Building Formal Ontologies for Theology and Systems of Belief
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
4 Reformed Orthodoxy
Autopistia : the self-convincing authority of scripture in reformed theology Belt, H. van der Citation Belt, H. van der. (2006, October 4). Autopistia : the self-convincing authority of scripture in reformed theology. Retrieved from https://hdl.handle.net/1887/4582 Version: Corrected Publisher’s Version Licence agreement concerning inclusion of doctoral thesis in the License: Institutional Repository of the University of Leiden Downloaded from: https://hdl.handle.net/1887/4582 Note: To cite this publication please use the final published version (if applicable). id7775687 pdfMachine by Broadgun Software - a great PDF writer! - a great PDF creator! - http://www.pdfmachine.com http://www.broadgun.com 4 Reformed Orthodoxy The period of Reformed orthodoxy extends from the Reformation to the time that liberal theology became predominant in the European churches and universities. During the period the Lutheran, Reformed, and Anglican churches were the official churches in Protestant countries and religious polemics between Catholicism and Protestantism formed an integral part of the intense political strife that gave birth to modern Europe. Reformed orthodoxy is usually divided into three periods that represent three different stages; there is no watershed between these periods and it is difficult to “ ” determine exact dates. During the period of early orthodoxy the confessional and doctrinal codifications of Reformed theology took place. This period is characterized by polemics against the Counter-Reformation; it starts with the death of the second- generation Reformers (around 1565) and ends in the first decades of the seventeenth century.1 The international Reformed Synod of Dort (1618-1619) is a useful milestone, 2 “ because this synod codified Reformed soteriology. -
The Metaphysics of Time OA
Roskilde University Arthur Prior and Special Theory of Relativity: Two Standpoints from the Nachlass Kofod, Julie Lundbak Published in: The Metaphysics of Time Publication date: 2020 Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Citation for published version (APA): Kofod, J. L. (2020). Arthur Prior and Special Theory of Relativity: Two Standpoints from the Nachlass. In P. Hasle, D. Jakobsen, & P. Øhrstrøm (Eds.), The Metaphysics of Time: Themes from Prior (pp. 227-247). Aalborg Universitetsforlag. Logic and Philosophy of Time Vol. 4 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain. • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 24. Sep. 2021 The Metaphysics of Time Logic and Philosophy of Time, Vol. 4 Per Hasle, David Jakobsen, and Peter Øhrstrøm (Eds.) The Metaphysics of Time: Themes from Prior Edited -
Ontology and Information Systems
Ontology and Information Systems 1 Barry Smith Philosophical Ontology Ontology as a branch of philosophy is the science of what is, of the kinds and structures of objects, properties, events, processes and relations in every area of reality. ‘Ontology’ is often used by philosophers as a synonym for ‘metaphysics’ (literally: ‘what comes after the Physics’), a term which was used by early students of Aristotle to refer to what Aristotle himself called ‘first philosophy’.2 The term ‘ontology’ (or ontologia) was itself coined in 1613, independently, by two philosophers, Rudolf Göckel (Goclenius), in his Lexicon philosophicum and Jacob Lorhard (Lorhardus), in his Theatrum philosophicum. The first occurrence in English recorded by the OED appears in Bailey’s dictionary of 1721, which defines ontology as ‘an Account of being in the Abstract’. Methods and Goals of Philosophical Ontology The methods of philosophical ontology are the methods of philosophy in general. They include the development of theories of wider or narrower scope and the testing and refinement of such theories by measuring them up, either against difficult 1 This paper is based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. BCS-9975557 (“Ontology and Geographic Categories”) and by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation under the auspices of its Wolfgang Paul Program. Thanks go to Thomas Bittner, Olivier Bodenreider, Anita Burgun, Charles Dement, Andrew Frank, Angelika Franzke, Wolfgang Grassl, Pierre Grenon, Nicola Guarino, Patrick Hayes, Kathleen Hornsby, Ingvar Johansson, Fritz Lehmann, Chris Menzel, Kevin Mulligan, Chris Partridge, David W. Smith, William Rapaport, Daniel von Wachter, Chris Welty and Graham White for helpful comments. -
History of Ontology from Suã¡Rez to Kant (1597-1781)
History of Ontology from Suárez to Kant (1597-1781) https://www.ontology.co/history.htm Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Birth of a New Science: the History of Ontology from Suárez to Kant INTRODUCTION "To begin with we want to state that ontology should be seen only as an interdiscipline involving both philosophy and science. It is a discipline which points out the problems of the foundations of the sciences as well as the borderline questions, and which further attempts to solve these problems and questions. Ontology is not a discipline which exists separately and independently from all the other scientific disciplines and also from other branches of philosophy. Rather, ontology derives the general structure of the world; it obtains the structure of the world as it really is from knowledge embodied in other disciplines. If one examines the history of philosophy one sees that ontology has never solved or attempted to solve the questions about the structures of our world independently, apart from the other philosophical disciplines or apart from the sciences. As is expressed by this symposium's topic, "Language and Ontology", ontology has derived the world's structure from other disciplines which describe reality, and has thus relied upon the languages of other disciplines. A common belief is that this derivation of the world's most general structures from the knowledge of other disciplines is ontology's only task. But now the belief is that in doing ontology one always selects the most important and most general laws from among all the laws which the various disciplines have to offer at any given time. -
Database and Ontology Mini-Series Data and Process Revisited
Ontolog: Database And Ontology Mini-Series Data and process revisited: ontology driving a paradigm shift in the development of business application systems Chris Partridge BORO Centre – Chief Ontologist Caveat – area of interest • Large Operational •Semantic Web Business Systems, Applications e.g. – “Collective –ERP Systems Knowledge” Systems –CRM Systems – Social networking – –FX Settlement Facebook Systems –Wikis – Trading Accounting – Bio-medical Systems dictionaries – Retail POS Systems • Inference – Telecom Billing – Logics – first order, Systems description Page 2 - © 2007 The BORO Centre Ltd. Thesis 1. There is a common interest in ‘what exists’ (= ontology) in philosophy and business systems 2. The business systems community works within a paradigm for this that is not adequate for the development of modern large complex systems 3. A review of where ontology fits into the development process leads to a proposal for revising this paradigm 4. The revised paradigm leads to a reassessment of one of today’s key IT problems – the re-development of legacy systems Page 3 - © 2007 The BORO Centre Ltd. Ontology: Philosophy and Business Systems •Goal: – Establish that there is a common interest in what exists (= ontology). – Start with a brief history of ontology Page 4 - © 2007 The BORO Centre Ltd. A brief history of Ontology • History of the word – The word ontology is from the Greek ὄν, genitive ὄντος: of being (part. of εἶναι: to be) and -λογία: science, study, theory. – While the etymology is Greek, the oldest extant record of the word itself is the Latin form ontologia, which appeared in 1661, in the work Ogdoas Scholastica by Jacob Lorhard (Lorhardus) and in 1631 in the Lexicon Philosophicum by Rudolph Göckel (Goclenius). -
Barry Smith 1 ARTIFICIAL COMPANIONS Ontology As A
THE RELEVANCE OF PHILOSOPHICAL ONTOLOGY TO INFORMATION AND COMPUTER SCIENCE Barry Smith Preprint version of a paper to appear in Ruth Hagengruber and Uwe Riss (eds.), Philosophy, Computing and Information Science, London: Pickering and Chatto, 2014, 75-83 1 ARTIFICIAL COMPANIONS Ontology as a branch of philosophy is the science of what is, of the kinds and structures of objects, properties, events, processes and relations in every area of reality. The earliest use of the term ‘ontology’ (or ‘ontologia’) seems to have been in 1606 in the book Ogdoas Scholas- tica by the German Protestant scholastic Jacob Lorhard. For Lorhard, as for many subsequent philosophers, ‘ontology’ is a synonym of ‘metaphysics’ (a label meaning literally: ‘what comes after the Physics’), a term used by early students of Aristotle to refer to what Aristotle himself called ‘first philosophy’. Some philosophers use ‘ontology’ and ‘metaphysics’ to refer to two distinct, though interrelated, disciplines, the former to refer to the study of what might exist; the latter to the study of which of the various alternative possible ontologies is in fact true of reality.1 The term – and the philosophical discipline of ontology – has enjoyed a checkered history since 1606, with a significant expansion, and consolidation, in recent decades (see Figure 1, which records references to ‘ontology’ in items accessible to the google website). We shall not discuss here the successive rises and falls in philosophical acceptance of the term, but rather focus on certain phases in the history of recent philosophy which are most relevant to the consideration of its recent advance, and increased acceptance, also outside the discipline of philosophy. -
Article JOURNAL of CATALAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY, Issues 7&8, 2014 | Print ISSN 2014-1572 / Online ISSN 2014-1564 DOI: 10.2436/20.3001.02.85 | P
article JOURNAL OF CATALAN INTELLECTUAL HISTORY, Issues 7&8, 2014 | Print ISSN 2014-1572 / Online ISSN 2014-1564 DOI: 10.2436/20.3001.02.85 | P. 11-30 Reception date: 8/11/2013 / Admission date: 12/12/2013 http://revistes.iec.cat/index.php/JOCIH Three theses on the historiography and ontology of Ferrater Mora Pompeu Casanovas Institute of Law and Technology Autonomous University of Barcelona [email protected] abstract This paper advances three theses on the link between ontology and history in Ferrater Mora’s works: (i) his intellectual history is a second-order semantic history, (ii) his ontology may be defined as a second-order hermeneutics, and (iii) his philosophy (which he called integrationism) consists of a second-order dialogue that, despite its limitations, comes to make sense within the latest generation of the Web. The paper also considers the role of computational ontologies in the management and organisation of philosophical contents. key words Ferrater Mora, ontology, ontologies, intellectual history, philosophy of history, integrationism. 1. Three theses on Ferrater Let me begin directly by spelling out the three theses that I would like to defend1: 1. Ferrater’s brand of intellectual history — I am referring to the history con- structed in his Dictionary2 and related articles — constitutes a second-order semantic history. 1 This paper is a revised version of a text presented at a conference devoted to the philosopher and essayist Josep Ferrater Mora (Barcelona 1912-1991) in commemoration of the cente- nary of his birth, organised jointly by the IEC and the Ferrater Mora Chair in Barcelona and Girona, respectively, on 7 and 8 November 2012. -
Divine Covenants, Absolute and Conditional: John Cameron and the Early Orthodox Development of Reformed Covenant Theology
MJT 17 (2006) 11-56 DIVINE COVENANTS, ABSOLUTE AND CONDITIONAL: JOHN CAMERON AND THE EARLY ORTHODOX DEVELOPMENT OF REFORMED COVENANT THEOLOGY by Richard A. Muller I. John Cameron and the Development of Early Reformed Orthodoxy John Cameron and Early Reformed Orthodoxy IT IS GENERALLY agreed that John Cameron (ca. 1579-1625) occupies a significant position in the early development of Reformed covenant theology. Although there are a series of fairly extensive older biographical studies,1 his thought has been examined primarily as a prelude to the theology of his student and successor in the Academy of Saumur, Moyses Amyraut, with little attention to its antecedents and its context. 1 On Cameron’s life, see Robert Wodrow, “Collections on the Life of Mr. John Cameron, Minister at Bordeaux, Professor of Divinity at Saumur, Principall of the College of Glasgow, and Professor of Divinity at Montauban,” in Collections upon the Lives of the Reformers and most eminent Ministers of the Church of Scotland, 2 vols. (Glasgow, 1848), II/2, pp. 81-229; Gaston Bonet-Maury, “Jean Cameron, pasteur de l’église de Bordeaux et professeur de théologie à Saumur et à Montauban, 1579-1625,” in Études de théologie et d’histoire (Paris: 1901), pp. 77-117; idem, “John Cameron: A Scottish Protestant Theologian in France,” in The Scottish Historical Review, 7 (1910), pp. 325-345; and H. M. B. Reid, The Divinity Principals in the University of Glasgow, 1545-1654 (Glasgow, 1917), pp. 170-251. 12 • MID-AMERICA JOURNAL OF THEOLOGY This somewhat retrospective reading of -
Ontology in Classical Greek Philosophy
This file is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 (CC BY-NC 3.0) Knowledge Engineering with Semantic Web Technologies Lecture 3: Ontologies and Logic 3.13 EXTRA: A Brief History of Ontology Dr. Harald Sack Hasso Plattner Institute for IT Systems Engineering University of Potsdam Autumn 2015 Semantic Web Technologies , Dr. Harald Sack, Hasso Plattner Institute, University of Potsdam What is Ontology? ● Etymology: ○ ον [greek] participle of „to be“ ○ λογια [greek] science ● (simplified) Definition: ○ „philosophical study of the nature of being, existence, or reality, as well as the basic categories of being and their relations....“ (wikipedia) ● General Question: ○ „what does exist or can be said to exist?“ ● General Metaphysics vs. Epistemology Jacob Lorhard: Ogdoas Scholastica, continens Diagraphen Typicam artium: Grammatices (Latinae, Graecae), SemanticLogices, Web Rhetorices, Technologies Astronomices, , Dr. Harald Ethices, Sack, Physices, Hasso Plattner Metaphysices, Institute, seu Ontologiae.University Sangalli:of Potsdam Straub, 1606 Fundamental Questions of Ontology 1. What does it mean for a being to be? ● When are two things identical? ● Is everything that exists also real? ● Does something exist, if it is only possible? ● Are there non-existing things? 2. What categories of objects do exist? ● Do things exist that are only unique or only multiple (Universalia)? ● Do things exist that are unilaterally dependent of others (Substances)? ● Of which sort is this dependency (Causality)? ● Do necessary properties -
Applied Ontology Cannot Share Data with One Another
Ontology is the philosophical discipline which aims to understand how things in the world are divided into categories and how these categories are related together. This is exactly what information scientists aim for in creating structured, automated Katherine Munn representations, called 'ontologies,' for managing information in fields such as science, government, Barry Smith (Eds.) industry, and healthcare. Currently, these systems are designed in a variety of different ways, so they Applied Ontology cannot share data with one another. They are often · idiosyncratically structured, accessible only to those who created them, and unable to serve as inputs for automated reasoning. This volume shows, in a non- Applied Ontology technical way and using examples from medicine and biology, how the rigorous application of An Introduction theories and insights from philosophical ontology can improve the ontologies upon which information Wachter management depends. RESEARCH Edited by Maria E. Reicher · Johanna Seibt Barry Smith · Daniel von METAPHYSICAL Katherine Munn, Barry Smith (Eds.) ontos 9 783938 793985 verlag Distributed in North and South America by Transaction Books ISBN 978-3-938793-98-5 Katherine Munn, Barry Smith Applied Ontology An Introduction M E T A P H Y S I C A L R E S E A R C H Herausgegeben von / Edited by Uwe Meixner • Johanna Seibt Barry Smith • Daniel von Wachter Band 8 / Volume 9 Katherine Munn, Barry Smith Applied Ontology An Introduction Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. -
Just War.Pdf
VU Research Portal Religionis Causa: Moral Theology and the Concept of Holy War van Eijnatten, J. published in Journal of Religious Ethics 2006 DOI (link to publisher) 10.1111/j.1467-9795.2006.00287.x document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) van Eijnatten, J. (2006). Religionis Causa: Moral Theology and the Concept of Holy War. Journal of Religious Ethics, 34, 609-635. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9795.2006.00287.x General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 26. Sep. 2021 RELIGIONIS CAUSA Moral Theology and the Concept of Holy War in the Dutch Republic Joris van Eijnatten ABSTRACT The claim is widespread that the preservation, or reintroduction, of Western traditions of holy war in the post-Reformation period was due mostly to Protestantism, especially in its Calvinist variety. -
THE LIBRARY of JOHN WEBSTER the Manuscript of the Catalogue Of
2 THE LIBRARY OF JOHN WEBSTER INTRODUCTION The manuscript ofthe catalogue ofthe library ofDr John Webster ofClitheroe is to be found today in the archives ofChetham's library, Manchester (Chetham MS A.6.47). It was previously in the ownership of the celebrated Lancashire antiquarian, James Crossley, who was himself given the manuscript on 12 June 1876 by a friend, the Reverend Thomas Corser of Stand.46 The manuscript consists of twenty-two foliated leaves bound with marbled boards and leather spine, and is almost certainly a copy of an original draft, composed by Webster himself, probably for the purpose of evaluating his estate.47 In Webster's will, dated 3 January 1680 (see Appendix 1), the contents ofthe library were valued at £400, a figure roughly approximating to the more accurate catalogue evaluation of £402 6s. 10d. The catalogue is systematically arranged according to subject and book-size and would appear to reflect the original plan ofthe books as they actually appeared on the shelves of Webster's library. It comprises fifteen sections (which, for the sake of convenience, I have labelled A to 0) with 1501 entries in total. This figure, however, is not an accurate assessment of the number of volumes once possessed by Webster. Although it is impossible to give a precise figure,48 a conservative estimate would indicate a total number ofvolumes in the region of 1662 (a figure which includes works from Section M which were not in Webster's possession at the time the catalogue was produced). Clearly, the sheer size of Webster's library is one of its most striking features, but what else, apart from the broadest generalizations, can it tell us about the owner ofthis collection? The limited use of such evidence is all too obvious.