Nietzsche's Ethics of the Future

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche's Ethics of the Future fascist philosopher was born. Though even a minimally thoughtful reading of his work would render this myth invalidated, this remained the very prob- lem in the way of clearing up the misconception surrounding Nietzsche’s Nietzsche’s Ethics of the Future: Creative thought and his name. For beyond the deplorable editing work that the Nazi philosophers did to transform Nietzsche’s message, the very association of Valuation and the Life of Self-Development his name to fascist parties and figures dissuaded many from touching his works. Thankfully there were a few thinkers early on who fought to expose this myth for what it was, and to let Nietzsche’s thought speak for itself.2 Alex Obrigewitsch Much work has since been done as well, and continues to be argued in the pages of Nietzsche scholarship. But the question remains a contested one: what exactly is Nietzsche’s ethics? You must change your life. In his On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche studies the historical lin- —Rainer Maria Rilke, “Archaic Torso of Apollo” eage of our moral values, in order to uncover their origin. In doing this, he Every animal is driven to pasture with a blow. discovers that, like all things human, they are rooted in our nature, our man- —Heraclitus, Fragment 11 ner of life.3 Nietzsche then diagnoses “modern morality” (essentially Judeo- Christian values) as an illness, as life-denying, and proposes to create a dif- Nietzsche’s future, his posthumous life, which incorporates our past, present, ferent ethics, based upon a revaluation or transvaluation of all values (See and future interpretations and evaluations of his work, is riddled with com- GM III §26-27).4 Such a transformation of our values would be a radically plications and misunderstandings.1 His conception of existence as the strug- new ethics; but the book that he was to write elucidating this ethics of the gle of absolute differences leads to him devaluing and debasing democracy future was never written, due to his sudden descent into madness. Nietzsche in the political sphere, as well as utilitarianism and deontology in the ethical sphere – for all three come down to an essential equality of human beings 2Cf., for example, Georges Bataille, “Nietzsche and the Fascists,” in Visions of Excess, ed. (in terms of rights, calculability, and rationality, respectively). What sort of and trans. Allan Stoekl (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1985); and Walter Kauf- ethics might this strange figure profess, then? Based on a fundamental mis- mann, Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist (Princeton: Princeton Universtiy Press, 1974). Kaufmann did much to make Nietzsche readable in English, both by his translations understanding of the central concept of his thinking, the will to power, com- and the work done in this book, where he works through the myth in order to uncover its bined with the willful propagation and proliferation of this very misunder- falsity as a defamation of the truth. standing by Nietzsche’s sister and the Nazi party, the myth of Nietzsche as a 3Cf. Friedrich Nietzsche, “from ‘Homer’s Contest’,” in The Portable Nietzsche, ed. and trans. Walter Kaufmann (Toronto: Penguin, 1976), page 32: “When one speaks of humanity, 1Cf. Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, in The Basic Writings of Nietzsche, ed. and trans. the idea is fundamental that this is something which separates and distinguishes man from Walter Kaufmann (Toronto: Random House, 2000), “Why I Write Such Good Books,” §1: nature. In reality, however, there is no such separation: “natural” qualities and those called “The time hasn’t come for me yet: some are born posthumously”; and in the “Preface,” 1, to truly “human” are inseparably grown together.” the same work, where Nietzsche makes the now famous proclamation, “Above all, do not 4Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, trans. Maudemarie Clark and Alan mistake me for someone else.” Such mistakes have conceived of a monstrous birth. J. Swensen (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1998). 781 792 provides us with a critique of morality, but does he offer anything to replace is this seething force which seeks expression as perpetual intensification and it? Looking to his notebooks, posthumously collated and published as The increase. And the “forms” to which Conway refers? These “forms” are the Will to Power, in conjunction with scattered hints and traces throughout his forms of life (in the Wittgensteinian sense) which manifestly express the will corpus, it is possible to garner an understanding of what such an ethics of to power, the arrangements of the fundamental differential forces or affects transvaluation might be. By combining elements from these sources with an which underwrite what we consider “reality.” What the will to power wills in understanding of Nietzsche’s metaphysics and ontology (which is insepara- self-overcoming is a new valuation, produced by a new hierarchy of forces, ble from his ethics, as shall be seen), I aim to dispel the misperception that affects, or drives – this manifests itself as a different form of life, a different Nietzsche’s ethics espouses conflict with others, egoism, and promotes vio- way of living and acting, and thus a different way of affirmatively relating lent spectacles of dominant power displays. Rather, it shall be shown that the oneself to life. conflict and domination is not expressed externally, upon others, but rather The real, according to Nietzsche, is an illusion, an error. For reality as inwardly, in relation to oneself. Nietzsche’s ethics explicates a way of liv- perceived by the senses or through consciousness is a by-product of forces ing by means of creative valuation, a life of affirmation and self-overcoming, and drives, and their affective interpretation. This means that every fact, aimed at development and improvement, as well as increase, of one’s life and insofar as it is always already interpreted (not thematically by consciousness, character. An ethos, then, in the Greek sense, aimed ever towards the future, but “unconsciously” by the forces and drives that make us up, that we “really” in line with human life, as well as life more generally. are), is not separate from value.5 Everything appears as though “colored” or The thought of Nietzsche could rightly be considered a Lebensphilosophie, filtered by our moral evaluations which shape our world by means of our in that its content and concerns can always be traced genealogically back to form of life.6 Our morals and values are thus “symptoms and sign languages” the fundament of life. Life is, for Nietzsche, a vital force of expression, an (WP §258) which can be semiotically translated back to the arrangement or élan vital, which works itself through all things. It is inextricably bound up conflictual relationship of struggle between our passions and fundamental with the will to power, which is an interminable intensification of life, whose affective forces. And this is precisely what allows Nietzsche to diagnose the expression is the increase of power, of force, of affective potential. Daniel W. metaphysical illness ailing humanity, the Weltschmerz which has plagued us Conway describes the will to power as “the irrepressible surge of life [which] since at least the late nineteenth century – it is our system of values, our form legitimates the continual obsolescence of formerly vital forms and the con- of life, and thus the arrangement of our passions and drives, what we desire tinual creation of new forms,”(538) which connects it with another concept and affirm and what we prohibit and repress, which is producing our mass intertwined with life in Nietzsche’s thought, that being “self-overcoming.” Self-overcoming is the movement of the obsolescence of what was and the continual creation of what will be, to which Conway refers. It is inherent in the futurity of life, as the rolling wave which consumes what was in bringing 5Cf. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale, forth what is to come, the cascading triumph of life of which Percy Shel- ed. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage, 1968), §260: “we first make a thing painful by investing it with an evaluation. The extent of moral evaluations: they play a part in almost ley wrote. Nietzsche refers to self-overcoming as “the law of life the law every sense impression. Our world is colored by them.” of the necessary “self-overcoming” in the essence of life” (GM III §27). Self- 6Cf. WP §256: “I understand by “morality” a system of evaluation that partially coincides overcoming is essential and necessary for life because life is will to power, it with the conditions of a creature’s life.” 803 814 depression. Nietzsche links this to the historical effects of the ubiquity of the expense of difference, distance, and struggle (promoting death at the ex- Christianity and its life-denying desire for the “otherworldly.”7 pense of life, in other words).9 Luckily for us, morality is not a categorical Valuation, then, is a creative process – it prescribes and precludes the determination of reason; because it is a historical product of our lives, based possibilities and the relations open to our lives. Everything that is possible upon our valuations, there remains the possibility of transforming our lives is framed by a certain valuation which determines or delimits our reactions by transforming our values. But how would we do this? This is the proposal and our responses to these phenomena. As Nietzsche puts it, “there are no of Nietzsche’s ethics of the future – his future ethics, which
Recommended publications
  • PDF Download Nietzsche: Thus Spoke Zarathustra Ebook
    NIETZSCHE: THUS SPOKE ZARATHUSTRA PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Robert Pippin,Adrian Del Caro,Karl Ameriks,Desmond M. Clarke | 316 pages | 01 Aug 2006 | CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS | 9780521602617 | English | Cambridge, United Kingdom Thus Spoke Zarathustra: Study Guide | SparkNotes Zarathustra, however, turned sad, and said to his heart:. Long slept Zarathustra; and not only the rosy dawn passed over his head, but also the morning. At last, however, his eyes opened, and amazedly he gazed into the forest and the stillness, amazedly he gazed into himself. Then he arose quickly, like a seafarer who all at once sees the land; and he shouted for joy: for he saw a new truth. And he spoke thus to his heart:. The reduction of all psychology to physiology implies, to some, that human beings can be bred for cultural traits. This interpretation of Nietzsche's doctrine focuses more on the future of humanity than on a single cataclysmic individual. When I whispered into the ears of some people that they were better off looking for a Cesare Borgia than a Parsifal , they did not believe their ears. Several interpretations for this fact have been offered. Values involve a rank-ordering of things, and so are inseparable from approval and disapproval; yet it was dissatisfaction that prompted men to seek refuge in other-worldliness and embrace other-worldly values. Willing the eternal recurrence is presented as accepting the existence of the low while still recognizing it as the low, and thus as overcoming the spirit of gravity or asceticism. This action nearly kills Zarathustra, for example, and most human beings cannot avoid other-worldliness because they really are sick, not because of any choice they made.
    [Show full text]
  • Northrop Frye and Liberal Humanism
    Graham Good Northrop Frye and Liberal Humanism IMorthrop Frye was a lifelong liberal humanist. In 1988 he reiterated what he termed "my own confession of faith as a humanist, and my confidence in the value of what is called liberal education, a confidence that the social and political events contemporary with my seventy-five years of life have left totally unshaken." ' In the same paper he celebrated his political values: "I have remained a bourgeois liberal all my life because the serious ideals of democracy—personal liberty, free speech, equality of citizenship and tolerance of variety of opinion—are anti- doctrinaire ideals" (OE 3). This commitment to liberal humanism, which is consistent from the 1930s to the 1990s, has not attracted much attention in the secondary literature about Frye, though there are plenty of discus- sions of other aspects of his work. Yet liberal humanism is at the centre of his work, and, in fact, gives it its purpose. What accounts for the silence? Now that liberal humanism is no longer "current" in literary academia, Frye's advocacy of it is an embarrassment. Especially in Canada, but also elsewhere, there is still great respect for Frye's work, and perhaps this produces a desire to soften the obvious incompati- bility between it and post-structuralist theory by looking at its margins rather than its centre. To emphasize the liberal humanism would be to "date" Frye unkindly by tying him to the long-past heyday of such ideas. Frank Kermode recognized this "datedness" in a recent review: "Times have changed since, thirty years ago, the prophetic Frye was the height of fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzscheâ•Žs Death of God and the Slave-Revolt in Morality
    Winthrop University Digital Commons @ Winthrop University Showcase of Undergraduate Research and Creative Endeavors (SOURCE) SOURCE 2020 Apr 24th, 12:00 AM Nietzsche’s Death of God and the Slave-Revolt in Morality Ryan Haarer Winthrop University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.winthrop.edu/source Part of the Philosophy Commons Haarer, Ryan, "Nietzsche’s Death of God and the Slave-Revolt in Morality" (2020). Showcase of Undergraduate Research and Creative Endeavors (SOURCE). 104. https://digitalcommons.winthrop.edu/source/SOURCE_2020/allpresentationsandperformances/104 This Oral Presentation is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences and Events at Digital Commons @ Winthrop University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Showcase of Undergraduate Research and Creative Endeavors (SOURCE) by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Winthrop University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Ryan Haarer God’s Death and The Slave-Revolt in Morality PHIL-495 November 16th, 2019 2 ABSTRACT: None of Nietzsche’s theses stand out quite as much as his death of God thesis. An argument can be made that the death of God is the result of changes that the slave-revolt within morality bring about. Drawing on the observations that Nietzsche and scholars of Nietzsche have made regarding the equations made between the slaves and Christians, it is plausible that certain activities engaged in by the slaves and the Christians eventually lead to the disbelief, or death, in God. Primary focus of this essay will be given to the truth-seeking and the desire for progress that the slaves, or Christians, have.
    [Show full text]
  • The Case of Wagner, Nietzsche Contra Wagner, and Selected Aphorisms
    The Project Gutenberg EBook of The Case Of Wagner, Niet- zsche Contra Wagner, and Selected Aphorisms. by Friedrich Nietzsche. This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at http://www.guten- berg.org/license Title: The Case Of Wagner, Nietzsche Contra Wagner, and Selected Aphorisms. Author: Friedrich Nietzsche. Release Date: April 7, 2008 [Ebook 25012] Language: English ***START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE CASE OF WAGNER, NIETZSCHE CONTRA WAGNER, AND SELECTED APHORISMS.*** Friedrich Nietzsche I: The Case Of Wagner II: Nietzsche Contra Wagner III: Selected Aphorisms Translated By Anthony M. Ludovici Third Edition T. N. Foulis 13 & 15 Frederick Street Edinburgh and London 1911 Contents Translator's Preface. 2 Preface To The Third Edition . 7 The Case Of Wagner: A Musician's Problem . 16 Nietzsche contra Wagner . 57 Selected Aphorisms from Nietzsche's Retrospect of his Years of Friendship with Wagner. 79 Footnotes . 99 [ix] Translator's Preface. Nietzsche wrote the rough draft of “The Case of Wagner” in Turin, during the month of May 1888; he completed it in Sils Maria towards the end of June of the same year, and it was published in the following autumn. “Nietzsche contra Wagner” was written about the middle of December 1888; but, although it was printed and corrected before the New Year, it was not published until long afterwards owing to Nietzsche's complete breakdown in the first days of 1889.
    [Show full text]
  • Unmasking the Übermensch the Evolution of Nietzsche's Overman
    Unmasking the Übermensch The Evolution of Nietzsche’s Overman from David Bowie to Westworld _______________________________________________________________________ Siobhan Lyons Abstract Amongst Friedrich Nietzsche’s philosophical concepts – ‘god is dead’, eternal return – his concept of the Übermensch remains the most controversial and also the most debated, with various conflicting opinions on the precise nature (and intentions) of this enigmatic creature. More than a metaphorical concept, Nietzsche envisioned the possibility of such a transcendent figure, who existed beyond the conventional laws of good and evil and who would usher in a new system of values more befitting Nietzsche’s idealistic philosophy. Nietzsche would continually revisit the Übermensch throughout his work and revise its character, which would see the Übermensch evolve from an idealistic figure to a more tyrannical creature. Consequently, Nietzsche’s ambiguous treatment of the Übermensch inspired many dubious beliefs, from the Aryan ideal in Nazism to the perverse philosophy behind the infamous murders committed by Lewis and Loeb. Interpretations of the Nietzschean Übermensch can also be found frequently throughout popular culture, from the music of David Bowie to David Fincher’s Fight Club and the television series Westworld. While Bowie treated the Übermensch as a supernatural figure who abandoned the terrestrial world, the Übermensch was used to endorse underground philosophies predicated on violence in Fight Club, problematically linking the ideal of ‘self-overcoming’ with the oppression of others. A look at Westworld, however, reveals a far more nuanced understanding of the Übermensch’s potential as a figure who, while capable of tyranny, is able to channel their aggression in ways that push society in a new direction, forcing us to reconsider what transcendence truly entails.
    [Show full text]
  • Nietzsche on Convalescence
    NIETZSCHE ON CONVALESCENCE A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY EVREN SOYTOK IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN THE DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY SEPTEMBER 2019 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof. Dr. Yaşar Kondakçı Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Ş. Halil Turan Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Supervisor Examining Committee Members Prof. Dr. Ertuğrul R. Turan (Ankara Uni., DTCF) Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam (METU, PHIL) Assoc. Prof. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) PLAGIARISM PAGE I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name: Evren Soytok Signature: iii ABSTRACT NIETZSCHE ON CONVALESCENCE Soytok, Evren M.A., Department of Philosophy Supervisor: Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam September, 2019, 98 pages In this thesis, I will attempt to clarify Nietzsche’s notion of convalescence. To grasp his notion of convalescence requires a proper understanding and examination of his critique of traditional metaphysics that permeates his writings. In the context of his critique of metaphysical way of thinking, I will problematize the life-denying dualistic structure of metaphysics with its oppositional components and the Cartesian subject with respect to Nietzsche’s notion of life as will to power.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophy of the Antichrist in the Time of the Anthropocenic Multitude: Preliminary Lexicon for the Conceptual Network
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 2016 A Philosophy of the Antichrist in the Time of the Anthropocenic Multitude: Preliminary Lexicon for the Conceptual Network Gary Shapiro University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/philosophy-faculty- publications Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gary Shapiro, "A Philosophy of the Antichrist in the Time of the Anthropocenic Multitude: Preliminary Lexicon for the Conceptual Network," in The Digital Dionysus: Nietzsche and the Network-Centric Condition, ed. Dan Mellamphy and Nandita Biswas Mellamphy (Brooklyn, New York: Punctum Books, 2016), 82-94. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Philosophy of the Antichrist in the Time of the Anthropocenic Multitude: Preliminary Lexicon for the Conceptual Network Gary Shapiro NWW.IV, April 13, 2013 ANTICHRIST. Nietzsche's. not just being scary and shocking. He speaks of a "philosophy of the Antichrist" in one of the more explicitly political sections of Beyond Good and Evil, 1 in fact in a long concluding aphorism in §8, "Peoples and Fatherlands:' He reviews the mixed accomplishments of figures who helped to teach the nineteenth-century concept of "the higher human (Mensch)," including such diverse men as Napoleon, Wagner, Stendhal, and Heine. While all invented various forms of cul­ tural hybridity (cf iibernational), escaping the limits of nation­ alism, still all reverted to religion, and none "would have been capable of a philosophy of the Antichrist:' In the late preface to The Birth of Tragedy Nietzsche ventures to reveal the Anti­ christ's true name: Dionysus.
    [Show full text]
  • Digitalcommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) 1915 Nietzsche P. H. Frye University of Nebraska-Lincoln Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/midwestqtrly Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Frye, P. H., "Nietzsche" (1915). Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918). 46. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/midwestqtrly/46 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mid-West Quarterly, The (1913-1918) by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. Published in THE MID-WEST QUARTERLY 2:4 (July 1915), pp. 312-342. Published by G.P. Putnam’s Sons & the University of Nebraska. NIETZSCHE " Tad dem Schwachen" On account of the attention which Nietzsche has been attract­ ing of late, the occasion seems a favourable one for reviewing once more his life and work. In a letter to one of his acquaint­ ances, written in March, 1884, he himself prophesies with the proverbial modesty of genius that" in fifty years, perhaps, will the eyes of some few (or of one, for it requires genius) be opened to what has been done through me. For the present, however, it is not only difficult but quite impossible (in accordance with the laws of ' perspective ') to speak of me publicly without falling boundlessly short of the truth." To be sure, the time of which he spoke is not yet up; but since men's eyes are turned in that direction, it is fair to assume that the subject is not without interest at present.
    [Show full text]
  • Cornel West, “Frederic Jameson's Marxist
    Cornel West, “Frederic Jameson’s Marxist Hermeneutics,” boundary 2 11 (1) (1982), 177-200.* Fredric Jameson is the most challenging American Marxist hermeneutical thinker on the present scene. His ingenious interpretations (prior to accessible translations) of major figures of the Frankfurt School, Russian formalism, French structuralism and poststructuralism as well as of Georg Lukàcs, Jean-Paul Sartre, Louis Althusser, Max Weber and Louis Marin are significant contributions to the intellectual history of twentieth century Marxist and European thought. Jameson's treatments of the development of the novel, the Surrealist movement, of Continental writers such as Honoré de Balzac, Marcel Proust, Alessandro Manzoni, and Robbe Grillet, and of American writers, including Ernest Hemingway, Kenneth Burke and Ursula LeGuin, constitute powerful political readings. Furthermore, his adamantly anti-philosophical form of Marxist hermeneutics puts forward an American Aufhebung of poststructuralism which merits close scrutiny. In this essay I shall highlight Jameson's impressive intellectual achievements, specific theoretical flaws, and particular political shortcomings by focusing on the philosophical concerns and ideological aims in his trilogy.1 Jameson is first and foremost a loyal, though critical, disciple of * Note: I would like to extend my gratitude to Jonathan Arac, Stanley Aronowitz, Paul Bové, Fredric Jameson, David Langston, Michael Sprinker and Anders Stephanson for their incisive comments and criticisms of an earlier version of this essay.
    [Show full text]
  • University of Calgary Transvaluation of Architecture
    UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY TRANSVALUATION OF ARCHITECTURE: A PERSPECTIVE ON PERFORMATIVE VALUE IN ARCHITECTURE by KAMARAN ALI NOORI A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF ENVIRONMENTAL DESIGN IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ENVIRONMENTAL DESIGN THE FACULTY OF ENVIRONMENTAL DESIGN CALGARY, ALBERTA JANUARY 2011 © KAMARAN ALI NOORI 2011 Library and Archives Bibliotheque et 1*1 Canada Archives Canada Published Heritage Direction du Branch Patrimoine de I'edition 395 Wellington Street 395, rue Wellington OttawaONK1A0N4 Ottawa ON K1A 0N4 Canada Canada Your file Votre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-79656-6 Our file Notre reference ISBN: 978-0-494-79656-6 NOTICE: AVIS: The author has granted a non­ L'auteur a accorde une licence non exclusive exclusive license allowing Library and permettant a la Bibliotheque et Archives Archives Canada to reproduce, Canada de reproduce, publier, archiver, publish, archive, preserve, conserve, sauvegarder, conserver, transmettre au public communicate to the public by par telecommunication ou par I'lnternet, preter, telecommunication or on the Internet, distribuer et vendre des theses partout dans le loan, distribute and sell theses monde, a des fins commerciaies ou autres, sur worldwide, for commercial or non­ support microforme, papier, electronique et/ou commercial purposes, in microform, autres formats. paper, electronic and/or any other formats. The author retains copyright L'auteur conserve la propriete du droit d'auteur ownership and moral rights in this et des droits moraux qui protege cette these. Ni thesis. Neither the thesis nor la these ni des extraits substantiels de celle-ci substantial extracts from it may be ne doivent etre imprimes ou autrement printed or otherwise reproduced reproduits sans son autorisation.
    [Show full text]
  • Friedrich Nietzsche
    FRIED RICH NIETZSCHE F. C. COPLESTON, S.J., M.A. MANY people who have never read the works of Nietzsche possess some vague notion of what he taught. For them the philosophy of Nietzsche is represented by a few floating ideas—"Superman," "Will to Power," and even perhaps "blond beast." Others again have learnt a little more about Nietzsche and perhaps read some- thing of what he actually said; yet the net result is an impression of a passionate and destructive thinker, who launched his attacks on this side and on that, without any regard for consistency. For them there can be no philosophy of Nietzsche: they know that he often wrote in the form of aphorism and they picture his thought in general as a series of detached utterances, many of which are mutu- ally exclusive. It may then be of use to some, if we attempt to set forth the guiding inspiration and leading ideas of Nietzsche, for when these have been grasped, it will be seen that it is by no means absurd to speak of a philosophy of Nietzsche. It may well be impos- sible to reconcile all his utterances, at least so far as the words are concerned—though Nietzsche is of course not the only philosopher who betrays inconsistency in his thought—but it should be remem- bered that Nietzsche was not given to standing still: his thought developed. Moreover, he often spoke in an exaggerated form, so that some of the apparent inconsistencies may be ascribed to over- emphasis. In any case, even granting the presence of irreconcilable inconsistencies in his thought, Nietzsche's various theories not only may, but must, be seen as a whole, if they are seen in the light of his guiding ideas and inspiration.
    [Show full text]
  • Friedrich Nietzsche's Superman and Its Religious Implications
    Journal of Philosophy, Culture and Religion www.iiste.org ISSN 2422-8443 An International Peer-reviewed Journal Vol.45, 2019 Friedrich Nietzsche’s Superman and Its Religious Implications Anthony C. Ojimba (Ph.D) 1* Bruno Yammeluan Ikuli (Ph.D) 2 1.Department of Philosophy, University of Nigeria, Nsukka, Enugu State, Nigeria 2.Institute of Foundation Studies, Federal University, Otuoke, Bayalsa State, Nigeria Abstract This paper examines Nietzsche’s idea of the superman and its religious implications, with a view to showing that despite Nietzsche’s rejection of Christian religion and his attack on religious moral ideals, using his concept of the superman, Nietzsche fails in stripping humanity/man of his religious nature. Nietzsche’s superman represents the highest principle of the development of humanity and the affirmation of man’s full potentialities. He posits the superman as a critique on Christian religion and the crisis of modernity. This is because, according to him, the Christian morality stifles the development, freedom and creativity of humanity/man, as well as making him dependent on faith. Consequently, he advocates for the total rejection and abolition of the Christian moral ideals in order to make way for the freedom of humanity/man and consequently the emergence of super-humanity. Attempts are made to articulate Nietzsche’s concept of the superman and to highlight its link with his entire philosophic system. This will be examined critically, in each segment of the paper, to show its implications for religion. The paper employs the method of historical hermeneutics and textual analysis/exposition. Keywords: superman, religion, morality, reevaluation of values, Christianity, nihilism and modernity.
    [Show full text]