations. Such a system would b e generous

towards the p o or, rewarding those who p erform so cially valued work and

who seek to improve their chances of engaging in such work, as well as to

those who are poor through accidents not of their own making, such as

illness and job displacement.

The fth, however, is more troublesome: each of these asp ects of reci-

pro city is more salient, the less is the p erceived so cial distance among the

participants. This last generalization may help explain why inequalities are

so readily sustained even among apparently generous publics. Economic

inequality|particularly when overlaid with racial, ethnic, language, and

other di erences|increases the so cial distance that then undermines the

motivational basis for reaching out to those in need. Indeed, surveys consis-

tently reveal that the supp ort for those in need is stronger in so cieties whose

b efore tax and transfer incomes are more equal.

The exp erimental evidence, casual observation of everyday life, ethno-

graphic and paleoanthrop ological accounts of hunter-gatherer foraging bands

from the late paleolithic to the present and historical narratives of collective

struggles have combined to convince us that strong recipro city is a power-

ful and ubiquitous motive. But we hesitate to revise Homo economicus by

elevating the individually costly sharing and punishmentof norm violators

characteristic of Homo reciprocans to a privileged place in the rep ertoire of

human b ehaviors until wehave addressed the evolutionary puzzle p osed at

the outset. In short we are more prone to b elieve and to generalize from the

exp erimental and historical evidence we have intro duced if we can explain

how strong recipro city motives might have evolved despite the costs these

motives seemingly imp ose on those b earing them.

We have elab orated our attempt to resolve this puzzle in a recent tech-

nical pap er and we are continuing to explore the issue with a research team

of exp erimentalists, ethnographers, and others (Bowles and Gintis 1998a).

Our reasoning is that strong recipro city supp orts the adherence to norms

within groups and some of these norms|requiring work towards common

ends, sharing, and monogamy for example|are b ene cial to most group

memb ers. Where recipro city motives embrace the individually costly en-

forcement of these group-b ene cial norms, strong recipro city may evolve

b ecause Homo reciprocans will b e disprop ortionately likely to b e in groups

that have e ective norm adherence, and hence to enjoy the group b ene ts Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 15

of these norms. By contrast, where recipro city motivates the individually

costly enforcement of norms that on average confer little b ene t on group

memb ers, or in ict group costs, of course recipro city is unlikely to evolve.

Strong recipro city thus allows groups to engage in common practices

without the resort to costly and often ine ective hierarchical authority, and

therebyvastly increases the rep ertoire of so cial exp eriments capable of dif-

fusing through cultural and genetic comp etition. The relevant traits maybe

transmitted genetically and proliferate under the in uence of natural selec-

tion, or they may b e transmitted culturally through learning from elders and

age mates and proliferate b ecause successful groups tend to absorb failing

groups, or to b e emulated by them. We think it likely that b oth genetic and

cultural transmission is involved. The 100,000 years in which anatomically

mo dern humans lived primarily in foraging bands constitutes a suciently

long time p erio d, and a favorable so cial and physical ecology, for the evo-

lution of the combination of norm enforcement and sharing that we term

strong recipro city.

4 Strong Reciprocity and the Revolt Against Welfare

This mo del of Homo reciprocans supp orts our optimism concerning the p o-

litical viability of egalitarian p olicies. Like Petr Krop otkin (1989[1903])

almost a century ago, we nd comp elling evidence|b oth evolutionary and

contemp orary|for the force of human b ehavioral predisp ositions to act b oth

generously and recipro cally rather than self-interestedly in many so cial sit-

uations. While most egalitarians have failed to appreciate the practical

imp ortance of these predisp ositions in p olicy matters, their salience was

not missed by the conservative economist and philosopher FrederickHayek

(1978):18,20

... wanting to do good to known p eople will not achieve the

most for the community, but only the observation of its abstract

and seemingly purp oseless rules.. . . the long submerged innate

instincts have again surged to the top. [The] demand for a just

distribution. . . is thus strictly an atavism, based on primordial

emotions. And it is these widely prevalent feelings to which

prophets, (and) moral philosophers. . . app eal by their plans for

the delib erate creation of a new typ e of so ciety.

But while strong recipro city may supp ort egalitarianism, it may also

help explain the rising tide of opp osition to welfare state p olicies in the ad-

vanced market economies in the past decades. Sp eci cally, in light of the Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 16

exp erimental regularities outlined ab ove, we susp ect the following to b e true

as well: egalitarian p olicies that reward p eople indep endent of whether and

howmuch they contribute to so ciety are considered unfair and are not sup-

p orted, even if the intended recipients are otherwise worthy of supp ort, and

even if the incidence of non-contribution in the target p opulation is rather

low. This would explain the opp osition to many welfare measures for the

p o or, particularly since such measures are thoughttohave promoted various

so cial pathologies. At the same time it explains the continuing supp ort for

so cial security and medicare in the United States, since the public p ercep-

tion is that the recipients are `deserving' and the p olicies do not supp ort

what are considered anti-so cial b ehaviors. The public goods exp eriments

are also consistent with the notion that tax resistance by the nonwealthy

may stem from their p erception that the well-to-do are not paying their fair

share.

These inferences from the exp erimental evidence nd some con rmation

in survey and fo cus group data. Opp osition to egalitarian p olicies do es not

primarily re ect the sel sh interests of the economically secure. Indeed, in-

come and so cial background are very p o or predictors of the degree of one's

supp ort for either particular programs or egalitarianism in general. Of far

greater imp ort is one's views of why the p o or are p o or, and sp eci cally one's

b eliefs ab out the relative imp ortance of e ort rather than luck or other cir-

cumstances beyond the control of the individual in explaining individual

11

incomes. Christina Fong of Washington University compared individuals'

resp onses on nationally representative surveys to questions indicating sup-

p ort for increases or decreases in exp enditure on welfare with resp onses to

questions ab out why the poor are poor (\lack of e ort by the poor them-

selves"). In a 1990 sample of the General So cial Survey she found that only

18% of those citing \lack of e ort" thought to o little was sp entonwelfare,

while 49% resp onded \to o much." By contrast among those who thought

that \lack of e ort by the p o or themselves" was \not imp ortant" in explain-

ing poverty 44% thought that we were sp ending to o little on welfare, and

only 28%, to o much. Remarkably, Fong found that the b elief that e ort

is imp ortantto \getting ahead in life" has a considerably larger impact on

opp osition to aid to the poor than one's income, years of scho oling, and

parents' so cio economic status combined |those whose e ort b eliefs di ered

from the average by a standard deviation were more opp osed to aid than

11

Thomas Piketty (1995) also explores the imp ortance of one's b eliefs ab out the imp or-

tance of e ort but in his mo del those who b elieve e ort leads to success opp ose redistribu-

tion not b ecause the p o or are undeserving but b ecause the necessary taxes will discourage

e ort, thus raising the cost of aid. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 17

those whose level of privilege on all three measures was a standard deviation

ab ove the mean!

Fong's research con rms earlier studies. In a 1972 sample of white women

in Boston the p erceived work ethic of the p o or was a far b etter predictor of

supp ort for aid to the p o or than one's family income, religion, education, and

a host of other demographic and so cial background variables (Williamson

1974). Indeed in predicting supp ort for such aid, the addition of a single

variable measuring b eliefs ab out work motivation tripled the explanatory

power made p ossible using all of the background variables.

Consistent with our interpretation of these data, supp ort for anti-p overty

exp enditures varies with economic conditions. Fong found, for example that

statistically controlling for race, scho oling, income, religion and other vari-

ables, the self-employed tend to opp ose such p olicies, and that much of their

opp osition is statistically asso ciated with a b elief|no doubt grounded in

their exp erience|that individual e ort makes a di erence in getting ahead.

Martin Gilens of Yale University found that during recessions p eople are less

likely to explain p overtyby \lack of e ort by the p o or", and more likely to

supp ort egalitarian programs (Gilens 1999).

A more striking fact ab out the decline in the supp ort for the former Aid

to Families with Dep endent Children, Fo o d Stamps, and other means-tested

so cial supp ort programs in the United States, however, is that overwhelming

ma jorities opp ose the status quo, whatever their income, race, or p ersonal

history with such programs. This pattern of public sentiment, we think, can

b e accounted for in terms of the principle of strong recipro city.

We rely mainly on two studies. The rst (Farkas and Robinson 1996)

analyzes data collected in late 1995 by Public Agenda, a nonpro t, non-

partisan research organization. The authors conducted eight fo cus groups

around the country, then did a national survey, involving half-hour inter-

views, of 1000 randomly selected Americans, plus a national oversample of

200 African-Americans. The second, p olitical scientist Martin Gilens' Why

Americans Hate Welfare, is an analysis and review of several p olls executed

12

during the 1990's and earlier byvarious news organizations.

In the Public Agenda survey 63% of resp ondents thought the welfare

system should b e eliminated or \fundamentally overhauled" while another

34% thought it should b e \adjusted somewhat." Only 3% approved of the

system as is (p. 9). Even among resp ondents from households receiving

welfare only 9% expressed basic approval of the system, while 42% wanted

12

A third study byWeaver et al. (1995), drawing in addition on NORC and General

So cial Survey data, comes to broadly similar conclusions. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 18

a fundamental overhaul and an additional 46% wanted some adjustments.

The cost of welfare programs cannot explain this opp osition. While p eo-

ple generally overstate the share of the Federal budget devoted to welfare (p.

13

9), this cannot account for the observed opp osition. Farkas and Robinson

note that

By more than four to one (65% to 14%), Americans say the

most upsetting thing ab out welfare is that \it encourages p eo-

ple to adopt the wrong lifestyle and values," not that \it costs

to much tax money.". . . Of nine p ossible reforms presented to

resp ondents|ranging from requiring job training to paying sur-

prise visits to make sure recipients deserve b ene ts|reducing

b ene ts ranked last in p opularity(Table 4).

The cost, apparently, is not problem. In fo cus groups:

Participants invariably dismissed arguments ab out the limited

nancial costs of welfare in almost derisive terms as irrelevant

and b eside the p oint. (p. 9,10).

Nor can the p erception of fraud account for this opp osition. It is true that

64% of resp ondents (and 66% of resp ondents on welfare) b elieve welfare

fraud is a serious problem. However most do not consider it more seri-

ous than in other government programs, and only 35% of survey resp on-

dents would be more \comfortable with welfare" if fraud were eliminated

(p. 11,12).

In commenting on this fact Martin Gilens (1999):1,2 observes that \Pol-

itics is often viewed, byelites at least, as a pro cess centered on the question

`who gets what.' For ordinary Americans, however, p olitics is more often

ab out `who deserves what' and the welfare state is no exception." In the

Public Agenda study, resp ondents overwhelming consider welfare to b e un-

fair to working p eople and addictive to recipients. By a more than ve to

one margin (69% to 13%, and 64% to 11% for p eople receiving welfare),

resp ondents say that recipients abuse the system|for instance by not lo ok-

ing for work|rather than actually cheating the system|e.g., by collecting

multiple b ene ts (p. 12). Moreover, 68% ob ject (59% of welfare recipients)

that welfare is \passed on from generation to generation, creating a p er-

manent underclass"In the same vein, 70% (71% of welfare recipients) say

13

As a general rule non-exp erts vastly overstate the share of the tax revenues devoted

to things of which they disapprove, whether it b e foreign aid, welfare, aids research, or

military exp enditure|the opp osition is generally the cause of the exaggeration, not vice-

versa. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 19

welfare makes it \ nancially b etter for p eople to stay on welfare than to

get a job," 57% (62% of welfare recipients) think welfare encourages \p eo-

ple to b e lazy" and 60% (64% of welfare recipients) say the welfare system

\encourages p eople to have kids out of wedlo ck" (p. 14,15)

But this is b eside the p oint. Whether or not, for example, welfare causes

out of wedlo ck births, for example, or fosters an unwillingness to work, citi-

zens ob ject that the system provides nancial supp ort for those who under-

take these so cially disapproved b ehaviors. Their desire is to b ear witness

against the b ehavior and to disasso ciate themselves from it, whether or not

their actions can change it.

This then is the moral opp osition to welfare. Many of the ob jections

to the system, and many of the ethical judgments of the poor are based

on misconceptions, a lack of compassion, and prejudice, fanned by p oliti-

cal entrepreneurs of the right. Racial stereotyping and welfare bashing are

closely asso ciated. The public agenda survey shows that whites are much

more likely than African Americans to attribute negative attributes to wel-

fare recipients, and much more likely to blame an individual's p overty on

lack of e ort. But even here recipro city motives are evident. The survey

data show, writes Gilens, that

For most white Americans, race-based opp osition to welfare is

not fed by ill-will toward blacks, nor is it based on whites' desire

to maintain their economic advantages over African Americans.

Instead race-based opp osition to welfare stems from the sp eci c

p erception that, as a group, African Americans are not commit-

ted to the work ethic.

Taking account of the fact that many Americans see the currentwelfare

system as a violation of deeply held recipro city norms do es not oblige us to

either agree or disagree with these views. Still less do es it require that p olicy

makers adopt punitive measures and stingy budgets for the p o or. Indeed

the public strongly supp orts income supp ort measures when asked in ways

that make clear the deserving nature of the p o or: a 1995 NYT/CBS p oll,

for instance, found that twice as many agreed as disagreed that \it is the

resp onsibility of the government to take care of p eople who can't take care

of themselves."

Like Opp enheimer and Frohlich's exp erimental sub jects, those surveyed

by p ollsters, exhibit what wehave termed `basic needs generosity,' a virtually

unconditional willingness to share with others to assure them of some mini-

mal standard, esp ecially, as the survey data show, when this is implemented

through provision of food, basic medical care, housing, and other essential Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 20

go o ds. The interplay of basic needs generosity and strong recipro city, we

think, accounts for the salient facts ab out public opinion concerning welfare.

5 Conclusion

If we are right, egalitarians have misundersto o d the revolt against welfare

and the resistance to helping the needy, attributing it to sel shness by the

electorate rather than the failure of many programs to tap powerful com-

mitments to fairness and generosity and the fact that some programs app ear

to violate deeply held recipro city norms.

There is an obvious ob jection of our argument. \Morality is so cially de-

termined," we hear the reader musing, \so why not transform moralityto t

the needs of egalitarian p olicy rather than tailoring p olicy to existing moral-

ity?" Why not promote a public morality of expanded, virtually uncondi-

tional altruism towards p eople whom the hyp ercomp etitive, hyp erindividu-

alist market system have left b ehind, rather than pandering to the sometimes

punitive expressions of strong recipro city? Have not radical egalitarians,

from nineteenth century ab olitionists to contemp orary feminists, civil lib er-

tarians, and welfare state activists, successfully made consciousness-raising

a central part of their p olitical practice? What ever happ ened to the so-

cialist ideal of `from each according to his ability, to each according to his

needs' ? Why, in short, b e trapp ed by the present in designing a future?

Our answer is that while a strong public morality is imp ortant in an

egalitarian so ciety, the human mind is not a blank slate that is equally dis-

p osed to accept whatever moral rules are presented to it by either dominant

elites or egalitarian reformers. Rather, p eople are predisp osed to accept

some moral rules, others can be imp osed up on them with some diculty,

and still others cannot be imp osed in any stable manner at all. Egalitari-

ans have b een successful in app ealing to the more elevated human motives

precisely when they have shown that dominant institutions violate norms of

recipro city, and may b e replaced by institutions more consistent with these

norms. Countless other egalitarian initiatives have failed. We b elieve that

basic needs generosity and strong recipro city are among those that we are

predisp osed to accept. Barrington Mo ore, Jr., in his comparative study of

revolution and revolt cited earlier, expresses this idea in the following words:

... awareness of so cial injustice would b e imp ossible if human b e-

ings could b e made to accept any and all rules. Evidently there

are some constraints on the making of moral rules and there-

fore on the p ossible forms of moral outrage. (Barrington Mo ore Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 21

1978):5.

What accounts for our moral predisp ositions? The answer is some com-

bination of genes and culture. Neither is immutable, but likewise neither is

amenable to reconstruction in an arbitrary manner. The cultural and the

genetic structures that frame our lives and a ect our prop ensity to accept

or reject particular moral principles are pro ducts of cultural and biological

evolution. Moral principles succeed b ecause they have aided those individ-

uals who have used them and those groups in which they have b een preva-

lent. They may well conform to particular philosophical, p olitical, and/or

religious logics, but they p ersist largely b ecause the individuals and so cial

groups that have deployed these moral principles have prevailed, while others

that have not have p erished or b een assimilated.

This is not to say that culture change is always conservative and slow-

moving, for we know that this is not the case. Nor is public opinion immune

to p ersuasion, as the meteoric rise of environmental concerns and feminist

values over the past three decades attest. Rather it is to say that cultural

change, like technical change, is sub ject to enduring and material con-

straints. The evidence is that among these regularities is the ease with which

p eople assume the b ehavior of Homo reciprocans and the unsustainability

of egalitarian programs that violate norms of recipro city.

Many traditional pro jects of egalitarians, such as land reform and em-

ployee ownership of their workplaces are strongly consistent with recipro city

norms, as they make p eople the owners not only of the fruits of their lab ors,

but more broadly of the consequences of their actions. The same may be

said of more conventional initiatives such as improved educational opp or-

tunity and p olicies to supp ort home ownership|there is go o d evidence, for

example, that home ownership promotes active participation in lo cal p olitics

and a willingness to discipline p ersonally those engaging in antiso cial b ehav-

iors in the neighborhood. An expansion of subsidies designed to promote

employment and increase earnings among the p o or would tap p owerful reci-

pro city motives, as has b een suggested by Columbia University economist

Edmund Phelps in his recent book Rewarding Work (1997), and by Rob ert

Haveman in these pages. Similarly, so cial insurance programs might b e re-

formulated along lines suggested by University of California economist John

Ro emer in these pages to protect individuals from risks over which they

have no control, while not indemnifying p eople against the results of their

own choices, other than providing a minimal o or to living standards. In

this manner, for example, families could b e protected against regional uc-

tuations in home values|the main form of wealth for most p eople|as Yale Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 22

economist Rob ert Shiller (1993) has shown. Other forms of insurance could

partially protect workers from shifts in demand for their services induced by

global economic changes.

If we are correct, an egalitarian so ciety can b e built on the basis of these

and other p olicies consistent with strong recipro city, along with a guarantee

of an acceptable minimal living standard consistent with the widely do cu-

mented motives of basic needs generosity. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 23

References

Abbink, Klaus, Gary E. Bolton, Ab dolkarim Sadrieh, and Fang-Fang Tang,

\Adaptive Learning versus Punishment in Ultimatum Bargaining," 1996.

Discussion Pap er No. B0-381, University of Bonn.

Andreoni, James, \WhyFree Ride? Strategies and Learning in Public Go o d

Exp eriments," Journal of Public Economics 37 (1988):291{304.

, \Co op eration in Public Goods Exp eriments: Kindness or Confusion,"

American Economic Review 85,4 (1995):891{904.

Axelro d, Rob ert, The Evolution of Co op eration (New York: Basic Bo oks,

1984).

and William D. Hamilton, \The Evolution of Co op eration," Science 211

(1981):1390{1396 .

Balikci, Asen, The Netsilik Eskimo (New York: Natural History Press,

1970).

Blount, Sally, \When So cial Outcomes Aren't Fair: The E ect of Causal

Attributions on Preferences," Organizational Behavior & Human Decision

Pro cesses 63,2 (August 1995):131{144.

Blurton-Jones, Nicholas G., \Tolerated Theft, Suggestions ab out the Ecol-

ogy and Evolution of Sharing, Hoarding, and Scrounging," So cial Science

Information 26,1 (1987):31{54.

Bo ehm, Christopher, \The Evolutionary Development of MoralityasanEf-

fect of Dominance Behavior and Con ict Interference," Journal of So cial

and Biological Structures 5 (1982):413{421.

, Blood Revenge: The Enactment and Management of Con ict in Mon-

tenegro and Other Tribal So cieties (Philadelphi, PA: UniversityofPenn-

sylvania Press, 1984).

, \Egalitarian Behavior and Reverse Dominance Hierarchy," Current An-

throp ology 34,3 (June 1993):227{254.

Bolton, Gary E. and Rami Zwick, \Anonymity versus Punishment in Ulti-

matum Games," Games and Economic Behavior 10 (1995):95{121.

Bowles, Samuel, \Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of

Markets and Other Economic Institutions," Journal of Economic Litera-

ture 36 (March 1998).

and Herb ert Gintis, \The Evolution of Strong Recipro city," 1998. Santa

Fe Institute Working Pap er #98-08-073E.

and , \The Moral Economy of Community: Structured Populations

and the Evolution of Proso cial Norms," Evolution & Human Behavior

19,1 (January 1998):3{25. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 24

and , Recasting Egalitarianism: New Rules for Markets, States, and

Communities (London: Verso, 1998). Erik Olin Wright (ed.).

Camerer, Colin and , \Ultimatums, Dictators, and Manners,"

Journal of Economic Persp ectives 9,2 (1995):209{219.

Cameron, Lisa, \Raising the Stakes in the Ultimatum Game: Exp erimental

Evidence from Indonesia," 1995. Discussion Pap er #345, Departmentof

Economics, Princeton University.

Cashdan, Elizab eth A., \Egalitarianism among Hunters and Gatherers,"

American Anthrop ologist 82 (1980):116{120.

Coleman, James S., \Free Riders and Zealots: The Role of So cial Networks,"

So ciological Theory 6 (Spring 1988):52{57.

Damas, David, \Central Eskimo Systems of Fo o d Sharing," Ethnology 11,3

(1972):220{240.

Eckel, Catherine and Philip Grossman, \Chivalry and Solidarity in Ulti-

matum games," February 1997. Virginia Polytechnic Institute, Working

Pap er #E92-23.

Edda, \Havamal," in D. E. Martin Clarke (ed.) The Havamal, with Selec-

tions from other Po ems in the Edda 1923).

Endicott, Kirk, \Prop erty, Power and Con ict among the Batek of Mal-

aysia," in T. Ingold, D. Riches, and J. Wo o dburn (eds.) Hunters and

Gatherers (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1988) pp. 110{127.

Farkas, Steve and Jean Robinson, The Values we Live By: What Americans

Want from Welfare Reform (New York: Public Agenda, 1996).

Fehr, Ernst and E. Tougareva, \Do Comp etitive Markets with High Stakes

Remove Recipro cal Fairness? Exp erimental Evidence from Russia," 1995.

Working Pap er, Institute for Empirical Economic Research, Universityof

Zurich.

and Klaus M. Schmidt, \A Theory of Fairness, Comp etition, and Co op-

eration," 1997. Institute for Empirical Research in Economics, University

of Zuric  h.

and Simon Gachter, \Co op eration and Punishment," 1998. Working

Pap er, Institute for Empirical Economic Research, UniversityofZurich.

and , \Recipro city and Economics: The Economic Implications of

`Homo Recipro cans'," Europ ean Economic Review 42 (1998):845{859.

, , and Georg Kirchsteiger, \Recipro city as a Contract Enforcement

Device: Exp erimental Evidence," Econometrica 65,4 (July 1997):833{860.

Forsythe, Rob ert, Jo el Horowitz, N. E. Savin, and Martin Sefton, \Replica-

bility,Fairness and Pay in Exp eriments with Simple Bargaining Games," Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 25

Games and Economic Behavior 6,3 (May 1994):347{369.

Frohlich, Norman and Jo e A. Opp enheimer, Cho osing Justice: An Exp er-

imental Approach to Ethical Theory (Berkeley: University of California

Press, 1992).

Gilens, Martin, Why Americans Hate Welfare (University of Chicago Press,

1999).

Guth, Werner, R. Schmittb erger, and B. Schwarz, \An Exp erimental Anal-

ysis of Ultimatum Bargaining," Journal of Economic Behavior and Orga-

nization 3 (May 1982):367{388.

Hawkes, Kristen, \Sharing and Collective Action," in E. Smith and B. Win-

terhalder (eds.) Evolutionary Ecology and Human Behavior (New York:

Aldine, 1992) pp. 269{300.

, \Why Hunter-Gatherers Work: An Ancient Version of the Problem of

Public Go o ds," CurrentAnthrop ology 34,4 (1993):341{361.

Hayek, Frederick, The Three Sources of Human Values (London: London

Scho ol of Economics, 1978).

Ho man, Elizab eth, Kevin McCab e, and Vernon L. Smith, \So cial Distance

and Other-Regarding Behavior in Dictator Games," American Economic

Review 86,3 (June 1996):653{660.

, , Keith Shachat, and Vernon L. Smith, \Preferences, Prop erty Rights,

and Anonymity in Bargaining Games," Games and Economic Behavior 7

(1994):346{380.

Isaac, R. Mark and James M. Walker, \Group Size E ects in Public Go o ds

Provision: The Voluntary Contribution Mechanism," Quarterly Journal

of Economics 103 (1988):179{200.

Kaplan, Hillard and Kim Hill, \Food Sharing among Ache Foragers: Tests

of EXplanatory Hyp otheses," CurrentAnthrop ology 26,2 (1985):223{246.

and , \Hunting Ability and Repro ductive Success among Male Ache

Foragers: Preliminary Results," Current Anthrop ology 26,1 (1985):131{

133.

, , Kristen Hawkes, and Ana Hurtado, \Food Sharing among Ache

Hunter-Gatherers of Eastern Paraguay," Current Anthrop ology 25,1

(1984):113{115.

Kent, Susan, \And Justice for All: The DevelopmentofPolitical Centraliza-

tion Among Newly Sedentary Foragers," American Anthrop ologist 93,1

(1989):703{712.

Knauft, Bruce, \So cialityversus Self-interest in Human Evolution," Behav-

ioral and Brain Sciences 12,4 (1989):12{13. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 26

, \Violence and So ciality in Human Evolution," Current Anthrop ology

32,4 (August{Octob er 1991):391{428.

Kollo ck, Peter, \Transforming So cial Dilemmas: Group Identity and Co op-

eration," in Peter Danielson (ed.) Mo deling Rational and Moral Agents

(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997).

Krop otkin, Petr, Mutual Aid: AFactor in Evolution (New York: Black Rose

Bo oks, 1989[1903]).

Lee, Richard Borshay, The !Kung San: Men, Women and Work in a Foraging

So ciety (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979).

Mo ore, Jr. Barrington, Injustice: The So cial Bases of Ob edience and Revolt

(White Plains: M. E. Sharp e, 1978).

Nisb ett, Richard E. and Dov Cohen, Culture of Honor: The Psychology of

Violence in the South (Boulder: Westview Press, 1996).

Ostrom, Elinor, James Walker, and Roy Gardner, \Covenants with and

without a Sword: Self-Governance is Possible," American Political Science

Review 86,2 (June 1992):404{417.

Parsons, Talcott, \Evolutionary Universals in So ciety," American So ciolog-

ical Review 29,3 (June 1964).

Phelps, Edmund S., Rewarding Work: How to Restore Participation and

Self-supp ort to Free Enterprise (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,

1997).

Piketty, Thomas, \So cial Mobility and Redistributive Politics," Quarterly

Journal of Economics CX,3 (August 1995):551{584.

Polanyi, Karl, The Great Transformation (New York: Farrar and Rinehart,

1944).

Roth, Alvin, \Bargaining Exp eriments," in John Kagel and Alvin Roth

(eds.) The Handb o ok of Exp erimental Economics (Princeton: Princeton

University Press, 1995).

Sampson, Rob ert J., Stephen W. Raudenbush, and Felton Earls, \Neigh-

b orho o ds and Violent Crime: A Multilevel Study of Collective Ecacy,"

Science 277 (August 15, 1997):918{924.

Scott, James C., The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Reb ellion and Subsis-

tence in Southeast Asia (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1976).

Shiller, Rob ert J., Macro Markets: Creating Institutions for Managing So-

ciety's Largest Economic Risks (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).

Suleiman, Ramzi, \Exp ectations and Fairness in a Mo di ed Ultimatum

Game," Journal of Economic Psychology 17,5 (Novemb er 1996):531{554. Octob er 19, 1998

Is EqualityPasse? 27

Weaver, R. Kent, Rob ert Y. Shapiro, and Lawrence R. Jacobs, \Poll Trends:

Welfare," Public Opinion Quarterly 39 (1995):606{627.

Wenzel, George W., \Ningiqtuq: Resource Sharing and Generalized Reci-

pro city in Clyde River, Nunavut," Arctic Anthrop ology 32,2 (1995):43{

60.

Williamson, John B., \Beliefs ab out the Motivation of the Poor and Atti-

tudes toward PovertyPolicy,," So cial Problems 21,5 (June 1974):734{747.

Wo o dburn, James, \Egalitarian So cieties," Man 17,3 (1982):431{451.

and Alan Barnard, \Prop erty,Power and Ideology in Hunter-Gathering

So cieties: An Intro duction," in T. Ingold, D. Riches, and J. Wo o dburn

(eds.) Hunters and Gatherers (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1988) pp. 4{

31.

enPap ersnBoston ReviewnIs EqualityPasse.tex Octob er 28, 1998 Octob er 19, 1998