A Hundred Years of Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Hundred Years of Philosophy A HUNDRED YEARS OF PHILOSOPHY John Passmore -*"1 t,. I tq." I t' )l i PENGUINBOOKS -./ ('t ("(-^ ,l THE NEW REALISTS CHAPTER 11 pcriencedepends for its existenceupon the fact that it is experi- onccd was to be the most characteristic feature of the New The New Realists llcnlism. The secondaryqualities, Stout had also said, exist only as objccts of experience.If we look at a buttercup in a variety of years present IN the early of the century, it could no longer bc lightswe seedifferent shades ofcolour, without havingany reason presufned that Realism was intellectually disreputable,a mero to believethat the buttercup itself has altered; if a number of vulgar prejudice. What a mind knows, Brentano and Meinong observersplunge their hands into a bowl of water, they will report had argued,exists independently of the act by which it is known; vcry different degrees of warmth, even although nothing has Mach, and James after him - if they were still, from a Realist Iruppenedwhich could affect the water's temperature. Such facts point tainted of view, with subjectivism- had at least denied that dcmonstrate,Stout thought, that secondaryqualities exist only as what is immediately perceived is a state of mind; and then 'scnsa'- objectsof our perception;they are not actualproperties Moore, seconded by Russell, had rejected that thesis which of physicalobjects. Idealistslike phenomenalists Bradleyand like Mill had united in Nunn'sreply is uncompromising.The contrastbetween 'sensa' regarding as indisputable: that the existenceof objects of percep- and 'actual properties'is, he argues,an untenableone. All the tion consists the perceived. in fact that they are The 'New Real. nhadesof colour which the buttercuppresents to an observerare ism' brought togetherthese converging tendencies; it owedmuch uctual properties of the buttercup; and all the hotnessesof the to Meinong, more to Mach and James,and it acknowledgedtho w&terare propertiesof the water.The plain man and the scientist help Moore of and Russellin the battle againstIdealism. rscribea standardtemperature and a standardcolour to a thing The first, in England, to formulate the characteristic doctrinct nnd limit it to a certain region of space,because its complexity of the New Realismwas T. P. Nunn.l Best known as an educa. wouldotherwise defeat them. The fact remains,Nunn argues,that tionalist, Nunn wrote little philosophy, on but that little had an o thinghas not onehotness, for example,but many,and that these influence out of proportion all to its modest dimensions. In hotnessesare not in a limited regionof spacebut in variousplaces particular, his contribution to a symposiumon 'Are Secondary aroundabout the standardobject. A thing is hotter an inch away Independent Qualities of Perception?'2 was widely studied both than a foot away and hotter on a cold hand than on a warrn one, in England where,as we have alreadynoted, it struck Bertrand just as it is a paleryellow in one lieht than it is in another light. Russell'sroving fancy, and in the United States.Nunn there sus- To imagineotherwise is to confusebetween the arbitrary'thing' tained two theses:(l) that primary both the and the secondary of everyday life rand the 'thing' as experience shows it to qualitiesof really in perceived bodiesare them, whetherthey are be. not; (2) qualities perceived. or that exist as they are In Nunn's theory of perception,then, the ordinary conception Much of his argumentis polemical in form, with Stout'searlier of a material thing is revolutionized; that is the price he has to artidesr as its chief target. Stout had thought he could begin by payfor his Realism.A 'thing', now, is a colleclionof appearances' presuming that there are at least someelements in our experience evenifevery appeaxanceis independentofthe mind beforewhich which existonly in perceived pain. being - he instanced But Nunn it appears.Nunn's realism, at this point, is very like Mach's pain, precisely objects that in the manner of a material object, phenomenalism.The sameis true of American New Realism. presentsdifficulties us, path, to raisesobstacles in our is, in short, Scottish 'common-sensephilosophy', as we have already ob- somethingwe must reckon with. 'Pain,' he thereforeconcludes, served, dominated the American Universities during the greater something my 'is outside mind, with which my mind may como part of the nineteenthcentury; nor was it entirely swept out of into various relations.' A refusal to admit that anything wo €x- existenceeither by James'spragmatism or by Royce's idealism. 258 259 A HUNDREDYEARS OF PHILOSOPHY THE NBW REALISTS Peirce, to take the most notable case, continued to admire that contributions by E. B. Holt, W. T. Marvin, W. P. Montague, .critical 'subtle and well-balanced intellect, Thomas Reid'; his R. B. Perry, W. B. Pitkin and E. G. Spaulding. commonsensism'aowed much to Reid and his school. When The New Realismis the Realist equivalent of ldealism's Essays Peirce criticized Reid, furthermore, it was from a Realist point ln Philosophical Criticism. A number of philosophers, by no of view; Reid, he complained,had not wholly shakenhimself free nrcansunanimous on everypoint, felt that they had in commona .W€ from the Cartesian doctrine of representative perception. nrethodof approachto philosophy,with the help of which they have direct experienceof things in themselves,,peirce wrote in couldsatisfy their diverseaims. A manifesto,6it beginswith a long 1896.'Nothing can be more completelyfalse than that we can cxplanatory preface and ends with a series of brief policy- experienceonly our own ideas. That is indeed without exaggera- speeches.The world of philosophy could no longer pretend tion the very epitome of all falsity.' ignorance of the fact that a new and revolutionary spirit of The American tendency towards Realism, however, had been Itcalism was abroad. vigorously opposed by Royce rn The World and the Individaal ln many respects,however, The New Realism had little to add (1900). Realism was there defined as, above all, a defenceof in- exceptliveliness of statementto Moore's Refutationof ldealism. dependence,and Roycecriticized it as such.'The world of fact,, In other ways,again - in maintaining,for example,that philos- Roycedescribes the Realistas maintaining, 'is independentof our ophy is'peculiarly dependentupon logic' and in defendingthe knowledgeof that world . the vanishingof our mindsfrom that validity ofanalysis againstthe Idealist doctrine that'the truth is world would make no difference in the being of the independent the whole'- the New Realismis mainly important as a medium facts we know.' Royce's counter-argument, lengthy, robust and tlrrough which Russell'sconception of phllosophy was natural- ingenious, is designedto show that if independenceis ultimate - ized in America. Yet one must not overestimatethe New Real- not mere 'appearance'- then all relations,including the relation isnr'sindebtedness to English philosophy. Russell,after all, had of knowledge, are impossible in principle. In trying to preserve lcarnt many of his most characteristicdoctrines from William the independenceof the objects of knowledge the Realist ends, James,whom he describesas 'the most important of all critics of according to Royce, by destroying the very possibitity of know- Monism'. The point most vital in the logic of The New Realism ledge. - that relations are external - James had particularly urged. Royce's attack provoked an immediaie reply from two of his Marvin summed up that do4rine with rare succinctness.'In the former.pupils,R. B. Perryand W. P. Montague.sRelatedness and proposition"the term a is in the relation .Rto the term b", aR independence,they argued, perfectly are compatible.The task of in no degreeconstitutes b, nor does-Rb constitute a, nor doesR explainingin what 'independence'consistsis not, however,an constituteeither a or b.' From this it follows, presumingthat easy one; in England, Schiller had attacked Nunn on this very knowledgeis a relation, that the known is not constitutedby its point. To give a satisfactory account ofindependence was one of relationto the knowel, or the knower by its relationto the known, the two main problemswhich confrontedthe New Realists;the or either knower or known by the fact that it is a constituentin other was to explain, without abandoningRealism, how reality the knowledgerelation. is to be distinguishedfrom illusion - that rock on which so many On so much, the New Realistsagreed. There wasnot the same hogefullyJaunched Realismshave foundered. agreementabout the nature of the knower or the nature of the American philosophical journals, in the first decade of the known. When Russellrefered favourably to the 'new Realism' preseJrtcentuq/, cdntain a multitude of attempts to sketch a hc meantthe'neutral monism' which Perry and Holt had worked Realist philosophy which would deal satisfactorily with these out under the influenceof Mach, Jamesand Nunn.? Other New problems.But New Realismdid not comeof ageuntil the publica- Realists, Montague especially, were highly critical of neutral tion in l9l2 of The New Realism, a cooperative volume with monism. 260 261 A HUNDRED YEARS OF PIIILOSOPHY THE NEW REALISTS The Holt-Perry variety of realism is an out-radicalizing qf No doubt, Perry admits, other people sometimesfind it difficult James'sradical empiricism. Jameshad denied that there is suchaiq to decidewhat I am thinking about - that is why it is plausible entity as 'consciousness';its adherents,he wrote, ,are clingiilg' to suggsslthat the contentsof my
Recommended publications
  • THE VOLUNTARY SIMPLICITY MOVEMENT a Multi-National Survey Analysis in Theoretical Context
    ! 3 THE VOLUNTARY SIMPLICITY MOVEMENT A multi-national survey analysis in theoretical context Superfluous wealth can buy superfluities only. – Henry Thoreau 1. Introduction The Voluntary Simplicity Movement can be understood broadly as a diverse social movement made up of people who are resisting high consumption lifestyles and who are seeking, in various ways, a lower consumption but higher quality of life alternative (Grigsby, 2004; Alexander, 2009, 2011a). In 2011 a multi-national online survey was launched for the purpose of gaining empirical insight into this ‘post- consumerist’ social movement. Presently 2268 participants in the movement have completed our 50-question survey and that makes it by far the most extensive sociological examination of the movement available (Elgin and Mitchell, 1977; Schor, 1998; Pierce, 2000; Kasser, 2002; Craig-Lees and Hill, 2002; Grigsby, 2004; Brown and Kasser, 2005; Hamilton and Denniss, 2005). This chapter presents a foundational analysis of these survey results.1 !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1 This chapter is a lightly revised version of the paper that appeared in the Journal of Consumer Culture (2012), co-authored by Samuel Alexander and Simon Ussher. Although the original paper was based on 2268 participants, at the time of writing this revised version (March 2015) that number had grown to 3708 participants. The results have not changed in any significant way by these extra participants, however to remain consistent with the peer-reviewed paper the results below remain based on 2268 participants. The survey is still open, collecting more data. See here: 37 SAMUEL ALEXANDER 2. Why Examine the Voluntary Simplicity Movement? Before turning to the survey and its results, we wish to provide some theoretical context to this research by outlining briefly why we chose to examine the Voluntary Simplicity Movement (hereafter, the ‘Simplicity Movement’).
    [Show full text]
  • Emergentism As an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism
    SURI 7 (2) 2019: 1-22 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion: Between Materialist Atheism and Pantheism James Franklin University of New South Wales Abstract: Among worldviews, in addition to the options of materialist atheism, pantheism and personal theism, there exists a fourth, “local emergentism”. It holds that there are no gods, nor does the universe overall have divine aspects or any purpose. But locally, in our region of space and time, the properties of matter have given rise to entities which are completely different from matter in kind and to a degree god-like: consciousnesses with rational powers and intrinsic worth. The emergentist option is compared with the standard alternatives and the arguments for and against it are laid out. It is argued that, among options in the philosophy of religion, it involves the minimal reworking of the manifest image of common sense. Hence it deserves a place at the table in arguments as to the overall nature of the universe. Keywords: Emergence; pantheism; personal theism; naturalism; consciousness 1. INTRODUCTION The main options among world views are normally classifiable as either materialist atheism, pantheism (widely understood) or personal theism. According to materialist atheism, there exists nothing except the material universe as we ordinarily conceive it, and its properties are fully described by science (present or future). According to personal theism, there exists a separate entity (or entities) of a much higher form than those found in the 2019 Philosophical Association of the Philippines 2 Emergentism as an Option in the Philosophy of Religion material universe, a god or gods.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Analytic Philosophy
    History of Analytic Philosophy Series Editor Michael Beaney Humboldt University Berlin King’s College London Berlin, Germany Series editor: Michael Beaney, Professor für Geschichte der analytischen Philosophie, Institut für Philosophie, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Germany, and Regius Professor of Logic, School of Divinity, History and Philosophy, University of Aberdeen, Scotland. Editorial board members: Claudio de Almeida, Pontifcal Catholic University at Porto Alegre, Brazil Maria Baghramian, University College Dublin, Ireland Thomas Baldwin, University of York, England Stewart Candlish, University of Western Australia Chen Bo, Peking University, China Jonathan Dancy, University of Reading, England José Ferreirós, University of Seville, Spain Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Gottfried Gabriel, University of Jena, Germany Juliet Floyd, Boston University, USA Hanjo Glock, University of Zurich, Switzerland Nicholas Griffn, McMaster University, Canada Leila Haaparanta, University of Tampere, Finland Peter Hylton, University of Illinois, USA Jiang Yi, Beijing Normal University, China Javier Legris, National Academy of Sciences of Buenos Aires, Argentina Cheryl Misak, University of Toronto, Canada Nenad Miscevic, University of Maribor, Slovenia, and Central European University, Budapest Volker Peckhaus, University of Paderborn, Germany Eva Picardi, University of Bologna, Italy Erich Reck, University of California at Riverside, USA Peter Simons, Trinity College, Dublin Thomas Uebel, University of Manchester, England More information
    [Show full text]
  • Transition Towns Movement, Which Is One of the More Promising Social Movements to Emerge During the Last Decade in Response to the Overlapping Problems Outlined Above
    ! 11 THE TRANSITION MOVEMENT Questions of diversity, power, and affluence 1. Introduction1 As the global economy continues to degrade planetary ecosystems (Rockstrom et al., 2009); as biodiversity continues to decline (United Nations, 2010); as climate scientists offer increasingly confident and dire warnings (IPCC, 2013); as peak oil arrives (Miller and Sorrell, 2014; Brecha, 2013); as fresh water and other key resources become scarcer (Brown, 2011) while population continues to grow (UNDSEA, 2012); and as financial systems continue to show signs of instability (Tverberg, 2012), the question of how nations around the world are going to ‘transition’ to a stable, just, and sustainable society is more pressing than ever. Things seem to be getting worse, not better, which calls for new thinking and new action, both at the personal and social levels, but also at the macroeconomic and political levels. If early in the environmental movement it was assumed that buying ‘green’ products, switching to energy efficient light bulbs, and taking shorter showers were the ‘lifestyle’ solutions to environmental problems, more recent evidence firmly indicates that such measures are not working or are not going to be anywhere near sufficient, necessary though they may be. The extent of ecological overshoot is too great (Global Footprint Network, 2013). Furthermore, many promised efficiency gains that were supposed to flow from technological advances seem to be getting lost to the Jevons Paradox and rebound effects (Herring and Sorrell, 2009; Polimeni et al., 2009), meaning that technology – the !!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!!! 1 This chapter is a lightly revised version of Simplicity Institute Report 14g, co-authored by Samuel Alexander and Esther Alloun.
    [Show full text]
  • The Moral and Ethical Weight of Voluntary Simplicity
    _____________________________________________________ THE MORAL AND ETHICAL WEIGHT OF VOLUNTARY SIMPLICITY A philosophical review Samuel Alexander and Jacob Garrett Simplicity Institute Report 17a, 2017 ___________________ SIMPLICITY INSTITUTE The Moral and Ethical Weight of Voluntary Simplicity: A Philosophical Review Samuel Alexander and JacoB Garrett 1. Introduction A vast and growing body of scientific literature is impressing upon us that human economic activity is degrading planetary ecosystems in ways that are unsustainable. Taken as a whole, we are overconsuming Earth’s resources, destabilising the climate, and decimating biodiversity (Steffan et al, 2015; IPCC, 2013; WWF, 2016). At the same time, we also know that there are billions of people around the world who are, by any humane standard, under-consuming. Alleviating global poverty is likely to place even more pressure on an already over-burdened planet. To make matters worse still, the global population, currently at 7.4 billion people, is expected to rise to around 9.7 billion by mid- century and 11 billion by the end of the century (Gerland et al, 2014), compounding already severe sustainability and social justice crises. Continuous economic growth seems socially necessary but ecologically disastrous (Meadows et al, 2004). What makes this entire situation more tragic still is that the high-consumption, Western-style lifestyles driving the environmental crisis are often failing to live up to their promise of a happy and meaningful life, leaving many people alienated from their communities, disconnected from nature, unhealthy, and overworked (Hamilton and Denniss, 2005; Lane, 2000). In this context, calls by environmentalists to reject consumerist lifestyles and growth-orientated economies in favour of less impactful consumption and production practices seem powerful, even compelling, from a range of environmental, social, and even self-interested perspectives (Trainer, 2010).
    [Show full text]
  • Human Understanding in the Philosophy of R.G. Collingwood
    HUMAN UNDERSTANDING IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF R.G. COLLINGWOOD JOHN KARABELAS PhD, CARDIFF UNIVERSITY 2009 HUMAN UNDERSTANDING IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF R.G. COLLINGWOOD JOHN KARABELAS PhD, CARDIFF UNIVERSITY 2009 UMI Number: U585273 All rights reserved INFORMATION TO ALL USERS The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Dissertation Publishing UMI U585273 Published by ProQuest LLC 2013. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author. Microform Edition © ProQuest LLC. All rights reserved. This work is protected against unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code. ProQuest LLC 789 East Eisenhower Parkway P.O. Box 1346 Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 DECLARATION This workha&not previously been accepted in substance for any degree and is not concurrently submitted in candidature for any degree. S ig n e^j^. .................. (candidate) Date ^.f.. .7.. STATEMENT 1 This thesis is bfiioo submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of i.(insert MCh, MD, MPhil, PhD etc, as appropriate) Signedf (candidate) Date .l^ .....^ ..(c/....'?^f!0.C\. STATEMENT 2 This thesis is the result of my own independent work/investigation, except where otherwise stated. Other sources are acknowledged by explicit references. Sign (candidate) Date .1^9.... STATEMENT 3 I hereby give consent for my thesis, if accepted, to be available for photocopying and for inter-library loan, and for the title and summary to be made available to outside organisatjj Signe< (candidate) D a t e .
    [Show full text]
  • Was Spinoza a Naturalist?
    WAS SPINOZA A NATURALIST? by ALEXANDER DOUGLAS Abstract: In this article I dispute the claim, made by several contemporary scholars, that Spinoza was a naturalist. ‘Naturalism’ here refers to two distinct but related positions in contemporary philosophy. The first, ontological natu- ralism, is the view that everything that exists possesses a certain character (variously defined) permitting it to be defined as natural and prohibiting it from being defined as supernatural. I argue that the only definition of onto- logical naturalism that could be legitimately applied to Spinoza’s philosophy is so unrestrictive as to tell us nothing about the content of his ideas. The second, methodological naturalism, is the view that the natural sciences are the best means of finding out substantial truths about the concrete world. I present some historical research showing that Spinoza’s way of positioning himself with respect to other philosophers in the Dutch Republic casts very serious doubt on the claim that he was a methodological naturalist. This adds further weight to arguments that have already been made against the naturalist reading of Spinoza. Introduction One thing that is often said of Spinoza is that he was a naturalist.1 This claim is important in the context of contemporary analytic philosophy, where naturalism is something of an industry standard. Jack Ritchie suggests that: . if you were to ask a contemporary philosopher in the English-speaking world – one of the living and thus not so great – to classify her philosophical position, I would
    [Show full text]
  • Voluntary Simplicity As an Aesthetics of Existence
    ! 11 VOLUNTARY SIMPLICITY AS AN AESTHETICS OF EXISTENCE The art of ethics in a consumer age Men have become the tool of their tools. The best works of art are the expression of man’s struggle to free himself from this condition. – Henry David Thoreau 1. Introduction Throughout the Western philosophic tradition, ethics and morality have generally referred to the task of living in accordance with a body of objectively verifiable moral rules, of adhering to a moral code that is knowable through rational inquiry and which, by virtue of its rational basis, applies to all people in all places. Philosophers have always disagreed, of course, about which of the possible moral codes is the objectively true one. But there has been a widespread consensus that discovering such a code is the aim of moral thought and that living in accordance with such a code is the aim of moral behaviour. We can see this assumption underlying the work of almost all the great moral philosophers – from Plato, through St Aquinas, to Kant and Bentham, and beyond – and well into the 20th century this assumption remained an almost unquestioned verity (see Rorty, 1999: Ch. 4). The logic beneath this assumption is quite understandable. If we are to live our lives according to the dictates of a moral code, even when it is not in our immediate self-interest to do so, then we should want the code to which we have subscribed to be somehow 253 SAMUEL ALEXANDER deserving of our obedience. Nobody would want to live according to moral rules if those rules were just the arbitrary assertions of some megalomaniac who simply wanted all humanity to abide by his or her personal standards of conduct.
    [Show full text]
  • British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, and the Origins of Analytic Aesthetics
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 12 2008 British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics Chinatsu Kobayashi Université du Québec à Montréal Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Kobayashi, Chinatsu (2008) "British Idealist Aesthetics, Collingwood, Wollheim, And The Origins Of Analytic Aesthetics," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. British Idealist Aesthetics 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of two, Bernard Bosanquet and Robin Collingwood appear, therefore, to Cognition, Logic and Communication be the only idealist aestheticians of significance in the first half of the twentieth century.4 Of the two, Collingwood knew more about art5 and August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy was by far more original, as he produced a philosophy of art that truly pages 1-40 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.136 engaged with the artistic preoccupations of his days in The Principles of Art (Collingwood 1938). Among the ‘realists’, the topic was hardly more popular: only Samuel Alexander and E.
    [Show full text]
  • Planned Economic Contraction: the Emerging Case for Degrowth
    This article was downloaded by: [University of Helsinki] On: 13 November 2012, At: 04:55 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Environmental Politics Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fenp20 Planned economic contraction: the emerging case for degrowth Samuel Alexander a b a Office for Environmental Programs, University of Melbourne, Australia b The Simplicity Institute Version of record first published: 20 Apr 2012. To cite this article: Samuel Alexander (2012): Planned economic contraction: the emerging case for degrowth, Environmental Politics, 21:3, 349-368 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2012.671569 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub- licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. Environmental Politics Vol. 21, No.
    [Show full text]
  • Voluntary Simplicity Strongly Backed by All Three Main Normative-Ethical Traditions
    Voluntary Simplicity Strongly Backed by All Three Main Normative-Ethical Traditions Rupert Read University of East Anglia, UK Samuel Alexander University of Melbourne, Australia Jacob Garrett Simplicity Institute, Melbourne, Australia AbstrAct. We examine the growing ‘Voluntary Simplicity’ (VS) movement from the perspectives of Utilitarianism, Kantian deontology, and Virtue Ethics. We argue that, from each of these three diverse perspectives, there is a compelling argument to the conclusion that citizens of the ‘developed’ world ought to embrace such simplicity in their own lives, and to facilitate its greater adoption societally and globally. We conclude by asking why it is that this compelling conclusion has not already been more widely found and acted upon. In reflect- ing on this question we outline some arguments for why a culture of voluntary simplicity may be needed to drive political and macroeconomic change. Keywords. Kant, Peter Singer, neoliberalism, moderation, climate change, eudaimonia I. IntroductIon vast body of scientific literature impresses upon us all that human A economic activity is degrading planetary ecosystems in ways that will make any form of ‘business as usual’ impossible. We humans are over- consuming earth’s resources, destabilising the climate, and decimating biodiversity (Steffen et al. 2015; IPCC 2013; WWF 2016). At the same time, we know that it is a minority of us who are largely responsible for this; there are many millions of people around the world who, by any humane standard, are ‘under-consuming’. Alleviating global poverty will place even more pressure on an already over-burdened planet.1 To make ethical perspectives – march 2018 matters worse, the global population, currently at 7.6 billion people, is expected to rise to around 9.7 billion by mid-century and 11 billion by the century’s end (Gerland et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham Research Online
    Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 11 October 2018 Version of attached le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Thomas, Emily (2019) 'The idealism and pantheism of May Sinclair.', Journal of the American Philosophical Association., 5 (2). pp. 137-157. Further information on publisher's website: https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2018.45 Publisher's copyright statement: This article has been published in a revised form in Journal of the American Philosophical Association https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2018.45. This version is free to view and download for private research and study only. Not for re-distribution, re-sale or use in derivative works. c American Philosophical Association 2018. Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk The Idealism and Pantheism of May Sinclair 1 Introduction May Sinclair (1863-1946) was a British novelist, feminist, and idealist philosopher.
    [Show full text]