Open Bilgerdissertation.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Open Bilgerdissertation.Pdf The Pennsylvania State University The Graduate School College of the Liberal Arts A CRITICAL EXPLICATION OF THE FIRST TWO SECTIONS OF FICHTE’S GRUNDLAGE DER GESAMTEN WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE A Dissertation in Philosophy by Paul Rudolf Bilger © 2011 Paul Rudolf Bilger Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2011 ii The dissertation of Paul R. Bilger was reviewed and approved* by the following: Dennis J. Schmidt Professor of Philosophy Chair of Committee Dissertation Adviser Christopher P. Long Associate Professor of Philosophy Brady Bowman Assistant Professor of Philosophy Jeffrey Nealon Professor of English Nancy Tuana Professor of Philosophy Director of Graduate Studies for the Department of Philosophy *Signatures are on file at the Graduate School iii Abstract In this dissertation, I offer a critical explication of the theoretical section of Johann Gottlieb Fichte‘s Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge (Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, abbreviated as Grundlage); in doing so, I explore the highly idiosyncratic mode of philosophical reasoning used in that text. In doing this, it is of decisive importance to understand how a set of philosophical figures function to drive the development of the conceptuality required for Fichte‘s project. As such, the explication of this work partly involves tracing the way in which figurative language and geometrical schema develop and drive the determination of that conceptuality. In closely following the Grundlage‘s series of concepts and schemata, we are better able to understand the decisive importance such figures play in Fichte‘s thought, and, more generally, develop a deeper appreciation of the role of the imagination in philosophical thinking. iv Table of Contents Introduction…………………………………………………… 1 Chapter 1: Fichtean Schemata and Figurative Language…..…… 10 Chapter 2: Architectures of System……………………………. 25 Chapter 3: I and not-I …………………………………………. 51 Chapter 4: Division and Determination.……...……………..…. 71 Chapter 5: the Principle of Ground …...…………….……...…. 89 Chapter 6: Efficacy and Substantiality…………………………. 108 Chapter 7: Inter-active and Independent Activities….…………. 139 Chapter 8: Consciousness as Crossing…...…………….………. 164 Chapter 9: Ideal and Real Ground…………..…………………. 176 Chapter 10: the Determination of Totality……………………... 199 Chapter 11: Imagination and Anstoß…………………….….….... 211 Chapter 12: the Deduction of Representation……….…………. 235 Conclusion: The Role of Liminal Figurativity in the Grundlage…. 253 Bibliography…………………………………………………….. 257 1 Introduction How at all does the empirical I stand to the pure I-I? Anyone who wants to be a philosopher will more than appreciate a little information on this, and above all want not to become a ludicrous creature by being transformed, eins zwei drei kokolorum, into speculation. — Søren Kierkegaard, Concluding unscientific postscript Fichte‘s thought is difficult to understand but easy to caricature. As Günter Zöller notes, the difficulty of his work arises from the fact that he ―eschewed established philosophical terminology, continued to revise the presentation of his philosophical position throughout his lifetime and made unprecedented demands for sustained concentration on the listeners of his lectures and the readers of his works‖ (Fichte‘s Transcendental Philosophy 25). As opposed to this, the central position which he gives to the I, especially in his Jena period, makes it easy to reduce his philosophy to a slogan: ―The I is to be the central principle of philosophy,‖ which, when read superficially, appears to be nothing more than philosophical narcissism1. The seeming opacity of his thinking, when combined its traditional reception as a mere subjective idealist— a paving stone on the way from Kant to Hegel— had left the careful study of his work in a state of near total neglect until the relatively recent resurgence2 of interest in his work in the second half of the twentieth century. Given the difficulty of engaging Fichte, and the ease of dismissing him as the ―Philosopher of the I,‖ one might wonder if understanding Fichte is worth the effort. 1 This is a comparatively benign way of interpreting the Fichtean centrality of the I. In Eclipse of Reason, Max Horkheimer writes, ―in [Fichte‘s] early doctrine, according to which the sole raison d‘être of the world lies in affording a field of activity for the imperious transcendental self, the relation between the ego [das Ich] and nature is one of tyranny.‖ Horkheimer understands modern rationality to be much closer to this portrayal of Fichte than that rationality itself recognizes. 2 Foreshadowed by Heidegger‘s lectures on German Idealism, but truly coming into its own, in German speaking countries, with Dieter Henrich‘s work on Fichte (Henrich, Einsicht). In the English speaking world, Daniel Breazeale has been instrumental in both making his work accessible in translation and in editing multiple anthologies which comment on some phase of his thinking. See the bibliography, below, for an indication of its scope. 2 I initially encountered Fichte‘s work in a graduate course on German Idealism; at this time, I became acquainted with the work of his Jena period (1794 — 1800). This period of his thinking is marked by both an insistence on establishing scientific (i.e. Wissenschaftlich) rigor within philosophy and the project of securing, through philosophical thought, the foundations of the other sciences. In itself, this is not unusual, as many thinkers of the same era (e.g. Karl Leonhard Reinhold, Jacob Sigismund Beck, etc.) understood themselves as having a similar, if not identical, project. Nor is it unique to Fichte that he finds his point of departure in the study of Kant‘s critical philosophy (the same is true of Reinhold and Beck) or even that he aspires to ―complete‖ the Kantian project. What struck me about Fichte was the way in which he thematizes representation itself: representation— the experience of a certain set of mental determinations as free or constrained— isn‘t simply presupposed but set forth as something which must be explained, but must itself be accounted for. Given the critical parameters of Fichte‘s philosophy, this cannot mean explaining representation on the basis of something which exists wholly independently of it. Representation must be accounted for on the basis of something not wholly other to it, yet also more fundamental than it (i.e. unlike representation, not requiring a higher ground to explain). This means that the principles which account for the emergence of representation can neither be ―things in themselves‖ nor themselves mere representations. If these principles were things in themselves, he would be left with the skeptical impasse of how knowledge of such things is possible; if they were mere representations, he would be presupposing the very thing he sets out to account for. Fichte‘s turn to the I (das Ich) must be understood in terms of this exigency. On the one hand, the I is the being for whom there are representations; on the other, it is, itself, the representing being (the Kantian legacy)— the I is active in representation. But merely appealing to the I is not sufficient; the representations which must be accounted for are not mere fancy but are bound up with feelings of necessity and constraint. How and why should the I limit itself in this way? Yet, 3 once again, appealing to a thing-in-itself as the limiting principle of the I is not acceptable, as that outstrips the limits of critical philosophy. The I, ―itself,‖ becomes something which must be understood— not, at this point, by appealing to a ground outside the I, but through a more nuanced examination of the I‘s self-constitution. Like representation, the I cannot be simply presupposed, but the peculiar logic of its ―self-positing‖ must be investigated. At this point, the problem of representation becomes the problem of self-consciousness; this is because the I‘s existence is unthinkable apart from its self-positing. For Fichte, self-consciousness is not a matter of coming to be conscious of something which pre-existed that act, but is itself the activity through which both the being which is conscious and the being which that being is conscious of exist. For the I to be an I, it must be conscious of itself as an I. Indeed, this is why Dieter Henrich understood Fichte‘s thought to be of contemporary relevance. Henrich writes, ―[a]nyone seeking a suitable concept of ‗self-consciousness‘ must go back to Fichte and the knowledge he achieved‖— it is not new that the I is taken as an explanatory ground (consider Descartes); what is new is the way in which self-consciousness itself becomes a problem. Thus, in Fichte‘s Jena period, we find two questions which are not without contemporary relevance— the question of the emergence of representation, and the question of essential nature of subjectivity. Because of this relevance, it is the aim of this dissertation to provide readers with some access to Fichte‘s thought in its earliest, distinctively Fichtean phase— his work from 1794, by way of the lecture handbook he published that year. The text under consideration here is Fichte‘s 1794 lecture handbook, Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge (Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, hereafter abbreviated as Grundlage). This was the first (and only public) detailed presentation of the foundation of his philosophy, and, as the date suggests, we also have in this text a representative presentation of the earliest phase of the Jena period. Though many essays have been written, there has been little in the way of a sustained 4 explication of this text3. Because the chief interest for this work is the emergence of representation and the self-constitution of the I, I will limit the investigation of the Grundlage to the first two parts. To make sense of this work, we will also be making extensive use of two other texts from this period— the prospectus for the same lecture course (Concerning the Concept of the Wissenschaftslehre) and an essay he wrote on the origin of language the following year (―On the Linguistic Capacity and the Origin of Language‖).
Recommended publications
  • International Yearbook for Hermeneutics 17 · 2018
    International Yearbook for Hermeneutics 17 · 2018 International Yearbook for Hermeneutics Internationales Jahrbuch für Hermeneutik edited by Günter Figal and Bernhard Zimmermann in cooperation with Damir Barbaric´, Gottfried Boehm, Luca Crescenzi, Ingolf Dalferth, Nicholas Davey, Maurizio Ferraris, Jean Grondin, Pavel Kouba, Irmgard Männlein-Robert, Hideki Mine, Hans Ruin, John Sallis, Dennis Schmidt, Dirk Westerkamp 17 · 2018 Focus: Logos Schwerpunkt: Logos Mohr Siebeck Editorial directors / Redaktionsleitung: Dr. Tobias Keiling, PhD Dr. Anna Novokhatko Editorial team / Redaktion: Jon Burmeister Benjamin Harter Jerome Veith The Yearbook calls for contributions in English or German on topics in Philosophical Hermeneutics and bordering disciplines. Please send manuscripts to yearbook-he r m e n e u t i c s @altphil.uni-freiburg.de. All articles, except when invited, are subject to a double blind review. We assume that manuscripts are unpublished and have not been submitted for publi- cation elsewhere. Citations are to be made according to the style in the present volume. Detailed information on formatting manuscripts can be downloaded from: http://www.alt p h i l .uni-freiburg.de/IYH. Das Jahrbuch bittet um Zusendungen auf Deutsch oder Englisch zu Themen der Phil- osophischen Hermeneutik und angrenzender Disziplinen. Bitte senden Sie Manuskripte an: [email protected]. Alle Artikel, die nicht auf Einladung der Herausgeber verfasst worden sind, werden in einem double blind review-Verfahren begutachtet. Es wird davon ausgegangen, dass es sich bei eingereichten Manuskripten um un- veröffentlichte Originalbeiträge handelt, die nicht an anderer Stelle zur Veröffentlichung vorgelegt worden sind. Literaturhinweise bitte wie im vorliegenden Band. Ausführliche Hinweise für Manuskripte können unter http://www.altphil.uni-freiburg.de/IYH herun- tergeladen werden.
    [Show full text]
  • SCHILLER, NOVALIS, and the CONCEPT of AUFHEBUNG Hammam Aldouri
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 15, no. 1, 2019 BEFORE HEGEL: SCHILLER, NOVALIS, AND THE CONCEPT OF AUFHEBUNG Hammam Aldouri ABSTRACT: Philosophical explorations of the concept of Aufhebung (sublation, supersession) immediately prior to its formulation in Hegel’s work have remained relatively absent within the context of both Hegel scholarship and German Idealism studies. Hegel is often simply represented as the originator of the concept and the latter is understood almost exclusively within his oeuvre. This essay addresses this lack by offering an exposition of the notion as it unfolds in two works from 1795-1796: Friedrich Schiller’s Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man and Novalis’ Fichte Studies. In these works, we find distinctive examinations of Aufhebung understood as the name of a process in which a subject comprehends itself in relation to its own processual development. My guiding premise is that without an adequate comprehension of the way in which Aufhebung is constructed and comprehended in the last years of the eighteenth century, we cannot establish the vantage point from which to reconstruct Hegel’s early conception of the notion, a conception which begins to emerge in his earliest Frankfurt writings in 1797, as a contribution to the constellation of post-Kantian conceptions. Keywords: Aufhebung, Schiller, Novalis, Aesthetic Education, Fichte Studies INTRODUCTION The concept of Aufhebung (sublation, supersession) is, without question, one of the most contested and discussed concepts of Hegel’s philosophical enterprise th th 1 and its critical reception in the 19 and 20 centuries. One distinctive 1 So much so, in fact, that it has led philosopher’s such as Jean-Luc Nancy to state that there is “no great study of Hegel that is not a study on the Aufhebung.” Nancy 2001, 158n7.
    [Show full text]
  • Facing Nature: the Infinite in the Flesh
    Facing Nature: The Infinite in the Flesh Robert Daniel Victorin-Vangerud, B.A., M.Div. This thesis is presented for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of. Murdoch University Perth, Western Australia 2004 I declare that this thesis is my own account of my research. ------------------------------------- Robert Daniel Victorin-Vangerud i Abstract “Facing Nature: The Infinite in the Flesh” by Robert Victorin-Vangerud This thesis explores the relation between two interpretations of chôra, drawn from a reading of Plato’s Timaeus. The first I label the elemental chôra. The second, I call the social chôra. The first chapter addresses the elements in Ionian philosophy, with an eye toward the political and social backdrop of the important cosmological notion of isonomia, law of equals. Here social and elemental are continuous. Chapter two looks at the next phase of Presocratic thought, Elea, specifically Parmenides and his influence on later thought, then turns to Heidegger’s reading of Parmenides’ through the key word of alêtheia. Finally, I offer a reading of Parmenides through a different key word— trust. The third chapter examines Plato’s cosmology in the Timaeus, focusing on the way the beginning of this dialogue inflects the dialogue in a political/social direction, putting the social chôra in tension with the elemental chôra that the body of the Timaeus’ discusses. In the fourth chapter, which examines the Phaedrus, this tension is inverted, since this dialogue on writing and justice set in what proves to be the mesmerizing and erotic elemental milieu of the world outside the walls of the polis. The second half of the dissertation turns to some modern thinkers within the phenomenological tradition or its wake who write about elementals.
    [Show full text]
  • On Hegel on Buddhism Mario D'amato Rollins College, [email protected]
    Rollins College Rollins Scholarship Online Student-Faculty Collaborative Research 1-1-2011 The pS ecter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism Mario D'Amato Rollins College, [email protected] Robert T. Moore Rollins College Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.rollins.edu/stud_fac Part of the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Published In D'Amato, Mario and Moore, Robert T., "The peS cter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism" (2011). Student-Faculty Collaborative Research. Paper 28. http://scholarship.rollins.edu/stud_fac/28 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Rollins Scholarship Online. It has been accepted for inclusion in Student-Faculty Collaborative Research by an authorized administrator of Rollins Scholarship Online. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Specter of Nihilism: On Hegel on Buddhism ∗ Mario D’Amato and Robert T. Moore Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) is renowned as one of the most complex and comprehensive modern philosophers. The goal of his philosophical system is nothing less than to explain the interrelationships among all the multifarious aspects of the whole of reality, including the entire array of historical religions. But Hegel’s dialectical method has been criticized as being speculative and idealistic, and his interpretation of religion has been written off by some as an overly ambitious attempt to force the historical religions into the confines of a predetermined hierarchical scheme. As for his perspective on Buddhism, Hegel interprets it as a form of nihilism, stating that for Buddhism, “the ultimate or highest [reality] is…nothing or not- being” and the “state of negation is the highest state: one must immerse oneself in this nothing, in the eternal tranquillity of the nothing generally” (LPR 253).1 Hegel’s interpretation of Buddhism has of course been appropriately criticized in recent scholarship, most ably by Roger-Pol Droit in his work The Cult of Nothingness: The Philosophers and the Buddha (2003).
    [Show full text]
  • The Generation of Higher Mental Functions in Vygotsky's Concepts of Development and Contradiction
    Research on Humanities and Social Sciences www.iiste.org ISSN 2224-5766 (Paper) ISSN 2225-0484 (Online) Vol.7, No.18, 2017 The Generation of Higher Mental Functions in Vygotsky’s Concepts of Development and Contradiction Ahmed Alnajjar, Ph.D. Mohamed Elhammoumi, Ph.D. Department of Psychology and Counseling, United Arab Emirates University, Al Ain City, UAE To study something historically means to study it in the process of change; that is the dialectical method's basic demand” (Vygotsky, 1978, p. 64-65). “Dialectics covers nature, thinking, history-it is the most general, maximally universal science. The theory of the psychological materialism or dialectics of psychology is what I call general psychology” (Vygotsky, 1997, p. 330). “It is dialectics that has given psychology its stability and its meaning … Through dialectics psychology is able to be at once a natural science and a human science …. dialectics has enabled psychology to comprehend the organism and its environment, in constant interaction, as a single, unified whole” (Wallon, 1951, p. 34). Abstract In this paper we argue that Vygotsky’s psychological research paradigm is a research epistemology, methodology, and ontology of theory and practice that attempts to build a psychology grounded within the social historical and cultural setting in which he/she evolved. Vygotsky’s whole enterprise was to establish a concrete human psychology committed to investigate how human nature changes, conceiving human development not just as quantitative, cumulative and linear, but also as qualitative, transformative change. In this outlook, contradiction leads to new contradictions, not necessarily “equilibrium”. The dialectical concepts of contradiction, development and transformation were fundamental to Vygotsky’s psychology.
    [Show full text]
  • Bataille and Derrida's Reading Of
    HeyJ XLIII (2002), pp. 295–310 ‘TARRYING WITH THE NEGATIVE’: BATAILLE AND DERRIDA’S READING OF NEGATION IN HEGEL’S PHENOMENOLOGY RAPHAEL FOSHAY St Michael’s Abbey, Farnborough, UK/ Clare Hall, University of Cambridge, UK Derrida’s endorsement, in his early essay ‘From Restricted to General Economy: A Hegelianism Without Reserve’ (1967), of Bataille’s critique of Hegelian dialectic joins many such early self-positionings in Derrida’s work within the Nietzschean–Heideggerian critique of dialectic. It is only quite recently that accumulated critical attention has been turned on the conspicuous continuity of Derrida’s work with this central tenet of the post-idealist critique of metaphysics.1 Recent work on Nietzsche’s understanding of Hegel finds serious deficiencies in his grasp of Hegelian dialectic,2 and Heidegger, while making frequent lapid- ary dismissals, is even more than usually elusive in his avoidance of explicit treatment of the role of the dialectical moment in the Hegelian speculative idealist dilation of reality as rational. The present article queries the understanding and workings of dialectic both in Hegel’s Phenomenology3 and in Derrida’s enthusiastic alignment with Bataille’s critique of that text. This latter critique takes issue with Hegel’s portrayal in the Phenomenology of negation as it finds phenomenal expression in the dialectic of the Master and the Bondsman. In Bataille’s view, in elid- ing the material difference between negation and death, Hegel’s treatment of the master–slave dialectic is seen to be exemplary of the fundamental incoherence of speculative idealism, its failure fully to think the material, embodied conditions of any possible speculative self-appropriation.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant and Heidegger on the Issue of Displacement
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Dissertations Theses and Dissertations 1990 The Problem of the Imagination for Subjectivity: Kant and Heidegger on the Issue of Displacement Richard Findler Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Findler, Richard, "The Problem of the Imagination for Subjectivity: Kant and Heidegger on the Issue of Displacement" (1990). Dissertations. 2912. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_diss/2912 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 1990 Richard Findler THE PROBLEM OF THE IMAGINATION FOR SUBJECTIVITY: KANT AND HEIDEGGER ON THE ISSUE OF DISPLACEMENT by Richard Findler A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Loyola University of Chicago in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy .'' ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I cannot go into my past and thank everyone who has in some way contributed to my dissertation, so let me thank those people who have directly contributed to it. First, I would like to thank Dr. John Sallis for having directed my dissertation. The insights and instruction I have received from him have proven to be invaluable, and there is no way I can truly thank him for everything he has done for me over the years.
    [Show full text]
  • Featured Title with RESPECT for NATURE Living As Part of The
    Philosophy featured title featured title THE SCIENCE WITH RESPECT OF KNOWING FOR NATURE J. G. Fichte’s 1804 Lectures Living as Part on the Wissenschaftslehre of the Natural World J. G. Fichte J. Claude Evans Translated and with an Introduction by Walter E. Wright Explores how humans can take the lives of animals and plants while maintaining The first English translation of Fichte’s a proper respect both for ecosystems second set of 1804 lectures on the and for those who live in them. Wissenschaftslehre. We eat, inevitably, at the expense of other living creatures. How can Considered by some to be his most important text, this series we take the lives of plants and animals while maintaining a proper of lectures given by Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762–1814) at his respect for both ecosystems and the individuals who live in them— home in Berlin in 1804 is widely regarded as the most perspicuous including ourselves? In this book philosopher J. Claude Evans presentation of his fundamental philosophy. Now available challenges much of the accepted wisdom in environmental ethics in English, this translation provides in striking and original and argues that human participation in the natural cycles of life language Fichte’s exploration of the transcendental foundations and death can have positive moral value. of experience and knowing in ways that go beyond Kant and Reinhold and charts a promising, novel pathway With a guide for the nonphilosophical reader, and set against for German Idealism. Through a close examination of this work the background of careful and penetrating critiques one can see that Fichte’s thought is much more than a way station of Albert Schweitzer’s principle of reverence for life and Paul Taylor’s between Kant and Hegel, and thus it makes the case for Fichte’s philosophy of respect for nature, Evans uses hunting and catch- independent philosophical importance.
    [Show full text]
  • Aufheben Civilization and Its Latest Discontents
    Aufheben Civilization and its Latest Discontents Against His-story, Against Leviathan! by Fredy Perlman (Detroit: Black & Red, 1983). from Aufheben #4 (1995) "I'm born in a certain age which has certain instruments of production and certain kinds of knowledge; I have the possibility to combine my ability with my knowledge, and can use the socially available means of production as instruments with which to realize an individual or collective project." R. Gregoire & F. Perlman, 1969[1] Civilization is under attack. A new critical current has emerged in recent years, united by an antagonism towards all tendencies that seem to include 'progress' as part of their programme. Perlman's book, described in the AK Distribution 1993 Catalogue as "One of the most significant and influential anarchic texts of the last few decades" (p. 30), is one of the key texts in this 'primitivist' current. In the U.S.A. and this country, it is in anarchist circles - particularly amongst those engaged in eco- struggles - that primitivism has become particularly popular. But Perlman used to be a Marxist (see the quote above), and he contributed usefully to the development of a libertarian version of Marx's theory for a number of years. The wholesale abandonment of Marx in favour of primitivism has touched the non-Leninist revolutionary milieu in this country too, with the recent conversion of Wildcat (UK)[2] to the anti-civilization position. One direction that the primitivist current points in is the need to develop a critique of technology. This is something the old left cannot grasp, and is one of the reasons why it is unable to connect properly with tendencies toward communism.
    [Show full text]
  • Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // … Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011.07.32
    Coll6/19/2019ege of Arts and LetEncyclopediaters of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline, Part I: Science of Logic // Reviews // Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews // … Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011.07.32 Everything Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline, Part I: Science of Logic Published: July 31, 2011 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Basic Outline, Part I: Science of Logic, Klaus Brinkmann and Daniel O. Dahlstrom (eds., trs.), Cambridge University Press, 2010, 358pp., $95.00 (hbk), ISBN 9780521829144. Reviewed by Christopher Yeomans, Purdue University This new translation of what is commonly known as the Encyclopedia Logic is the third volume in the series of Cambridge Hegel Translations under the general editorship of Michael Bauer. It is a readable, accurate and sometimes surprisingly elegant translation with a minimum of editorial apparatus that presents the work as the "basic outline" that it is. As the full title suggests, the Encyclopedia Logic is the first part of Hegel's systematic but condensed presentation of his mature philosophy, which is followed by two additional parts covering the philosophies of nature and spirit (Geist). Mostly the Encyclopedia Logic covers the same ground as his earlier (and much larger) Science of Logic, though in a much more schematic form and sometimes in a slightly different order. But it also includes an extensive section -- almost 90 pages in this edition -- entitled the "Preliminary Conception", in which Hegel provides a historical introduction to his philosophy beginning with ancient Greek philosophy and continuing on through empiricism and Kant. This is the best introduction to his thought that Hegel himself wrote, both because of its relative brevity and the clarity of the historical references as compared to his official introduction, the 1807 Phenomenology of Spirit.
    [Show full text]
  • Toward a New Foundationalism
    Toward a New Foundationalism Toward a New Foundationalism: From Carnap to Kripke, and from Husserl to Sallis By Bernard Freydberg Toward a New Foundationalism: From Carnap to Kripke, and from Husserl to Sallis By Bernard Freydberg This book first published 2021 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2021 by Bernard Freydberg All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-6205-0 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-6205-9 For Akiko, Forever. TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ................................................................................... ix Foreword .................................................................................................... x Prelude ..................................................................................................... xiii On the Way to Ruling Image: Rethinking two Canonical Platonic Tropes A Note on the Unusual Tone of this Book ............................................... xvi Rudolph Carnap .......................................................................................... 1 William James ...........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Poetic Imagination in Heidegger and Schelling
    The Poetic Imagination in Heidegger and Schelling Author: Christopher S. Yates Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/3056 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2011 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy THE POETIC IMAGINATION IN HEIDEGGER AND SCHELLING a dissertation by CHRISTOPHER S. YATES submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May, 2011 © copyright by CHRISTOPHER S. YATES 2011 ii The Poetic Imagination in Heidegger and Schelling Christopher Yates Advisor: John Sallis Readers: Richard Kearney, Jason Wirth Abstract This dissertation investigates the importance of the imagination in the thought of F.W. J. Schelling and Martin Heidegger, and argues that Heidegger’s later philosophy cannot be understood properly without appreciating Schelling’s central importance for him. It is increasingly recognized today that Schelling, who had long been overlooked, is an important figure in post-Kantian German Idealism. However, his significance for Heidegger’s concentration on the creative character of thought remains undervalued. I argue that, by tracing the theme of imagination in these thinkers, the milieu of Schelling’s absolute idealism and that of Heidegger’s hermeneutic phenomenlogy may be understood as distinct discourses that nevertheless share in a profound impulse to overcome sensible- intelligible and subject-object dualisms and retrieve and refine the productive and projective character of reason. This impulse is first evident in both thinkers’ attention to the role of imagination in Kant’s critical project (for Schelling, cir.
    [Show full text]