A Posteriori Deductions Dynamical Conception of Matter And, 126

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Posteriori Deductions Dynamical Conception of Matter And, 126 Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76618-0 - Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays Edited By Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser Index More information INDEX a posteriori deductions An Account of Sir Isaac Newton’s dynamical conception of matter and, Philosophical Discoveries 126–128 (MacLaurin), 300–301, 308–317 geometrical conception of matter Acta eruditorum (Leibniz), 39 and, 116–119, 134–136 action at a distance, 192–194, 347–348 aprioriassumption active force, Leibniz’s concept of, 40–41 causation and, 270–279 air resistance, laws of motion and, 171, Locke’s discussion of nature and, 366 265–266 alchemy, Newton’s interest in, 3nn7–8, spacetime theory and, 197 107–111 absolute motion d’Alembert,J.L.R.,109, 192, 195, 282, definitions of, 199 285n15, 378–379 DiSalle’s discussion of, 215–217 algebra dispositional account of mass and, as analysis, 223–224 329–331 curves expressed in, 225–226 Newton’s concept of, 196–218 Algebra (Kinckhuysen), 226 Scholium discussion of, 206–215 Analogies of Experience, Kant’s space-time theories and, development of, 355 200–206 analysis. See also theoretical analysis absolute rest influence of Principia on, 361–364, absolute motion and, 209–215 366–371 Euler’s theories on time and space Newton’s discussion of, 224–229, and, 173–175 250–253 absolute rotation, 204–206 terminology and definitions of, absolute space 221–224 Kant’s discussion of, 342–359 Analysis per Quantitatum, Series, Newton’s definition of, 200–206, Fluxiones, ac differentias cum 208–209, 211–215, 347–359 Enumeratio Linearum Tertii absolute velocities, Newtonian Ordinis (Newton), 8 space-time theory and, 202–206 Anstey, P. R., 57–58, 58n18 abstract quantity, fluxions theory and, apogee, mean motion of, 377–383 224 approximations acceleration Newton’s research and, 394n22 centripetal force and, 372–377 successive approximation, 100 force and, 163–167 area rule of Kepler, 156–158, 160–162 universal law of gravitation and, planetary bodies and, 162, 164, 162–167 179n20, 364–366 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76618-0 - Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays Edited By Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser Index More information 420 index areas for curves, Cartesian Bacon, Francis, 57–59, 59n21, 62n27 co-ordinates, 220–221 Barber,K.F.,16n10, 17n11 argument for universal gravitation Barrow, Isaac, 8 (AUG). See universal gravitation composition of motion theory, Aristotle 236–239, 238n26–27, 239n29, analysis methods of, 221–226 245, 247 causation and, 85 on De Analysis, 224–229 Locke’s discussion of, 52–53 Geometrical lectures of, 236 metaphysics of, 320–321 geometrical objects defined by, model of science and mathematics, 71–77 70, 74–77, 77n17, 80, 82 justification of postulates by, 77–82 on motion, 213, 249 on mathematics as science, 70–71 teleology of, 345–346 on mechanics in geometry, 83–85 unities of form and matter of, 39 on nature and mathematics, 69–101 astronomy physical significance of mathematics influence of Principia on, 360–364, and, 96–97 393–395 on postulates as practice of natural philosophy and, 61–68, mechanics, 97–100 61n26, 65n31 Bayesian theory, models and Newton’s discussion of, 65n31, hypotheses in, 91n41 67–68 Bayle, Pierre, 310 simultaneity theory in, 368 Belkind, Ori, 6, 138–168, 210–211 atheism, 350 Bennett, Jonathan, 24–25 atomism, Newton’s discussion of, Bentley, Richard, 3, 87n32, 130n24, 29n30 285, 286n17, 291, 347–348 attraction Berkeley, George, 304–305, 308, 333 force proportional to mass, 175 Bernoulli, Johann, 40 hypotheses concerning, 139–146, Biener, Zvi, 6–7, 105–137 177–183 Blancanus, Josephus, 72n4, 75n11, Kant’s discussion of, 342, 355–356 77n17 lunar precession and, 193–194 Blay, Michel, 3n6 as matter property, 280–298 Bloch, Leon,´ 3n6 Maupertuis’s defense of, 286–298 bodies in motion motion and, 85–89, 88n34 bodies plural, Cartesian concept of, postulates of mathematical/physical 14n5 distinction, 89–91 “body in general,” Cartesian concept s’Gravesande’s defense of Newton’s of, 14–16, 14n4 theories concerning, 283–286 Boyle’s dispositional theory and, structural assumptions and, 320–326 146–156 closed systems of interacting bodies, third law of motion and, 121–124, 183–185 175–185 Descartes’s discussion of, 13–20, attraction-at-a-distance, Locke’s 16–17 concept of, 64–65 dispositional account of mass and, AUG (argument for universal 327–331 gravitation). See universal dynamical conception of matter and, gravitation 111–116 Axioms of Intuition, 353n17 Euler’s theories on time and space Ayers, Michael, 266n21, 284n14 and, 173–175 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76618-0 - Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays Edited By Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser Index More information index 421 geometrical conception of matter Cambridge Companion to Newton, and, 116–119 3n9 gravity and, 128–130 Cambridge Platonism, 343, 357n25 Huygens’s rules for, 169–170, Carnap, Rudolf, 204–205 188–190 Cartesian co-ordinates Leibniz on force and, 33–41 areas for curves and, 220–221 Locke’s discussion of, 263–269 polynomial equations and, 234–236 mechanical aether principle, quadrature rules and, 226 107–111 Cassini, G. D., 191, 393n20 natural philosophy and role of, Cauchy, A.-L., 116n13 57–62, 85 causation Newtonian space-time principles deductive reasoning and, 140–146 and, 203n9 discrepancy as measurement and, Newton’s account of, 7, 13–32, 91–97 24n21 force and, 96n50 Newton’s divine phenomenalism Hume’s Newtonian ideal of, and, 335–338 269–279 Newton’s laws and force of, 42–47 Kant’s discussion of, 354–355 “problem of bodies” principle, mathematical/physical distinction 16–32 and, 85–89 proportionalities and, 130–136 mathematics and, 71–77 quantity of motion and, 151–156 Maupertuis’s discussion of, 287–288 solid bodies, Descartes’s discussion metaphysics of space and, 349–359 of, 18n12, 28–29 postulates of mathematical/physical space and, 111n9 distinction, 89–91 third law of motion and, 121–124 Cavendish, H., 194, 206n12, 363 Bonneau, Franc¸ois de (Sieur de Celestial Mechanics (Laplace), 361, Verdus), 239–241 394n23 bootstrap confirmation, laws of celestial mechanics, Newton’s influence motion and, 179n20 on, 382–383 Boscovichian point-particles, 116, 136 centrifugal force, Newtonian Boulliau, Ismael,¨ 364 space-time and, 206 Boyle, Robert centripetal force on bodies in motion, 7, 262 Area Law of Kepler and, 156–158 dispositional theory of, 320–326 Cotes’s commentaries on, 119–121 Locke and, 263 gravitation and, 142, 143n12 natural philosophy and work of, inverse-square measurements and, 49–51, 57–68, 58nn18–19, 59n21, 369–371 59n23, 60nn24–25, 62n27, 66n32 planetary bodies and, 179n20 Newtonian and Humean approaches chemistry, Newton’s legacy and history to problems of, 332–335 of, 2 Brading, Katherine, 7, 13–32 Child, J. M., 236, 238n26 Brahe, Tycho, 391 Christensen, David, 179n20 Brown, Harvey, 197 Clairaut, A. C., 192, 378–383, 391–392 bucket argument Clarke, Samuel, 109, 213, 285–286, 291 absolute vs. relative motion and, co-linearity, Newtonian space-time 207–208, 214–217 theory and, 202–206 Newtonian space-time and, 204–206 Cogitata physico mathematica Burtt, E. A., 2 (Mersenne), 240n34 © in this web service Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-76618-0 - Interpreting Newton: Critical Essays Edited By Andrew Janiak and Eric Schliesser Index More information 422 index Cohen, I. B. Corollary VI, 203n9, 216 on discrepancy as measurement, corpuscular hypothesis 92n42, 93n43 Boyle’s dispositional theory and, on dynamical conception of matter, 320–326 125 Newton’s concept of mass and, on force and motion theory, 326–331 44–47 Cotes, Roger, 6, 105–107 on Newton’s definitions, on attraction, 295n37, 297n41 198n2 on dynamical conception and status on Newton’s theories, 2–5 of laws, 124–128 Collins, John, 224–227, 239–240n34 on gravity as essential property, collisions 128–130, 276n29, 357n23 Huygens’s rules concerning, “invisible hand” commentaries of, 169–170, 188–190 119–130, 136–137 third law of motion concerning, Newton’s Challenge and, 307–308 146–147, 152–156, 171, on proportionalities, 130–136 178–183 third law critiqued by, 175–185 color, Boyle’s dispositional theory on third law of motion, 121–124 concerning, 320–326 critical philosophy, Kant and evolution common cause principle, of, 352–359 demonstrative induction and, Critique of Pure Reason (Kant), 144n14 300–301, 350n14 composition of motions. See rule of curves composition in De Methodis, 245, 247–251 of Barrow, 236–239 method of tangents and, 240–247 cycloids, 240–243 perihelion of Mercury and, 384–389 in De Methodis, 245, 250–253 squaring of, 225–226 ellipse and, 243, 245 Van Heuraet’s theorem and, 232, general law for, 243–248 235–236 quadratrix, composition of motion Cutting-off of a Ratio (Apollonius), for, 243, 245 222n5 speeds and, 253 cycloid, composition of motions for, spirals and, 243–245 240–243 theory of, 229 universal gravitation and, 155–156, data, evidence and, 361–364 161–162, 167–168 De Analysis per Aequationes Numero “Confesio naturae contra atheistas” Terminorum Infinitas (Newton), (Leibniz), 34 222, 224–229 conservation, of momentum, 150–151, “De Arcanis Motus et Mechanica ad 154–156, 158, 166–167 puramGeometriamreducenda” constant ratio, speeds of motions and, (Leibniz), 36n11 239n30 De Corpore (Hobbes), 34 continuum mechanics, Newtonian de Gandt, Franc¸ois, 3n6 theory and, 116 De Gravitatione et Aequipondio Copernicus, N., 361–362 Fluidorum (Newton), 4,
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy of Science -----Paulk
    PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE -----PAULK. FEYERABEND----- However, it has also a quite decisive role in building the new science and in defending new theories against their well-entrenched predecessors. For example, this philosophy plays a most important part in the arguments about the Copernican system, in the development of optics, and in the Philosophy ofScience: A Subject with construction of a new and non-Aristotelian dynamics. Almost every work of Galileo is a mixture of philosophical, mathematical, and physical prin~ a Great Past ciples which collaborate intimately without giving the impression of in­ coherence. This is the heroic time of the scientific philosophy. The new philosophy is not content just to mirror a science that develops independ­ ently of it; nor is it so distant as to deal just with alternative philosophies. It plays an essential role in building up the new science that was to replace 1. While it should be possible, in a free society, to introduce, to ex­ the earlier doctrines.1 pound, to make propaganda for any subject, however absurd and however 3. Now it is interesting to see how this active and critical philosophy is immoral, to publish books and articles, to give lectures on any topic, it gradually replaced by a more conservative creed, how the new creed gener­ must also be possible to examine what is being expounded by reference, ates technical problems of its own which are in no way related to specific not to the internal standards of the subject (which may be but the method scientific problems (Hurne), and how there arises a special subject that according to which a particular madness is being pursued), but to stan­ codifies science without acting back on it (Kant).
    [Show full text]
  • The Experimental Verdict on Spacetime from Gravity Probe B
    The Experimental Verdict on Spacetime from Gravity Probe B James Overduin Abstract Concepts of space and time have been closely connected with matter since the time of the ancient Greeks. The history of these ideas is briefly reviewed, focusing on the debate between “absolute” and “relational” views of space and time and their influence on Einstein’s theory of general relativity, as formulated in the language of four-dimensional spacetime by Minkowski in 1908. After a brief detour through Minkowski’s modern-day legacy in higher dimensions, an overview is given of the current experimental status of general relativity. Gravity Probe B is the first test of this theory to focus on spin, and the first to produce direct and unambiguous detections of the geodetic effect (warped spacetime tugs on a spin- ning gyroscope) and the frame-dragging effect (the spinning earth pulls spacetime around with it). These effects have important implications for astrophysics, cosmol- ogy and the origin of inertia. Philosophically, they might also be viewed as tests of the propositions that spacetime acts on matter (geodetic effect) and that matter acts back on spacetime (frame-dragging effect). 1 Space and Time Before Minkowski The Stoic philosopher Zeno of Elea, author of Zeno’s paradoxes (c. 490-430 BCE), is said to have held that space and time were unreal since they could neither act nor be acted upon by matter [1]. This is perhaps the earliest version of the relational view of space and time, a view whose philosophical fortunes have waxed and waned with the centuries, but which has exercised enormous influence on physics.
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Spacetime Structure
    Classical Spacetime Structure James Owen Weatherall Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science University of California, Irvine Abstract I discuss several issues related to \classical" spacetime structure. I review Galilean, Newto- nian, and Leibnizian spacetimes, and briefly describe more recent developments. The target audience is undergraduates and early graduate students in philosophy; the presentation avoids mathematical formalism as much as possible. 1. Introduction One often associates spacetime|a four-dimensional geometrical structure representing both space and time|with relativity theory, developed by Einstein and others in the early part of the twentieth century.1 But soon after relativity theory appeared, several authors, such as Hermann Weyl (1952 [1918]), Elie´ Cartan (1923, 1924), and Kurt Friedrichs (1927), began to study how the spatio-temporal structure presupposed by classical, i.e., Newtonian, physics could be re-cast using the methods of four-dimensional geometry developed in the context of relativity. These reformulations of classical physics were initially of interest for the insight they offered into the structure of relativity theory.2 But this changed in 1967, when Howard Stein proposed that the notion of a \classical" spacetime could provide important insight arXiv:1707.05887v1 [physics.hist-ph] 18 Jul 2017 Email address: [email protected] (James Owen Weatherall) 1The idea of \spacetime" was actually introduced by Minkowski (2013 [1911]), several years after Einstein first introduced relativity theory. 2And indeed, they remain of interest for this reason: see, for instance, Friedman (1983), Malament (1986a,b, 2012), Earman (1989b), Fletcher (2014), Barrett (2015), Weatherall (2011a,b, 2014, 2017d,c), and Dewar and Weatherall (2017) for philosophical discussions of the relationship between relativity theory and Newtonian physics that make heavy use of this formalism.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Spacetime Is Probably a Substance Author(S): Tim Maudlin Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol
    Buckets of Water and Waves of Space: Why Spacetime Is Probably a Substance Author(s): Tim Maudlin Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 60, No. 2 (Jun., 1993), pp. 183-203 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/188350 . Accessed: 28/12/2012 20:13 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded on Fri, 28 Dec 2012 20:13:44 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Philosophy of Science June, 1993 BUCKETS OF WATER AND WAVES OF SPACE: WHY SPACETIME IS PROBABLY A SUBSTANCE* TIM MAUDLINtt Department of Philosophy Rutgers University This paper sketches a taxonomy of forms of substantivalism and relationism concerning space and time, and of the traditional arguments for these positions. Several natural sorts of relationism are able to account for Newton's bucket experiment. Conversely, appropriately constructed substantivalism can survive Leibniz's critique, a fact which has been obscured by the conflation of two of Leibniz's arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Physics/0409010V1 [Physics.Gen-Ph] 1 Sep 2004 Ri Ihteclsilshr Sntfound
    Physical Interpretations of Relativity Theory Conference IX London, Imperial College, September, 2004 ............... Mach’s Principle II by James G. Gilson∗ School of Mathematical Sciences Queen Mary College University of London October 29, 2018 Abstract 1 Introduction The question of the validity or otherwise of Mach’s The meaning and significance of Mach’s Principle Principle[5] has been with us for almost a century and and its dependence on ideas about relativistic rotat- has been vigorously analysed and discussed for all of ing frame theory and the celestial sphere is explained that time and is, up to date, still not resolved. One and discussed. Two new relativistic rotation trans- contentious issue is, does general[7] relativity theory formations are introduced by using a linear simula- imply that Mach’s Principle is operative in that theo- tion for the rotating disc situation. The accepted retical structure or does it not? A deduction[4] from formula for centrifugal acceleration in general rela- general relativity that the classical Newtonian cen- tivity is then analysed with the use of one of these trifugal acceleration formula should be modified by transformations. It is shown that for this general rel- an additional relativistic γ2(v) factor, see equations ativity formula to be valid throughout all space-time (2.11) and (2.27), will help us in the analysis of that there has to be everywhere a local standard of ab- question. Here I shall attempt to throw some light solutely zero rotation. It is then concluded that the on the nature and technical basis of the collection of field off all possible space-time null geodesics or pho- arXiv:physics/0409010v1 [physics.gen-ph] 1 Sep 2004 technical and philosophical problems generated from ton paths unify the absolute local non-rotation stan- Mach’s Principle and give some suggestions about dard throughout space-time.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1704.03334V1 [Physics.Gen-Ph] 8 Apr 2017 Oin Ffltsaeadtime
    WHAT DO WE KNOW ABOUT THE GEOMETRY OF SPACE? B. E. EICHINGER Department of Chemistry, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington 98195-1700 Abstract. The belief that three dimensional space is infinite and flat in the absence of matter is a canon of physics that has been in place since the time of Newton. The assumption that space is flat at infinity has guided several modern physical theories. But what do we actually know to support this belief? A simple argument, called the ”Telescope Principle”, asserts that all that we can know about space is bounded by observations. Physical theories are best when they can be verified by observations, and that should also apply to the geometry of space. The Telescope Principle is simple to state, but it leads to very interesting insights into relativity and Yang-Mills theory via projective equivalences of their respective spaces. 1. Newton and the Euclidean Background Newton asserted the existence of an Absolute Space which is infinite, three dimensional, and Euclidean.[1] This is a remarkable statement. How could Newton know anything about the nature of space at infinity? Obviously, he could not know what space is like at infinity, so what motivated this assertion (apart from Newton’s desire to make space the sensorium of an infinite God)? Perhaps it was that the geometric tools available to him at the time were restricted to the principles of Euclidean plane geometry and its extension to three dimensions, in which infinite space is inferred from the parallel postulate. Given these limited mathematical resources, there was really no other choice than Euclid for a description of the geometry of space within which to formulate a theory of motion of material bodies.
    [Show full text]
  • 6 Space Substantivalism and Relationism Newton's Argument For
    6 Space Substantivalism and relationism abstract entities vs concrete entities. regions is commonly thought to be concrete but that isn’t in the category of material objects. realists would say regions or space do exist. Anti-realists about space would say, regions are an unnecessary addition. God creating the universe The realist about regions thinks that God has first to make an enormous container – the regions – in order to put the objects in. The anti-realist thinks that all God has to do to make the universe is make a bunch of objects, and then arrange them in a certain way. Those who are realists about regions are called substantivalists, whilst those who are anti- realists about regions are often called relationists. Newton’s argument for absolute space Dirction + Speed = velocity # Velocity + acceleration = innertial forces Newton’s bucket Newton’s argument for substantivalism – if velocity has to be relative to something, and acceleration is a change in velocity, then acceleration has to be relative to something as well. But, says Newton, it’s possible for one object to accelerate even though there’s no object that the acceleration could be relative to. But, as it must be relative to something, it must be relative to something that was not an object: it must be relative to space itself; ergo, space must exist. Stage 1: The rope is twisted but has not been let loose. The bucket and the water are at rest with respect to one another. Stage 2: The rope has been let loose and the bucket has started to rotate.
    [Show full text]
  • General Relativity and Spatial Flows: I
    1 GENERAL RELATIVITY AND SPATIAL FLOWS: I. ABSOLUTE RELATIVISTIC DYNAMICS* Tom Martin Gravity Research Institute Boulder, Colorado 80306-1258 [email protected] Abstract Two complementary and equally important approaches to relativistic physics are explained. One is the standard approach, and the other is based on a study of the flows of an underlying physical substratum. Previous results concerning the substratum flow approach are reviewed, expanded, and more closely related to the formalism of General Relativity. An absolute relativistic dynamics is derived in which energy and momentum take on absolute significance with respect to the substratum. Possible new effects on satellites are described. 1. Introduction There are two fundamentally different ways to approach relativistic physics. The first approach, which was Einstein's way [1], and which is the standard way it has been practiced in modern times, recognizes the measurement reality of the impossibility of detecting the absolute translational motion of physical systems through the underlying physical substratum and the measurement reality of the limitations imposed by the finite speed of light with respect to clock synchronization procedures. The second approach, which was Lorentz's way [2] (at least for Special Relativity), recognizes the conceptual superiority of retaining the physical substratum as an important element of the physical theory and of using conceptually useful frames of reference for the understanding of underlying physical principles. Whether one does relativistic physics the Einsteinian way or the Lorentzian way really depends on one's motives. The Einsteinian approach is primarily concerned with * http://xxx.lanl.gov/ftp/gr-qc/papers/0006/0006029.pdf 2 being able to carry out practical space-time experiments and to relate the results of these experiments among variously moving observers in as efficient and uncomplicated manner as possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1007.1861V1 [Gr-Qc] 12 Jul 2010 Feulms N Hp.Temaueeto Uhagravito-Mag a Such of Measurement 10 the Is Shape
    A laser gyroscope system to detect the Gravito-Magnetic effect on Earth A. Di Virgilio∗ INFN Sez. di Pisa, Pisa, Italy K. U. Schreiber and A. Gebauer† Technische Universitaet Muenchen, Forschungseinrichtung Satellitengeodaesie Fundamentalstation Wettzell, 93444 Bad K¨otzting, Germany J-P. R. Wells‡ Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Canterbury, PB4800, Christchurch 8020, New Zealand A. Tartaglia§ Polit. of Torino and INFN, Torino, Italy J. Belfi and N. Beverini¶ Univ. of Pisa and CNISM, Pisa, Italy A.Ortolan∗∗ Laboratori Nazionali di Legnaro, INFN Legnaro (Padova), Italy Large scale square ring laser gyros with a length of four meters on each side are approaching a sensitivity of 1 10−11rad/s/√Hz. This is about the regime required to measure the gravito- magnetic effect (Lense× Thirring) of the Earth. For an ensemble of linearly independent gyros each measurement signal depends upon the orientation of each single axis gyro with respect to the rotational axis of the Earth. Therefore at least 3 gyros are necessary to reconstruct the complete angular orientation of the apparatus. In general, the setup consists of several laser gyroscopes (we would prefer more than 3 for sufficient redundancy), rigidly referenced to each other. Adding more gyros for one plane of observation provides a cross-check against intra-system biases and furthermore has the advantage of improving the signal to noise ratio by the square root of the number of gyros. In this paper we analyze a system of two pairs of identical gyros (twins) with a slightly different orientation with respect to the Earth axis. The twin gyro configuration has several interesting properties.
    [Show full text]
  • An Essay on the Coriolis Force
    James F. Price Woods Hole Oceanographic Institution Woods Hole, Massachusetts, 02543 http:// www.whoi.edu/science/PO/people/jprice [email protected] Version 3.3 January 10, 2006 Summary: An Earth-attached and thus rotating reference frame is almost always used for the analysis of geophysical flows. The equation of motion transformed into a steadily rotating reference frame includes two terms that involve the rotation vector; a centrifugal term and a Coriolis term. In the special case of an Earth-attached reference frame, the centrifugal term is exactly canceled by gravitational mass attraction and drops out of the equation of motion. When we solve for the acceleration seen from an Earth-attached frame, the Coriolis term is interpreted as a force. The rotating frame perspective gives up the properties of global momentum conservation and invariance to Galilean transformation. Nevertheless, it leads to a greatly simplified analysis of geophysical flows since only the comparatively small relative velocity, i.e., winds and currents, need be considered. The Coriolis force has a simple mathematical form, 2˝ V 0M , where ˝ is Earth’s rotation vector, V 0 is the velocity observed from the rotating frame and M is the particle mass. The Coriolis force is perpendicular to the velocity and can do no work. It tends to cause a deflection of velocity, and gives rise to two important modes of motion: (1) If the Coriolis force is the only force acting on a moving particle, then the velocity vector of the particle will be continually deflected and rotate clockwise in the northern hemisphere and anticlockwise in the southern hemisphere.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton Vs. Leibniz: Intransparency Vs. Inconsistency
    Newton vs. Leibniz: Intransparency vs. Inconsistency Karin Verelst Vrije Universiteit Brussel1 [email protected] The only way to avoid becoming a metaphysician is to say nothing E.A. Burtt Abstract Introduction The early modern debates on the nature of space enjoy a renewed interest in the recent philosophical literature. Focal points of the discussion are the opposition between the “absolute” vs. the “relational ” conception of space and the related issue of its presumed substantival nature. Quintessential formulations of the key positions in the debate remain the viewpoints attributed to Newton and Leib- niz. But scholarly disagreement concerning them remains stark. Especially with respect to Newton the defended interpretations range from anti-metaphysical readings (based on the notorious “I do not feign hypotheses”) to at first glance almost theological readings that have him speculate about the relation between God and world. Leibniz, on the other hand, is presented as Newton’s counter- part, who sets out tackling mechanical problems with an a priori metaphysical scheme — inherited from Descartes — already laid out in his mind. But Newton arXiv:1203.2292v1 [physics.hist-ph] 10 Mar 2012 clearly conceived of himself as a natural philosopher [52, p. 2], while Leibniz, certainly in his earlier years, would have insisted on his use of strictly mechanical concepts only [10, Introduction]. We believe that, in order to be able to judge on the “metaphysical degree” of the positions taken by our protagonists, we should understand more clearly what metaphysics itself is about. This question is often ignored. We shall show 1FUND-CLEA, Dept. of Mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Space, Time and Einstein
    Space, Time and Einstein Space, Time and Einstein An Introduction J. B. Kennedy © J. B. Kennedy 2003 This book is copyright under the Berne Convention. No reproduction without permission. All rights reserved. First published in 2003 by Acumen Acumen Publishing Limited 15A Lewins Yard East Street Chesham HP5 1HQ www.acumenpublishing.co.uk ISBN: 1-902683-66-8 (hardcover) ISBN: 1-902683-67-6 (paperback) British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library. Designed and typeset by Kate Williams, Abergavenny. Printed and bound by Biddles Ltd., Guildford and King’s Lynn. For Carole and John Crascall Contents Preface and acknowledgements ix Part I: Einstein’s revolution 1 1 From Aristotle to Hiroshima 3 2 Einstein in a nutshell 7 3 The twin paradox 31 4 How to build an atomic bomb 40 5 The four-dimensional universe 50 6 Time travel is possible 66 7 Can the mind understand the world? 71 Part II: Philosophical progress 75 8 Who invented space? 77 9 Zeno’s paradoxes: is motion impossible? 92 10 Philosophers at war: Newton vs. Leibniz 104 11 The philosophy of left and right 126 12 The unreality of time 133 13 General relativity: is space curved? 139 14 The fall of geometry: is mathematics certain? 149 15 The resurrection of absolutes 159 16 The resilience of space 172 vii SPACE, TIME AND EINSTEIN Part III: Frontiers 175 17 Faster than light: was Einstein wrong? 177 18 The Big Bang: how did the universe begin? 185 19 Black holes: trapdoors to nowhere 188 20 Why haven’t aliens come visiting? 193 21 The inflationary and accelerating universe 197 22 Should we believe the physicists? 202 Appendix A: Spacetime diagrams 207 Appendix B: Symmetry and Lorentz’s minority interpretation 222 Appendix C: Simple formulas for special relativity 225 Appendix D: Websites 227 Appendix E: Guide to further reading 229 Index 239 viii Preface and acknowledgements The ongoing revolution in our understanding of space and time is so central to the drama of our times that no educated person can remain ignorant of it.
    [Show full text]