Human Fallibility and the Separation of Powers

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Human Fallibility and the Separation of Powers COMMENT HUMAN FALLIBILITY AND THE SEPARATION OF POWERS The limits of human knowledge is one of Hayek’s most enduring insights, writes Jonathan Crowe umans are fallible—and this fallibility of powers in modern administrative democracies is the hardest thing for us to grasp. and a plea for the importance of humility in public We have limited knowledge—and the life. The separation of powers is integral to modern limits of our knowledge routinely governance—but we can never take it for granted, Hprevent us from realising just how much we do because the very reasons that make it important not know. Our reasoning processes are vulnerable also explain why officials fail to honour it. to various forms of distortion and bias—and these distortions and biases often cause us to overlook Epistemological fallibility our own partiality. We are prone to favour familiar Humans have limited powers of knowledge and people and concepts over the unfamiliar—and deliberation. These limitations apply to all kinds of our lack of understanding of other viewpoints human decisions, but they are particularly acute at prevents us from realising the ways in which we the governmental level. Political actors must make marginalise them. We are susceptible to temptations decisions on a daily basis about what laws and that lead us to go against our conscience—and policies are best suited to organise the community. these temptations also provide incentives not to However, a human community scrutinise our behaviour. is a hugely complex institution. Humans are fallible, but the way our society It encompasses a large number is structured inevitably means that some humans of individuals with their own gain power to make decisions that impact on the diverse preferences and life plans. lives of others. Constitutional principles such as The short and long term plans of the rule of law and the separation of powers exist these individuals intersect in many to protect people from the flawed decisions of complex ways. These interactions, those in positions of power. However, the officials holding these positions routinely struggle to recognise their own fallibility. It is for this reason Jonathan Crowe is Professor of Law at Bond University. that the separation of powers—like other This is an edited version of his chapter in Rebecca constitutional limits—is continually under threat. Ananian-Welsh and Jonathan Crowe (eds), Judicial This article examines the various forms of Independence in Australia: Contemporary Challenges, human fallibility that underpin the separation Future Directions (The Federation Press, Sydney, 2016). of powers. It distinguishes epistemological, It is reproduced with permission of The Federation Press, which holds copyright. This new collection also includes psychological, ethical and moral fallibility and contributions from two scholars affiliated with CIS: examines how each of these human failings is Professor James Allan and Professor Suri Ratnapala. For exacerbated by political forces. It concludes with further information, see www.federationpress.com.au a reflection on the vulnerability of the separation 42 POLICY • Vol. 32 No. 2 • Winter 2016 JONATHAN CROWE in turn, are sensitive to a vast number and array of Psychological fallibility environmental influences. It is not only that humans face serious challenges The limitations on the ability of human actors in obtaining and analysing the information to effectively regulate a complex society play a necessary to organise a complex society. The central role in the constitutional theory of Friedrich decisions humans make based on the information A. Hayek.1 Hayek notes that human knowledge they have before them also tend to be distorted by about how to organise social institutions is subject various kinds of cognitive biases. One pervasive to severe and intractable limitations. This is partly form of bias concerns the human tendency to because humans have limited capacity to acquire, favour familiar people and concepts over unfamiliar store and process complex information. More ones. This gives rise to a range of psychological importantly, however, it is because of the complexity phenomena, such as in-group bias—the tendency and dynamism of human relations. The task of to treat people you know more favourably than designing social institutions involves coordinating strangers—and confirmation bias—the tendency a diverse collection of human actors, each with to prefer pre-existing ideas and concepts to rival their own intricate sets of nested preferences. hypotheses. The process of identifying and aggregating these preferences is therefore deeply complex. A further challenge is posed by the dynamism Hayek’s response to the limitations of of social arrangements. Individual preferences are human knowledge places heavy emphasis constantly changing and these changes influence on constitutional values such as the the ways people interact with social institutions. separation of powers and the rule of law. Hayek, of course, does not wish to deny that we can make some headway in studying and predicting the patterns of social organisation. Economics Some of the most influential contemporary and the other social sciences have developed work in moral psychology—such as the sophisticated methodologies for this purpose. experimental studies conducted by Jonathan Haidt However, Hayek—a celebrated economist and and Daniel Kahneman—utilises what are known social scientist himself—wishes to sound a note of as dual process models of cognition. Dual process caution about such efforts. A comprehensive and models see cognition as involving two types of accurate picture of social workings is beyond the processes: one kind involves fast, intuitive snap abilities of even the greatest economists—let alone judgments, while the other involves self-conscious, your average parliamentarian. reflective deliberation.3 Many decisions we make in Hayek’s response to the limitations of human our lives are initially based on snap judgments that knowledge places heavy emphasis on constitutional may or may not be tempered by more deliberate values such as the separation of powers and the reflection. These snap judgments are not arbitrary, rule of law. Human attempts to organise society but are frequently based on rough rules of thumb run a serious risk of unintended or perverse or heuristics that enable us to deal with complex consequences. Hayek is therefore highly critical situations in a manageable way. However, these of what he terms constructivist rationality: the idea heuristics, while indispensable to cognition, can that all worthwhile human institutions can and also undermine the integrity of our decisions.4 should be planned by human reason.2 He argues The dual process model reinforces the likelihood that the best way to shield people from these kinds of distortions such as in-group preference and of errors of judgment is through a stable set of confirmation bias finding their way into political general rules placing limits on the exercise of decisions. These kinds of biases are likely to shape government power. The separation of powers people’s political affiliations and reinforce them facilitates this by imposing internal checks and over time.5 This helps to explain why politicians balances on the decisions of government officials. often seem to be motivated more by party loyalty POLICY • Vol. 32 No. 2 • Winter 2016 43 HUMAN FALLIBILITY AND THE SEPARATION OF POWERS than by an interest in openly debating specific very idea of ethics, for Singer, involves adopting a policy issues: they have a strong cognitive bias ‘universal point of view’, according to which ‘my towards agreeing with members of their political own interests cannot, simply because they are my in-group and endorsing ideas with which they are interests, count more than the interests of anyone familiar. Moral psychologists have noted the role else.’9 Singer recognises, however, that humans of other cognitive biases, such as loss aversion and typically find it difficult to make impartial decisions overestimating the probability of unlikely events, between their own self-interest and the interests in shaping political choices.6 of others. Some philosophers have regarded the Related issues also arise concerning judicial natural partiality of humans as a challenge to the reasoning. The research in moral psychology I have very idea of ethical duties. Friedrich Nietzsche, for been discussing suggests that judicial decisions, like example, claims that humans naturally ‘feel toward other kinds of reasoning processes, will depend [other people] almost as free and irresponsible as significantly upon pre-reflective snap judgments.7 toward plants and stones. That the other suffersmust A recent study on parole decisions by Israeli judges be learned; and it can never be learned completely.’10 suggests that even seemingly trivial factors like Nietzsche’s comments reflect a very pessimistic the length of time since the judges’ last meal can view of the human capacity for compassion that significantly affect their decisions.8 The cognitive is not shared by many other philosophers. There biases affecting government officials therefore is no doubt, however, that the human tendency strengthen the case for avoiding concentrations towards self-interest and partiality represents a deep of power and making decisions subject to review. seated challenge for ethical and political thought. The separation of powers responds to this issue The answer is not to give up on ethics entirely, but by ensuring that no one person or group has a rather to tread carefully when distributing social monopoly on the exercise of government authority. power, so as not to give a monopoly to particular social interests. The institutions of constitutional government—including the separation of powers— The human tendency towards self-interest represent one attempt to recognise human and partiality represents a deep seated partiality in the design of political institutions. challenge for ethical and political thought. It is because humans tend to prefer sameness to difference and privilege the self over the other that the power of each branch of government must be Ethical fallibility kept in check.
Recommended publications
  • GCLP Newsletter Issue 4 October 2019
    ISSUE 4 OCTOBER 2019 (FOR THE PERIOD AUGUST 2018 - SEPTEMBER 2019) GCLP NEWSLETTER Message from the Co-Directors Professor Jonathan Crowe Associate Professor Danielle Ireland-Piper The year 2019 saw the Global and Comparative Law and Policy (GCLP) Network launch its first ‘social and legal change’ event under the leadership of Professor Jona- than Crowe. Three prominent survivors of sexual violence—Nina Funnell, Bri Lee and Saxon Mullins—shared their experiences with the legal system in a panel discussion Contact us: c/o Faculty of held at Bond University. The panellists reflected upon the challenges they encountered Law, Bond University, 14 in their cases and made suggestions for reform. University Drive, Robina QLD The GCLP also hosted a number of other events, including a guest lecture providing 4226 comparative perspectives on free speech, a seminar on global constitutionalism, and, Twitter: @GCLP_Network thanks to Assistant Professor Narelle Bedford, a NAIDOC Week event. The GCLP was further delighted to serve as co-host to the Chief Justice of the High Court of Australia, E: [email protected] or the Hon. Susan Kiefel AC. The Chief Justice delivered the 2109 Sir Gerard Brennan [email protected] lecture with her address ’How common is the common law? A historical and compara- Find us online: tive perspective’. The lecture was well-attended, including by the profession, staff, and bond.edu.au/gclp students. The research activities of many GCLP members caught the attention of the media, and a number also contributed ‘impact’ pieces, such as to The Conversation. GCLP members continue to contribute quality publications and several interesting comparative and international projects are underway.
    [Show full text]
  • Existentialism, Liberty and the Ethical Foundations of Law
    EXISTENTIALISM, LIBERTY AND THE ETHICAL FOUNDATIONS OF LAW JONATHAN GEORGE CROWE BA (Hons), LLB (Hons) Qld A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy T. C. Beirne School of Law Department of Philosophy, School of History, Philosophy, Religion and Classics The University of Queensland March 2006 DECLARATION BY THE CANDIDATE I DECLARE THAT the work presented in this thesis is, to the best of my knowledge and belief, original and my own work, except as acknowledged in the text, AND THAT the material has not been submitted, either in whole or in part, for a degree at this or any other university. _________________________________ JONATHAN GEORGE CROWE ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS In completing an extended academic work, one invariably incurs substantial intellectual and personal debts. My intellectual debts, for the most part, appear sufficiently in the body of the thesis; I wish to focus here on the personal ones. Some debts, however, straddle the intellectual and the personal. My two academic advisors, Suri Ratnapala and Julian Lamont, fall into this category. I have benefited greatly from their patient and insightful comments. Perhaps even more importantly, I have profited from their examples of how to conduct oneself with integrity, openness and passion as a researcher, teacher and colleague. Many staff members at the University of Queensland have gone out of their ways to make me feel welcome in both the Law School and the Philosophy Department. I am grateful to them. I would also like to acknowledge the collegiality and support of my fellow doctoral candidates, particularly Pierre-Jean Bordahandy, Elizabeth Dickson, Lisa Toohey and David Willis.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defence of Roach V Electoral Commissioner I
    2019 The Narrative Model of Constitutional Implications 91 THE NARRATIVE MODEL OF CONSTITUTIONAL IMPLICATIONS: A DEFENCE OF ROACH V ELECTORAL COMMISSIONER JONATHAN CROWE* The role of implications in Australian constitutional law has long been debated. Jeffrey Goldsworthy has argued in a series of influential publications that legitimate constitutional implications must be derived in some way from authorial intentions. I call this the intentionalist model of constitutional implications. The intentionalist model has yielded a sceptical response to several recent High Court decisions, including the ruling in Roach v Electoral Commissioner that the Constitution enshrines an implied conditional guarantee of universal franchise. This article outlines an alternative way of thinking about constitutional implications, which I call the narrative model. I argue that at least some constitutional implications are best understood as arising from historically extended narratives about the relationship of the constitutional text to wider social practices and institutions. The article begins by discussing the limitations of the intentionalist model. It then considers the role of descriptive and normative implications in both factual and fictional narratives, before applying this analysis to the Australian Constitution. I argue that the narrative model offers a plausible basis for the High Court’s reasoning in Roach v Electoral Commissioner. I INTRODUCTION Constitutional implications have been controversial in Australia at least since Justice Isaacs railed against them in Amalgamated Society of Engineers v Adelaide Steamship Co Ltd.1 The controversy has been sustained by the role of implications in pivotal High Court decisions such as Australian Communist Party v Commonwealth and Melbourne Corporation v Commonwealth.2 It arguably * Professor of Law, Bond University.
    [Show full text]
  • Contributors
    Contributors THE EDITORS Jonathan Crowe is Professor of Law at Bond University. His research explores the rela- tionship between law and ethics at both theoretical and applied levels. His most recent book, Natural Law and the Nature of Law (CUP, 2019), provides a systematic defence of natural law ideas in ethics, politics and jurisprudence. Constance Youngwon Lee is a Lecturer in Law at Central Queensland University and a PhD Candidate in Law at the University of Queensland. Her PhD thesis, entitled John Calvin’s Constitutional Theology, examines the implications of Calvin’s natural law theory for consti- tutional law and governance. THE AUTHORS Amalia Amaya is Research Professor in the Institute for Philosophical Research, National Autonomous University of Mexico. Nicholas Aroney is Professor of Constitutional Law at the University of Queensland. Jonathan Burnside is Professor of Biblical Law at the University of Bristol. Catherine Carol is a PhD Candidate in Philosophy at the University of Queensland. Eoin Carolan is Professor of Law at University College Dublin. Gary Chartier is Distinguished Professor of Law and Business Ethics at La Sierra University. Michael Detmold is Emeritus Professor of Law at the University of Adelaide. Richard J. Dougherty is an Associate Professor of Politics at the University of Dallas. George Duke is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at Deakin University. Jere L. Fox is an Associate Professor of Law and Management at La Sierra University. Norman P. Ho is an Associate Professor of Law at the Peking University School of Transnational Law. Nadirsyah Hosen is a Senior Lecturer in Law at Monash University.
    [Show full text]
  • Legal Obligation and Social Norms
    Jonathan Crowe* and Lucy Agnew** LEGAL OBLIGATION AND SOCIAL NORMS ABSTRACT HLA Hart famously argues that legal obligation is best understood by analysing law as a species of social rule. This article engages with recent work in social psychology and norm theory to critically evaluate Hart’s theory. We draw on the social intuitionist model of practical decision- making associated with Amos Tversky, Daniel Kahneman and Jonathan Haidt to argue that legal officials rely on holistic intuitive judgements to identify their legal obligations. We then explain the evolution and persistence of legal rules by reference to the theory of social norms offered by Cristina Bicchieri. This way of thinking about legal obligation lends support to Hart’s account of law as a social practice. However, it challenges other aspects of his views, such as the idea that the only necessary factor in determining the content of law is its socially recognised sources. It also casts doubt on Hart’s claim that legal obligation does not empirically extend beyond legal officials to other members of the community. Hart’s account can be adapted to meet these criticisms, but not without under- mining its commitment to legal positivism. I INTRODUCTION egal philosophy today is dominated, for better or worse,1 by legal positivism — the view that the only necessary factor in determining whether something Lcounts as law is recognition by social sources.2 A distinction is often drawn in * Professor of Law, Bond University. ** Graduate Lawyer, RBG Lawyers. The authors would like to thank the anonymous reviewers for their detailed and helpful comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Jurisprudence As Practical Reason: a Celebration of the Collected Essays of John Finnis
    Margaret White AO* JURISPRUDENCE AS PRACTICAL REASON: A CELEBRATION OF THE COLLECTED ESSAYS OF JOHN FINNIS EDITED BY MARK SAYERS AND ALADIN RAHEMTULA SUPREME COURT LIBRARY, 2013 122 PP ISBN 978 0 9872471 4 8 ohn Finnis attended Oxford University (University College) as a Rhodes Scholar for South Australia from 1962 to 1965 where his doctoral thesis supervisor was JH L A Hart whose highly influential The Concept of Law had been published the previous year.1 Finnis’ thesis topic was an examination of judicial power with particular reference to Australian federal constitutional law. Finnis taught briefly in other institutions including at University of California, Berkeley, and later as Head of Law at the University of Malawi on secondment from Oxford from 1976 to 1978. But he was, essentially, an Oxford man. He progressed from law tutor at University College from 1966 to Rhodes Reader in the Laws of the British Commonwealth and the United States from 1972 to 1989 and was elected Professor of Law and Legal Philosophy in 1989, holding that chair until his recent retirement. In 2011 Oxford University honoured Finnis with a five volume collection of selected essays and other of his papers covering 50 years in both academic and public forums. The Supreme Court of Queensland has marked this important event with a small volume of essays and recollections, edited by Mark Sayers, a legal philosopher and barrister in practice in Queensland and Aladin Rahemtula OAM, former Queensland Supreme Court Librarian, deep thinker and long-time admirer of Finnis’ work. The editors hope that this celebration will rekindle a more systemic interest in legal philosophy in this country and a recognition of the usefulness of natural law thinking in the resolution of the big and difficult questions, such as end-of-life decisions, abortion and same-sex marriage.
    [Show full text]
  • Nov/Dec Newsletter 2017
    ASPIRATIONS & INSPIRATIONS Law Research Newsletter November-December 2017 Conferences/Seminars On 18 December 2017, Professor William van Caenegem and participants from around the world gathered at the Australian Embassy in Paris for the second Interna- tional Comparative Colloquium on IP and Fashion: from Creator to Consumer. Partici- pants included representatives of the fashion design world, such as the IP Rights En- forcement Manager of Hermes International, the Director of Jewellery Design of Car- tier, and the former Legal Director, IP and Brand Protection, of Tommy Hilfiger and LVMH. The discussions were centred around the design of IP rules for the purpose of sup- porting creative fashion brands in the differing conditions of a number of jurisdictions. A number of comparative articles have now been published around this topic, co- authored by William van Caenegem, Violet Atkinson, Viv Azard and Julien Canlorbe. The importance of the Colloquium was highlighted in the opening address by Brenden Berne (Australian ambassador to France), who noted the impending FTA negotiations between the EU and Australia and deepening economic ties with France. A further colloquium or conference will be held this year. From L-R, Catherine Palmer - Principal Legal Counsel - Joseph, United Kingdom, Violet Atkinson – Bond University and Cronin Litigation, Australia, Jean-Claude Masson – IP Rights Enforcement Manager, Hermes International, Associate Pro- fessor Eleonora Rosati – University of Southampton and Attorney, Italy , Chair: Viviane Azard – Attorney,
    [Show full text]
  • Downloaded from Elgar Online at 10/02/2021 10:54:28AM Via Free Access Viii Research Handbook on Natural Law Theory
    Contributors THE EDITORS Jonathan Crowe is Professor of Law at Bond University. His research explores the rela- tionship between law and ethics at both theoretical and applied levels. His most recent book, Natural Law and the Nature of Law (CUP, 2019), provides a systematic defence of natural law ideas in ethics, politics and jurisprudence. Constance Youngwon Lee is a Lecturer in Law at Central Queensland University and a PhD Candidate in Law at the University of Queensland. Her PhD thesis, entitled John Calvin’s Constitutional Theology, examines the implications of Calvin’s natural law theory for consti- tutional law and governance. THE AUTHORS Amalia Amaya is Research Professor in the Institute for Philosophical Research, National Autonomous University of Mexico. Nicholas Aroney is Professor of Constitutional Law at the University of Queensland. Jonathan Burnside is Professor of Biblical Law at the University of Bristol. Catherine Carol is a PhD Candidate in Philosophy at the University of Queensland. Eoin Carolan is Professor of Law at University College Dublin. Gary Chartier is Distinguished Professor of Law and Business Ethics at La Sierra University. Michael Detmold is Emeritus Professor of Law at the University of Adelaide. Richard J. Dougherty is an Associate Professor of Politics at the University of Dallas. George Duke is an Associate Professor of Philosophy at Deakin University. Jere L. Fox is an Associate Professor of Law and Management at La Sierra University. Norman P. Ho is an Associate Professor of Law at the Peking University School of Transnational Law. Nadirsyah Hosen is a Senior Lecturer in Law at Monash University.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law Anarchism
    STUDIES IN EMERGENT ORDER VOL 7 (2014): 288-298 Natural Law Anarchism Jonathan Crowe* Gary Chartier’s book, Anarchy and Legal Order (2013), makes a significant contribution to four distinct, albeit overlapping fields: natural law theory, libertarian and anarchist theory, philosophy of law and political philosophy. It builds on Chartier’s previous work in a series of books and articles exploring issues in natural law, anarchism and economic justice.1 The book is unconventional not only in defending market anarchism from a leftist perspective, but also for doing so within a natural law ethical framework. As a natural law theorist with market anarchist leanings, I am more sympathetic than many readers will be to Chartier’s project. However, the unconventional nature of the arguments is part of the work’s appeal. Chartier’s book uses the resources of the natural law tradition in ethics to defend a vision of law without the state. It therefore presents a theory of what might be termed natural law anarchism. Some readers may find this combination of views surprising. The most prominent contemporary defender of natural law ideas, John Finnis, heavily emphasizes the role of state institutions (1980).2 However, Finnis’s theory arguably gives a misleading picture of the relationship between natural law and the state. Natural law theory is, in fact, highly hospitable to anarchism. I wish to begin by drawing this out, since it helps put Chartier’s project in context. I will then look in more detail at some features of Chartier’s account. Natural Law and the State The natural law tradition in ethics, politics and jurisprudence is highly diverse.
    [Show full text]
  • The Internet and Ethical Values Been Much More Successful
    © Dong Wenjie/Getty Images © Dong Wenjie/Getty CHAPTER 1 The Internet and Ethical Values Many decades have passed since the first communications were trans- mitted over a fledgling global network, which would later be called the internet. At the time, few would have predicted the internet’s explosive growth and persistent encroachment on our personal and professional lives. For techno-optimists, the emancipatory promise of this technical infrastructure is still unfolding. As the internet matures it has become a more personal experience, thanks to the fusion of smartphones and social networks. Retrieving the latest news, an online search with Goo- gle’s help, listening to music, watching a YouTube video, and checking one’s Newsfeed on Facebook are just some of the activities done countless times each day with the help of apps and mobile devices.1 Some sovereignties, however, have felt threatened by this decen- tralized power and information egalitarianism. As a result, they have attempted to extend their power over this anarchic network and its information flows. However, the control of networked technologies through law and regulation has often been a futile effort. Technical infrastructures that expedite the flow of information can easily become a means for obstructing or excluding information. The regime of law has had a hard time suppressing the dissemination of pornography on the internet, but software systems that filter out indecent material have 1 © Jones & Bartlett Learning LLC, an Ascend Learning Company. NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION. 2 Chapter 1 The Internet and Ethical Values been much more successful. This reality reflects technology’s paradox- ical nature—it not only endows individuals with the capacity to more fully exercise their rights (such as free speech), but it also makes possi- ble the development of tools that can undermine those rights.
    [Show full text]
  • Explaining Natural Rights: Ontological Freedom and the Foundations of Political Discourse
    EXPLAINING NATURAL RIGHTS: ONTOLOGICAL FREEDOM AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF POLITICAL DISCOURSE Jonathan Crowe* Introduction.............................................................................................71 I. The Explanatory Question..............................................................73 A. Nozick’s Theory of Rights .......................................................75 B. Ontological Freedom................................................................78 C. Sartre on Ontology and Politics..............................................81 II. The Analytical Question .................................................................85 A. Three Types of Rights ..............................................................86 B. Negative and Positive Freedom..............................................93 III. The Normative Question ................................................................98 A. Freedom, Value and Choice ..................................................100 B. Diversity and Exclusion.........................................................105 IV. Conclusion ......................................................................................110 * Senior Lecturer and Fellow, Centre for Public, International and Comparative Law, T. C. Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland. I would like to thank Tom Campbell, Maurice Goldsmith, Julian Lamont, Suri Ratnapala and Lisa Toohey for their helpful comments and suggestions. An earlier version of this article was pre- sented as part of the faculty seminar
    [Show full text]
  • Jonathan Crowe
    Jonathan Crowe Faculty of Law Phone: +61 7 3955 1291 Bond University Email: [email protected] Gold Coast, Queensland 4229 Papers: bond.academia.edu/JonathanCrowe Australia Appointments Professor, Faculty of Law, Bond University, 2016-present Associate Professor, T. C. Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland, 2012-16 Senior Lecturer, T. C. Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland, 2008-12 Visiting Scholar, Philosophy Department, Georgetown University, January-June 2010 Lecturer, T. C. Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland, 2005-08 Tutor, T. C. Beirne School of Law, University of Queensland, 2002-04 Tutor, Philosophy Department, University of Queensland, 2002 Education PhD, Law and Philosophy, University of Queensland, 2006 Thesis: Existentialism, Liberty and the Ethical Foundations of Law Examiners: John Gardner (Professor of Jurisprudence, University of Oxford and Visiting Professor, Yale Law School) and Tom Campbell (Professorial Fellow, Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics, Charles Sturt University) Dean’s Commendation for Outstanding Research Higher Degree Thesis, Graduate School, University of Queensland LLB with Honours Class IIA, University of Queensland, 2002 BA with Honours Class I in Philosophy, University of Queensland, 2000 Publications Books 1. Jonathan Crowe, Natural Law and the Nature of Law, complete manuscript currently under re- view by Cambridge University Press 2. Rebecca Ananian-Welsh and Jonathan Crowe (eds), Judicial Independence in Australia: Contem- porary Challenges, Future Directions (Federation Press, 2016) (in press) 3. Jonathan Crowe, Legal Theory (Thomson Reuters, 2nd ed., 2014) Jonathan Crowe 2 4. Jonathan Crowe and Kylie Weston-Scheuber, Principles of International Humanitarian Law (Ed- ward Elgar, 2013) Marco Sassóli, University of Geneva: ’This is a concise and nuanced overview of International Humanitarian Law (IHL).
    [Show full text]