Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Covert Modality in Non-Finite Contexts Covert modality in non-finite contexts By Rajesh Bhatt Reviewed by Anastasia Giannakidou Summary by the author We also discuss a case that is the inverse of the environments in (1): an environment where there is a modal word in the structure but not in the interpret- 1. Issues ation (cf. 2). This dissertation investigates the distribution and interpretation of Covert Modality. Covert Modality is (2) (from Thalberg, 1969) modality which we interpret but which is not asso- a. In those days, Brown was able to hit bulls-eyes ciated with any lexical item in the structure that we three times in a row. (modal) are interpreting. This dissertation investigates a class b. Brown was able to hit three bulls-eyes in a row. of environments that involve covert modality. Exam- (context: Yesterday, Brown hit three bulls-eyes ples of covert modality include wh-infinitival comple- in a row. Before he hit three bulls-eyes, he fired ments, infinitival relative clauses, purpose clauses, the 600 rounds, without coming close to the bulls- have to construction, and the is to construction (cf. 1): eye; and his subsequent tries were equally wild.) (non-modal) (1) a. Tim knows [how to solve the problem]. (¼ Tim knows how one/he could/should solve This environment is interesting for the same reason as the problem) the environments in (1) – it involves a non-trivial b. Jane found [a book to draw cartoons in] for mapping between the structure and interpretation. Sara. How is it possible that (2a) is modal when (2b) is non- (¼ Jane found a book for Sara one could/ modal (and vice-versa)? Our analysis of this environ- should draw cartoons in) ment (in Chapter 5) will analyze the difference c. [The man to fix the sink] is here. between (2a) and (2b) in terms of a covert modal, (¼ The man whose purpose is to fix the sink is which is identified as a generic operator. Crosslin- here. guistic evidence is provided for this proposal by d. Sue went to Torino [to buy a violin]. showing that in languages where the perfective/ (¼ Sue went to Torino so that she could buy a imperfective distinction reflects the absence/presence violin.) of genericity, the modal reading is available only in e. Bill has to reach Philadelphia before noon. the presence of imperfective aspect. In the presence of (¼ Bill must reach Philadelphia before noon.) perfective aspect, the ability modal behaves like an f. Will is to leave tomorrow. implicative verb (e.g. Bulgarian, Catalan, Hindi, (¼ Will is scheduled/supposed to leave Modern Greek etc.). tomorrow.) The interpretation of (1a–f) involves modality; how- 2. Dissertation Outline and Summary ever, there is no lexical item that seems to be the source of the modality. What (1a–f) have in common 2.1. Chapter 2: The syntax of infinitival relatives is that they involve infinitivals. Of the environments The goal of this chapter is to determine what kinds of in (1a–f), we will investigate infinitival relatives and structures best represent different kinds of infinitival infinitival questions in this dissertation. (The have to relative clauses. We begin with a discussion of the construction is discussed in Bhatt, 1997.) The follow- syntactic properties of different kinds of infinitival ing questions about covert modality are addressed: relative clauses. We argue that subject infinitival what is the source of this modality, what are its relatives (e.g. the man to fix the sink) differ structurally semantic properties, why are some but not all infin- from non-subject infinitival relatives (e.g. the book to itival relatives modal, and why are all infinitival questions modal? Rajesh Bhatt, Department of Linguistics, University of Texas, Austin, 78712, USA, [email protected] Title of the dissertation: Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Author: Rajesh Bhatt. Degree date: 1999. Institution: University Anastasia Giannakidou, Department of Linguistics, University th of Pennsylvania. Supervisors: S. Iatridou, A. Kroch. 196pp. of Chicago, 1010 E. 59 Street, Chicago, IL 60637, USA, Available from www.ircs.upenn.edu [email protected] Glot International Vol. 7, No. 1/2, January/February 2003 (52–59) 52 Ó Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2003, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden MA 02148, USA Dissertations Glot International, Volume 7, Number 1/2, January/February 2003 53 read). Subject infinitival relatives, but not object infinitival relatives. The force of the covert modality in infinitival relatives, share the following properties of object infinitival relatives seems to depend upon the reduced relatives: (i) the relativized element is always determiner – the book to read vs. a book to read (cf. Hackl in subject position, (ii) the subject position does not & Nissenbaum 1999). The modality in subject infin- receive case, (iii) the relativization is very local- only itival relatives does not seem to display such a the matrix subject can be relativized, (iv) the clausal dependency – the man to fix the sink vs. a man to fix structure that functions as a reduced relative can the sink. appear as the complement of predicative be (cf. Embick 1997; Iatridou, Anagnostopoulou & Izvorski, 2000), (v) no complementizer is permitted, and (vi) no 2.2. Chapter 3: Non-modal infinitival relative clauses relative pronoun is permitted. Subject infinitival The infinitival clause in a subject infinitival relative relatives are therefore assimilated with reduced can also be interpreted non-modally in certain relative clauses while non-subject infinitival relatives environments. The precise characterization of such are assimilated with non-reduced relative clauses. A environments and the properties of such infinitival structure is proposed for reduced relative clauses that clauses are discussed in this chapter. The syntactic captures the properties of reduced relative clauses in proposal in Chapter 2 is able to explain why only general and subject infinitival relatives in particular. subject infinitival relatives can be non-modal. How- This structure differs from the structure proposed for ever, the non-modal interpretation is only available full relative clauses in that it does not involve a CP in the presence of a particular set of modifiers. This projection and A’-movement to the specifier of a CP class of modifiers is identified as consisting of super- for predicate-formation. It has the advantage that we latives, ordinals, and nominal only cf. ???*the/every/no do not have to postulate A’-movement of an operator man to walk on the moon vs. the first/tallest/only man to from a non-case marked position. walk on the moon (cf. Kjellmer 1975; Pesetsky and Non-subject infinitival relative clauses are analyzed Torrego, 1999). The infinitival clause that receives a as full relative clauses. They involve a CP projection non-modal interpretation is required to be licensed and movement of a relative operator to the specifier of locally at LF. We argue that the appropriate licensing this CP. Infinitival questions and non-subject infiniti- configuration is made available under reconstruction val relative clauses thus have essentially the same of the head NP into its relative clause-internal posi- syntax which involves A’-movement of a phrase to tion. The reconstruction option is available to us if we the specifier of a [+rel/wh] C0. Infinitival [+rel/wh] assume a version of the head-raising analysis of C0 is identified as the locus of the modality that relative clauses. Nominal modifiers like superlatives appears in non-subject infinitival relatives and infin- and ordinals are able to reconstruct back into the itival questions. Since infinitival questions and non- relative clause along with the noun phrase. This option subject relative clauses must involve the infinitival is not available to determiners, and this is why [+rel/wh] C0 and the infinitival [+rel/wh] C0 has determiners like the/every/no are unable to license the modal semantics, all infinitival questions and non- non-modal reading. subject relatives involve modality. Similarities in the The licensing configuration proposed requires that behavior of the modality in non-subject infinitival in addition to the relative clause-internal interpret- relatives and infinitival questions are captured by ation of the head NP, the licensing element (the assigning the same semantics to [+rel] C0 and [+wh] superlative -est, ordinals, nominal only etc.) move C0. The details of the semantics of the infinitival [+rel/ from its NP-internal position to a position where it wh] C^0 are discussed in Chapter 4. takes the infinitival clause as an argument. With the Some but not all subject infinitival relatives are licensing configuration in hand, we are able to explain interpreted as modal (cf. the modal the man to fix the why both nominal first/last and relative clause-inter- sink vs. the non-modal the first man to walk on the nal adverbial first/last are able to license a non-modal moon). Our proposal that subject infinitival relatives reading (cf. the first/last man to read that book vs. the man do not involve the modally interpreted infinitival to read that book first/last). This is so because at LF, [+rel] C0 is compatible with the fact that not all subject which is the point at which the licensing configuration infinitival relatives are modal. We relate the modality applies, nominal first/last and the relative clause- in the modal subject infinitival relatives to a modality internal adverbial first/last are in the same (relative that can independently appear in the infinitival clause-internal) position. clause. Thus the modality in the subject infinitival Further evidence is provided for the possibility of relative the book to be read for class has the same source reconstructed interpretations of nominal modifiers in as the modality in The book is to be read for class.
Recommended publications
  • Participial Relative Clauses
    UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Participial Relative Clauses Sleeman, P. DOI 10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.185 Publication date 2017 Document Version Other version Published in Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Sleeman, P. (2017). Participial Relative Clauses. In M. Aronoff (Ed.), Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics [185] (Oxford Research Encyclopedias). Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.185 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) Download date:01 Oct 2021 Participial relative clauses Petra Sleeman Sleeman, P. Mar 2017, Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics. Aronoff, M. (ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press, (Oxford Research Encyclopedias). Summary Relative clauses of which the predicate contains a present, past or passive participle can be used in a reduced form.
    [Show full text]
  • Relative Clauses in Mandarin Chinese
    Relative Clauses in Mandarin Chinese Huiying Wen Queen Mary, University of London July 2020 Abstract This thesis is an investigation of the nature and theoretical analyses of the syntax of relative constructions in Mandarin Chinese, with a focus on adjunct relative con- structions and \gapless" relative constructions. In contrast to the traditional views, I propose that deriving these relative constructions requires a head raising strategy and show that this can give a better explanation of their properties and their interaction with comparatives deletion. I argue against the idea that adjunct relative constructions involve null opera- tor movement and defend a novel head raising approach using data from PP-in-situ adjunct relatives. With this in hand, I examine the syntactic analysis of gapless relatives, arguing that gapless relatives are true relatives as opposed to noun com- plements, and show that gapless relatives can be classified into two types: adjunct gapless relatives and resultative gapless relatives, depending on the semantic status of their head nouns. The former involves a manner-kind head noun which is the complement of a PP adjunct. The latter involves a result-kind head noun which is the complement of a null VP. Further, I extend this alternative approach to analyse comparative deletion in relative constructions. Queen Mary's OPAL #46 Occasional Papers Advancing Linguistics 1 Acknowledgements First, I would like to say a big thank you to my supervisor, Prof. David Adger. His immense knowledge and great passion for linguistics have inspired and encouraged me in all the time of syntactic research I spend at QMUL.
    [Show full text]
  • Processing Relative Clauses Varying on Syntactic and Semantic Dimensions: an Analysis with Event-Related Potentials
    Memory & Cognition 1995,23 (4), 477-494 Processing relative clauses varying on syntactic and semantic dimensions: An analysis with event-related potentials A. MECKLINGER Max-Planck-Institutefor Cognitive Neuroscience, Leipzig, Germany H. SCHRIEFERS The Nijmegen Institute for Cognition and Information, Nijmegen, The Netherlands and K. STEINHAUERand A. D. FRIEDERICI Max-Planck-Institute for Cognitive Neuroscience, Leipzig, Germany Event-related potentials were used to study how parsing of German relative clauses is influenced by semantic information, Subjects read well-formed sentences containing either a subject or an ob­ ject relative clause and answered questions concerning the thematic roles expressed in those sen­ tences. Half of the sentences contained past participles that on grounds of semantic plausibility bi­ ased either a subject or an object relative reading; the other half contained past participles that provided no semantic information favoring either reading. The past participle elicited an N400 com­ ponent, larger in amplitude for neutral than for semantically biased verbs, but this occurred only in the case of subject relative clauses. More specific effects were obtained only for a subgroup of sub­ jects, when these were grouped into fast and slow comprehenders on the basis of their question­ answering reaction times. Fast comprehenders showed larger N400 amplitudes for neutral than for semantically biased past participles in general and larger N400s for the latter when there was a bias for an object relative reading as opposed to a subject relative reading. Syntactic ambiguity resolu­ tion, indicated by an auxiliary in sentence final position, was associated in this subgroup with a pos­ itive component (P345), larger in amplitude for auxiliaries indicating an object relative reading than for those indicating a subjectrelative reading.
    [Show full text]
  • The Korean Internally-Headed Relative Clause Construction: Its Morphological, Syntactic and Semantic Aspects
    The Korean Internally-Headed Relative Clause Construction: Its Morphological, Syntactic and Semantic Aspects Item Type text; Electronic Dissertation Authors Lee, Jeongrae Publisher The University of Arizona. Rights Copyright © is held by the author. Digital access to this material is made possible by the University Libraries, University of Arizona. Further transmission, reproduction or presentation (such as public display or performance) of protected items is prohibited except with permission of the author. Download date 28/09/2021 06:40:45 Link to Item http://hdl.handle.net/10150/193783 THE KOREAN INTERNALLY-HEADED RELATIVE CLAUSE CONSTRUCTION: ITS MORPHOLOGICAL, SYNTACTIC AND SEMANTIC ASPECTS by Jeongrae Lee ________________________ Copyright © Jeongrae Lee 2006 A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF LINGUISTICS In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2006 2 THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA GRADUATE COLLEGE As members of the Dissertation Committee, we certify that we have read the dissertation prepared by Jeongrae Lee entitled The Korean Internally-headed Relative Clause Construction: Its Morphological, Syntactic and Semantic Aspects and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy ________________________________________________________Date: July 13, 2006 Heidi B. Harley ________________________________________________________Date: July 13, 2006 Simin Karimi ________________________________________________________Date: July 13. 2006 Andrew Barss ________________________________________________________Date: July 13, 2006 Rudolph C. Troike Final approval and acceptance of this dissertation is contingent upon the candidate’s submission of the final copies of the dissertation to the Graduate College. I hereby certify that I have read this dissertation prepared under my direction and recommend that it be accepted as fulfilling the dissertation requirement.
    [Show full text]
  • Past Participle Relative Clause
    Past Participle Relative Clause Unillustrated Isa amplify that architecture concedes egoistically and recess attractively. Richie disorientate her talk ajar, uninviting and self-glazed. Giovanni halogenated queasily. What is fused with our products, i have anything to appear in colloquial arabic we crossed a theory of science is nominative or present perfect simple past participle When an example that is this discussion between this is more! Can only forum has been fermented in. Relative comprehension do or perhaps see me of roles does not only way to vary depending on. Provide a relative clause is used that. That required to ensure you navigate through europe were covered in place at or past participle adjectives? Can work exclusively with past, please recommend content is: a verb in accordance with commas is beaming with past participle relative clause sometimes wonder whether, a commitment to nouns? Building and relative. May remain in our free grammar are passive participle forms if they started on their range of san francisco. The golden gate bridge, without adding an equivalent. And they allow us in a list of times, as adverbial phrase modifies a tricky affair after a central to put anything else even if necessary are? Context effects involving these, past participle relative clause is to contain a past indicative present analyses of view from a gesture of basic functionalities and multimedia. The relative clauses and not allowed due solely be viewed this is even though it contains factual errors and between reduced relatives could stand in a shorter railing. Although they all day tefl certificate and relative.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Complex Constructions: a Quantitative Corpus-Linguistic Approach to the Processing of English Relative Clauses
    Understanding complex sentences Understanding Complex Constructions: A Quantitative Corpus-Linguistic Approach to the Processing of English Relative Clauses Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) vorgelegt dem Rat der Philosophischen Fakultät der Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena von Daniel Wiechmann, MA geboren am 27.11.1974 in Itzehoe 1 A quantitative corpus-linguistic approach to the processing of English relative clauses Gutachter 1. Prof. Dr. Holger Diessel (FSU Jena) 2. Prof. Dr. Volker Gast (FSU Jena) 3. Prof. Dr. Anatol Stefanowitsch (Universität Bremen) Tag der mündlichen Prüfing: 9.4.2010 2 Understanding complex sentences TABLE OF CONTENTS 1 Introduction ...................................................................................................................... 5 1.1 Aims of this study ....................................................................................................... 5 1.1.1 Why relative clause constructions? .................................................................... 12 1.1.2 Characterizing English relative clause constructions ........................................ 15 1.2 Overture: Some precursors and some prerequisites .................................................. 36 1.2.1 Symbolization and mental states ........................................................................ 36 1.2.2 Linguistic units as processing instructions I: form to meaning ......................... 39 1.2.3 Linguistic units as processing instructions II: form
    [Show full text]
  • Amharic Relatives and Possessives: Definiteness, Agreement and the Linker
    Amharic relatives and possessives: Definiteness, agreement and the linker Marcel den Dikken — Linguistics Program — CUNY Graduate Center — [email protected] Ouhalla’s (2004) valuable discussion of relativized and possessed noun phrases in Amharic leaves a number of questions open. Foremost among these is the placement of the linker element yä-. Starting out from an analysis of relative clauses and possessors as predicates of their ‘heads’, this paper develops a syntax of complex noun phrases in Amharic that explains the raison d’être and placement of yä-, and in addition accommodates a variety of facts about definiteness marking and agreement in the Amharic complex noun phrase that have hitherto largely escaped attention or analysis. The analysis emphasizes the role of Predicate Inversion and head movement in syntax, and confirms and extends the minimalist Agree- and phase-based approach to syntactic relationships. Keywords: Agree, relative clause, possessor, Predicate Inversion, linker, phase, head movement, definiteness, gender agreement, Amharic 1 Introduction* Ouhalla (2004) presents an interesting perspective on the syntax of Semitic relativized and possessed noun phrases. The central ingredients of his analysis are that relative clauses originate the same DP–internal speci- fier positions that possessors are also base-generated in, and that relative clauses vary parametrically with respect to whether they are introduced by a C–head, as in English or Hebrew, or instead by a D–head, as Ouhalla argues is the case in Arabic and Amharic, the foci of his paper. Arabic and Amharic differ in that, in the latter, the relative clause’s TP raises to SpecDP, thus delivering a word order in which the D–head of the relative clause surfaces in final position.
    [Show full text]
  • Cinque (2010) Treats Prenominal Adjectives in Languages Like Bosnian
    194 SQUIBS AND DISCUSSION LONG-FORM AND SHORT-FORM Cinque (2010) treats prenominal adjectives in languages like Bosnian/ PRENOMINAL ADJECTIVES ARE Croatian/Serbian (BCS) and English either as APs in the specifiers NOT REDUCED RELATIVE of functional projections in the extended domain of N (direct modifica- CLAUSES IN BOSNIAN/ tion) or as predicates in reduced relative clauses in the specifiers of CROATIAN/SERBIAN functional projections (indirect modification), while postnominal ad- Aida Talic´ jectives in these languages are treated only as predicates in reduced University of Connecticut relative clauses. In this model, the direct-modification source is associ- ated with one set of interpretations and the indirect-modification source with a different set of interpretations. This proposed dual-source analy- sis raises the question whether there are any languages that mark this distinction with overt morphology. In this respect, Cinque considers languages, among them BCS, where adnominal modification has two distinct morphological shapes. Crucially, BCS adjectives have differ- ent morphological forms depending on their distribution: the ‘‘long form’’ and the ‘‘short form.’’ Cinque treats the two forms as being overt manifestations of the two sources of modification. In particular, he suggests that adnominal short-form adjectives are always reduced relative clauses (indirect modification), while long-form adjectives are ambiguous between the two sources. This proposal captures some distributional and ordering restrictions these two forms of BCS adjec- tives display. In this squib, I provide several empirical arguments against the claim that BCS is a language that overtly distinguishes between two sources of modification. By closely inspecting the distribution and interpretations of BCS adjectives, the ordering between the two forms in the prenominal position, and extraction possibilities out of APs, I show that both long- and short-form adjectives represent challenges for Cinque’s model.
    [Show full text]
  • How Reduced Are Reduced Relatives? Petra Sleeman and Els Verheugd
    How Reduced are Reduced Relatives? Petra Sleeman and Els Verheugd 1. Introduction In this paper we will argue that the prenominal participial constituent in (1) cannot be analyzed as a preposed reduced relative clause, contra Kayne (1994): (1) the recently sent book First we will show, on the basis of French and English data, that participial modifiers are, in principle, susceptible to being analyzed as reduced relatives. We will argue that reduced relatives differ from simple adjectives in terms of argument structure: whereas reduced relatives are the projection of a head with its arguments, simple adjectives do not have argument structure at all. Subse• quently, we will investigate the status of the modifier in (1). 2. Kayne's analysis Kayne (1994) analyzes postnominal participial constituents in English and French as reduced relative clauses. For antisymmetry reasons, full relatives are not generated as right-adjuncts, but as CPs selected by D°. The antecedent noun raises from within the clause to Spec,CP: (2) DP[the cp[booki ti sent ti to john]] (3) DP[le CP[livrei ti envoye ti á Jean]] the book sent to John 'the book sent to John' The prenominal position of the participial constituent recently sent in (1) is derived by movement of the predicate to Spec,CP whereas the NP stays in Spec,IP. This analysis is also proposed for simple adjectives such as yellow: (4) DP[the cp[[yellow]i book ti]] Linguistics in the Netherlands 1998, 187-199. DOI 10.1075/avt.15.17sle ISSN 0929-7332 / E-ISSN 1569-9919 © Algemene Vereniging voor Taalwetenschap 188 PETRA SLEEMAN AND ELS VERHEUGD Kayne states that Spec,CP has to be filled.
    [Show full text]
  • Processing Subject-Object Ambiguities in Dutch
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Groningen Digital Archive Processing Subject-Object Ambiguities in Dutch Edith Kaan Groningen Dissertations in Linguistics 20 ISSN 0928-0030 Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Processing Subject-Object Ambiguities in Dutch Proefschrift ter verkrijging van het doctoraat in de Letteren aan de Rijksuniversiteit Groningen op gezag van de Rector Magnificus, dr. F. van der Woude, in het openbaar te verdedigen op donderdag 1 mei 1997 des namiddags te 4.15 uur door Edith Kaan geboren op 31 juli 1969 te Emmen Promotor: Prof. dr. J. Koster Referent: Dr. L.A. Stowe ‘Stel je voor,’ zei Eiso, ‘dat we de woorden niet in een bepaalde volgorde konden krijgen.’ ‘Stel je voor,’ zei Ramselaar, ‘dat we dat niet konden omdat het niet hoefde. Stel je voor dat je twee woorden tegelijk kon uitspreken.’ ‘Dan zou de tijd zijn opgeheven,’ zei Eiso. -- Gerrit Krol, Een ongenode gast. Acknowledgments ____________________________________________________________________ In retrospect, the day I became a research assistant to Laurie Stowe was a major turning point in my short academic career. Although I still decided to write my MA thesis on Minimalist Syntax, I soon became so much intrigued by sentence processing and the technical aspects of running experiments that I decided to apply for an aio position in psycholinguistics. This book presents part of the work done during the past four years. I could not have completed this thesis so quickly but for the help of a number of people. First of all, Laurie Stowe deserves my greatest thanks.
    [Show full text]
  • S of Technology
    On Reduced Relatives with Genitive Subjects by Cornelia Krause MA Linguistics Friedrich Schiller Universitiit Jena, 1995 Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology September 2001 @ 2001 Cornelia Krause. All rights reserved. The author hereby grants to MIT permission to reproduce and to distribute publicly paper and electronic copies of this thesis document in whole or in part. Signature of Author: Department of Linguistics and Philosophy June 28, 2001 Certified by: Sabine latridou, Professor of Linguistics Thesis Supervisor Certified by: v - ,_ David Psetsky, Ferrari P. Ward Professor of Linguistics Thesis Supervisor Certified by: Ken Hale, Professor Emeritus of Linguistics Thesis Supervisor Accepted by: Alec Marantz, Professor of Linguistics Mead, of Linguistics and Philosophy SOF TECHNOLOGY Department CARCHIVES LIBRARIES On Reduced Relatives with Genitive Subjects by Cornelia Krause Submitted to the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy on June 28, 2001 in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Abstract What is the place of relatives with genitive subjects in a typology of relative clauses? Are they full or reduced, headed or free relatives? Can they appear pre- and postnominally? Can they be head-internal relatives? Are they finite or non-finite? Can they be restrictives and appositives? These are the questions that this thesis will address. Full relatives have nominative subjects. Thus, relatives with genitive subjects are not full relatives. Relatives with genitive subjects share, however, many properties with reduced relatives. Among others, both prohibit relative pronouns and complementizers.
    [Show full text]
  • Using Reduced Relative Clauses to Write Concisely
    George Mason University Writing Center writingcenter.gmu.edu The [email protected] Writing Center 703.993.1200 Using Reduced Relative Clauses to Write Concisely The building that is across from Robinson Hall A is the Fenwick Library. The building across from Robinson Hall A is the Fenwick Library. The two sentences above have completely identical meaning, but the number of words to express the same idea is different. Since academic writing is characterized by being concise and dense, reducing unnecessary words in sentences can help writers achieve this goal. This handout specifically addresses the reduction of relative clauses, an advanced grammatical structure commonly found in academic writing. Background The first sentence in the example above contains the relative clause that is across Robinson Hall A. How do we know that it is a relative clause? A relative clause starts with a relative pronoun (e.g. that, which, who, whose) and provides additional information about the noun it follows. In this case, the relative clause that begins with the pronoun that modifies the noun the building, specifying which building the writer refers to. It is also important to remember that any clause should have a subject and a verb. Does that is across Robinson Hall A have a subject and a verb? It does: the relative pronoun that functions as a subject and is as a verb. When relative pronouns function as subjects of a clause, a relative clause can be reduced in two main ways: Full Relative Clause Reduced Relative Clause If a relative pronoun is followed by be The magazines that are on The magazines that are on (in any form), both elements can be the table belong to me.
    [Show full text]