1 Introducing Philosophy Pragmatist Style

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Introducing Philosophy Pragmatist Style 1 INTRODUCING PHILOSOPHY PRAGMATIST STYLE: AN ESSAY by Paul T. Durbin Emeritus Professor Philosophy Department and Center for Energy and Environmental Policy University of Delaware (c) 2007 TOPICAL OUTLINE Part One: Science versus Metaphysics, with Pragmatism as Middle Ground Introduction to Part 1: Why Western Philosophy Begins with the Pre-Socratics; or from Mythical Unity to Proto-Scientific Pluralism Section One: Metaphysics from Parmenides to Plato, Aristotle, and Skepticism 1. Parmenides 2. Plato on Ideas 3. Aristotle's "Moderate Realist" Reinterpretation of Plato's Ideas 4. Greek Skepticism Section Two: Science Forerunners among the Greeks: the Pythagorean Roots of Empedocles' Pluralism; Euclidian Geometry and Archimedes; Plato, Aristotle, and the Atomists 1. Empedocles 2. Euclid, Archimedes, and Aristarchus 3. Nature in Plato, Aristotle, and the Atomists a. Plato b. Aristotle's Four Causes and Natural Explanations 2 c. The Ancient Atomists Section Three: Ethics from Socrates to Plato to Aristotle and the Stoics 1. Greek Paideia 2. Socrates 3. Plato 4. Aristotle 5. The Stoics Section Four: Practice, the Missing Ingredient: Greek Drama; Politics and the Sophists Reconsidered; plus the "Mechanical" Arts and Crafts 1. Greek Drama 2. The Sophists Reconsidered: Greek Politics 3. "Mechanical" Arts and Crafts Part Two: Radicalisms in Philosophy and How Pragmatism Differs Introduction to Part 2: What Does Radicalism in Philosophy Mean? Four Answers Plus Pragmatism Section One: Descartes and Epistemological Radicalism Section Two: Empiricist Radicalism: Bacon, Hume, and Mill Section Three: Transcendental Radicalism: Kant and Hegel Section Four: Political Radicalism: Marx Section Five: Enter American Pragmatism: Peirce, James, and Dewey 1. Peirce 2. James 3. Dewey Part Three: Analytical Pragmatism a. Joseph Margolis's Reinventing Pragmatism b. Larry Hickman on Analytical Applied Philosophy Part Four: Activist Philosophy: Why It Is Not a Misnomer Introduction: How Philosophers Typically Find Their Career Path, and How the Pragmatic Way Differs I originally wrote this introduction as an appendix, and I placed it there out of deference to the reticence to talk about such matters in introductions to philosophy. But for a pragmatist in the tradition of George Mead and John Dewey, it should come at the beginning. What I claim here is that the typical path to a philosophy career tends to mask all debts that the individual owes to others who have helped him or her along the way -- it is made to appear that the individual has accomplished everything by himself or herself, usually with only the recognition of one principal mentor -- whereas pragmatists insist on the fact that all intellectual advances are made within supportive groups, all the way back to fam- ilies of origin. In the process, I argue that philosophy departments (I'm thinking mostly 3 about departments in universities in the USA) would do a better educational job if they de-emphasized a record of outstanding individual achievement in favor of broader stand- ards of achievement. This is, obviously, an argument in favor of greater inclusiveness, but I make it here in the name of pragmatic activism, of likely benefits for society in general. Bertrand Russell is rare among philosophers in having written an autobiography. And among the many philosophers I have known in a long career and in many different types of departments, I know of only one -- David Norton, long-time colleague in the Philos- ophy Department at the University of Delaware, now deceased -- who regularly invoked his past in his classes and in his writings. For most of the philosophers I have known well, it's as though they had no past, certainly no past beyond the work they did in grad- uate school with a particular mentor; even there, the past is typically reduced to the in- tellectual problem on which they worked together, with themselves as manifesting some sort of disagreement or separation that marked their originality as they started out on their academic career. For an American Pragmatist in the tradition of Dewey and of Mead even more so, that would appear to be odd, even indefensible. This is because, in that tradition, a person's philosophy is never uniquely his or hers; it is usually only a small step forward in an evo- lutionary history that stretches all the way back to the beginnings of human thought -- and beyond that, to non-human communication, back to the very beginnings of evolution. Even at the point where most philosophers begin, if they dwell on the matter at all -- that is, with their graduate school work with a particular (usually identified as a partic- ularly gifted) mentor -- Mead would emphasize the intellectual culture of the mentor, his or her mentors and the school of thought represented by them, where individual creativity or originality shows up against a background that the group takes for granted. The origi- nality of the budding young philosopher (as is true, in a different sense, of budding young scientists; see Robert Merton's "On the Shoulders of Giants") is recognized not only by the mentor but by others sharing that school of thought -- including its disagreements with other schools of thought. Randall Collins shows in his "sociology of philosophies" -- he says it is the essence thereof -- that the same dynamic is operative in a wide variety of cultures, so-called Eastern as well as Western, from their origins up to the beginning of the twentieth century (the point at which he thinks he must stop for lack of adequate evidence for more recent philosophical schools). And all such schools of thought involve outstanding symbolic practitioners who are thought to have achieved the goals, and the rewards, of that particular approach, or to have vanquished opponents in a definitive way. Actually, in my experience, few philosophers are willing to reflect to any great extent even on their experiences in graduate school. They just want to go on about their work, like the scientists whom many of them emulate, solving their particular set of problems and advancing their particular careers. Since this is so, and displaying my own reticence about doing an intellectual autobio- graphy of my own philosophical development, what I will do here is talk about the typi- 4 cal development of the average philosopher -- as I have come to know philosophers in- dividually -- or the average student who takes up a philosophy major (in the USA) or a philosophy "career" (carrera in the Spanish version of a university specialization, which I also know reasonably well). Most philosophers I have known have been academic oddballs -- we used to call them "nerds," but each era has its own similar expression to describe the stereotype -- from a very early age. They stood out from the crowd, for instance in high school, not for ath- letic success or success with girls, but for their ability to do well in school, to get high grades, even to win intellectual awards. I have never done a survey in the years I have thought about this, but my hunch is that a very high percentage of academics who end up as philosophers were valedictorians when they graduated from high school. Some have been known almost all their lives, among their peers, as "professor" (that was one of my personal nicknames), or "egghead," or something similar. It's almost as if they have been destined or fated to be philosophers -- or mathematicians, or theoretical physicists or something similar. And the same thing shows up in their university careers. Along with future scientists and engineers, philosophers seem to choose their major or their career very early on; they gravitate to particular kinds of professors, sometimes taking classes with a particular pro- fessor as often as the rules of the university allow. I am stereotyping, I know, but the reader should bear with me. Making fun of my friends and colleagues is not my goal. I want to look at the path the typical philosophy major (to the extent there is such) takes, as he or she goes on to graduate school, but also at the path that led to the stereotypical behavior from the earliest school years to high school and university and graduate work in philosophy. I begin at the beginning. Most philosophers I have known -- there are some excep- tions, of course -- have been praised within their families for their braininess. They were praised, early on, for reading well and much. Some, though I really have to stretch to say this (given the lack of hard evidence I have), seem to have thought of books as their best friends; at least many say that books have been their friends all their lives. They have also excelled at test taking, a skill that is increasingly praised these days in public schools but that has always been praised in private schools. I suspect that they have also, from their earliest years, been favorites of their teachers, especially of par- ticular teachers who are known for fostering academic excellence. There are some studies of this phenomenon, though the focus is the academically gifted in general (not those who end up as philosophy professors), and the studies demonstrate at least anec- dotally a high percentage who have had special teachers somewhere in their school years who have influenced them either to choose their academic career path or to do well in it. In talking with colleagues in philosophy departments -- not focusing on particular philosophers' backgrounds but drawing inferences from what they say about their grad school work -- I have found that an overwhelming percentage of them continued these patterns, with their strong reinforcers, right into graduate school. They were now praised 5 to an even higher degree for their braininess, for their ability to please particular profes- sors and be admitted into their study groups or to go immediately into work that will lead to a choice of thesis topic.
Recommended publications
  • The Return of Vitalism: Canguilhem and French Biophilosophy in the 1960S
    The Return of Vitalism: Canguilhem and French Biophilosophy in the 1960s Charles T. Wolfe Unit for History and Philosophy of Science University of Sydney [email protected] Abstract The eminent French biologist and historian of biology, François Jacob, once notoriously declared ―On n‘interroge plus la vie dans les laboratoires‖1: laboratory research no longer inquires into the notion of ‗Life‘. Nowadays, as David Hull puts it, ―both scientists and philosophers take ontological reduction for granted… Organisms are ‗nothing but‘ atoms, and that is that.‖2 In the mid-twentieth century, from the immediate post-war period to the late 1960s, French philosophers of science such as Georges Canguilhem, Raymond Ruyer and Gilbert Simondon returned to Jacob‘s statement with an odd kind of pathos: they were determined to reverse course. Not by imposing a different kind of research program in laboratories, but by an unusual combination of historical and philosophical inquiry into the foundations of the life sciences (particularly medicine, physiology and the cluster of activities that were termed ‗biology‘ in the early 1800s). Even in as straightforwardly scholarly a work as La formation du concept de réflexe aux XVIIe et XVIIIe siècles (1955), Canguilhem speaks oddly of ―defending vitalist biology,‖ and declares that Life cannot be grasped by logic (or at least, ―la vie déconcerte la logique‖). Was all this historical and philosophical work merely a reassertion of ‗mysterian‘, magical vitalism? In order to answer this question we need to achieve some perspective on Canguilhem‘s ‗vitalism‘, notably with respect to its philosophical influences such as Kurt Goldstein.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R. J. Gómez WHAT IS THAT THING CALLED PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY? R. J. Gómez Department of Philosophy. California State University (LA). USA Keywords: Adorno, Aristotle, Bunge, Ellul, Feenberg, Habermas, Heidegger, Horkheimer, Jonas, Latour, Marcuse, Mumford, Naess, Shrader-Frechette, artifact, assessment, determinism, ecosophy, ends, enlightenment, efficiency, epistemology, enframing, ideology, life-form, megamachine, metaphysics, method, naturalistic, fallacy, new, ethics, progress, rationality, rule, science, techno-philosophy Contents 1. Introduction 2. Locating technology with respect to science 2.1. Structure and Content 2.2. Method 2.3. Aim 2.4. Pattern of Change 3. Locating philosophy of technology 4. Early philosophies of technology 4.1. Aristotelianism 4.2. Technological Pessimism 4.3. Technological Optimism 4.4. Heidegger’s Existentialism and the Essence of Technology 4.5. Mumford’s Megamachinism 4.6. Neomarxism 4.6.1. Adorno-Horkheimer 4.6.2. Marcuse 4.6.3. Habermas 5. Recent philosophies of technology 5.1. L. Winner 5.2. A. Feenberg 5.3. EcosophyUNESCO – EOLSS 6. Technology and values 6.1. Shrader-Frechette Claims 6.2. H Jonas 7. Conclusions SAMPLE CHAPTERS Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary A philosophy of technology is mainly a critical reflection on technology from the point of view of the main chapters of philosophy, e.g., metaphysics, epistemology and ethics. Technology has had a fast development since the middle of the 20th century , especially ©Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (EOLSS) HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aesthetics of Frustration: Diversity and the ASA
    The Aesthetics of Frustration: Diversity and the ASA Sherri Irvin University of Oklahoma As I began to write a more standard aesthetics paper on an entirely different topic, my thoughts turned to several episodes in which scholars of color presented their work at ASA meetings with recep- tions ranging from chilly to hostile. Some have stated that they will not likely return to the ASA due to these experiences. Because I be- lieve the resources of aesthetics can shed considerable light on social and political dynamics, I will examine some aesthetic elements of this situation and use them to inform a schematic proposal about how we might move forward. I don’t have the answers—finding them is not a task for one person, and scholars belonging to the communities that have been margin- alized and excluded in our professional spaces must be centrally involved. But serious discussion of these matters, which have been personally and professionally painful for me and far more so for THE AMERICAN SOCIETY FOR AESTHETICS: others, is badly needed, and I hope this contribution will renew a AN ASSOCIATION FOR AESTHETICS, discussion that was engaged by A.W. Eaton, Charles Peterson, and CRITICISM, AND THEORY OF THE ARTS Paul C. Taylor in the Aesthetics for Birds blog in late 2017. 1. VOLUME 41 NUMBER 2 SUMMER 2021 In 2010, the distinguished legal scholar and Yavapai Supreme Court justice Rebecca Tsosie was plenary speaker at the ASA annual meet- ing. I was struck not only by the critical Indigenous perspective she 1 The Aesthetics of Frustration: Diversity and brought to her discussion of the collection of Native American cul- the ASA tural objects in non-Native museums, but also by her gender pre- by Sherri Irvin sentation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Condition of Material Adequacy Classical Liberals
    CONSTITUTIONAL CAPITALISM: Economic Freedom, Social Justice and the Myth of Modern Liberalism John Tomasi Working draft: please do not quote. Chapter 4: The Condition of Material Adequacy Classical liberals should accept social justice as concept. But what particular conception of social justice should classical liberals affirm? In this chapter, I gather materials to answer this question. With varying degrees of self-consciousness, most every major thinker in the classical liberal tradition affirms some version of what I call the condition of material adequacy. According to this condition, a liberals can advocate the classical liberal institutions of limited government and wide economic liberty only if, in light of a broad-gauged evaluation of the historical and economic realities of the society in question, they believe those institutions are likely to generate an adequate material and social outcome for all citizens. Towards what state of affairs must the provision of the material goods be adequate if, according to classical liberals, the condition 1 of material adequacy is to be satisfied? There are probably as many ways to answer that question as there are classical liberals. I shall suggest, though, that one way is morally most attractive when we consider that question at the level of regime-advocacy that I call political theory. It is this: classical liberal institutions can be advocated only if those institutions are deemed likely to generate social conditions within which citizens might develop the powers they have as free and equal citizens. That is, classical liberal institutions should be advocated only if they are deemed likely to help secure a thickly substantive conception of liberal social justice.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism
    Consequentialism Consequentialism is the view that morality is all about producing the right kinds of overall consequences. Here the phrase “overall consequences” of an action means everything the action brings about, including the action itself. For example, if you think that the whole point of morality is (a) to spread happiness and relieve suffering, or (b) to create as much freedom as possible in the world, or (c) to promote the survival of our species, then you accept consequentialism. Although those three views disagree about which kinds of consequences matter, they agree that consequences are all that matters. So, they agree that consequentialism is true. The utilitarianism of John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham is a well known example of consequentialism. By contrast, the deontological theories of John Locke and Immanuel Kant are nonconsequentialist. Consequentialism is controversial. Various nonconsequentialist views are that morality is all about doing one’s duty, respecting rights, obeying nature, obeying God, obeying one’s own heart, actualizing one’s own potential, being reasonable, respecting all people, or not interfering with others—no matter the consequences. This article describes different versions of consequentialism. It also sketches several of the most popular reasons to believe consequentialism, along with objections to those reasons, and several of the most popular reasons to disbelieve it, along with objections to those reasons. Table of Contents 1. Basic Issues and Simple Versions a. Introduction to Plain Consequentialism b. What is a “Consequence”? c. Plain Scalar Consequentialism d. Expectable Consequentialism and Reasonable Consequentialism e. Dual Consequentialism f. Rule Consequentialism 2. Two Simple Arguments for Consequentialism a.
    [Show full text]
  • Vintage Marjorie Grene: a Review Essay on a Philosophical Testament
    Vintage Marjorie Grene: A Review Essay on A Philosophical Testament Phil Mullins ABSTRACT Key Words: Marjorie Grene, Michael Polanyi, person, ecological epistemology These reflections summarize major themes in Marjorie Grene's A Philosophical Testament. I also highlight Grene's comments on her many years of work with Polanyi and try to draw out some connections between Grene's thought and that of Polanyi. Marjorie Grene, A Philosophical Testament. Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1995. ISBN 0- 8126-9287-X (pbk). $18.95. Introduction Grene notes in her 1995 book A Philosophical Testament that she at first thought she would title the book “Persons”: When I first thought of writing this book, in fact, I meant to call it Persons. But then it turned out to be about a cluster of other topics, focussed especially on matters related to the problem of knowledge, and bringing in a lot of what professional philosophers call necessary conditions for our ways of knowing, or claiming to know, but not very directly about the concept of the person as such. Still, ‘persons’ is the title I thought of for this concluding chapter. Now I’m not sure why. I’ve rambled on about evolution, and reality, and perception and symboling and heaven knows what (173). Grene gives here a brief but fair summary of topics covered in her book, written in her mid eighties. Altogether her book is not tightly focused on a philosophical account of the person, it does treat the topic broadly, as she suggests, and insightfully by addressing a number of related topics that have interested her in her long career.
    [Show full text]
  • Joseph Margolis Aili W
    University of Dayton eCommons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy 2014 Joseph Margolis Aili W. Bresnahan University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub Part of the History of Philosophy Commons eCommons Citation Bresnahan, Aili W., "Joseph Margolis" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 5. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub/5 This Encyclopedia Entry is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Word Count: 3,633 [Main body text: 3,213; Bibliography: 420] Margolis, Joseph (b. 1924), American philosopher of aesthetics, history, science and culture. Methodological Overview. Margolis’ methodology is best located in the pragmatic tradition, broadly construed. His pragmatism lies in his commitment to understanding the world as part of collective and consensual human practice and situated interaction, his embracing of the changing nature of history and science, and in his approach to human knowledge as constructed. In particular this pragmatic bent is evidenced by his affinity for Charles Sanders Peirce’s semeiotics, by which thought shows us the real world through the interpretation of signs and symbols, and the existence of mind is legitimated as “objective” and “real.” Margolis also uses Peirce’s theory of predicative generals (as constructed but existent place-holders that focus discourse) in place of universals (as metaphysically fixed and existent types) as a way to discuss the discursive and indeterminate natures of what he considers to be inherently interpretable and significant properties of cultural artifacts (to be described more fully, below, as Intentional properties of artworks).
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Freedom and Public Argument: John Courtney Murray on “The American Proposition”
    Religious Freedom and Public Argument: John Courtney Murray on “The American Proposition” Robin W. Lovin* In his classic essays in We Hold These Truths, John Courtney Murray developed an understanding of “the American proposition” that integrated a theological account of human good with the search for public consensus in a constitutional democracy. While this understanding of the relationship between religious freedom and political life was incorporated into Catholic social teaching at the Second Vatican Council, subsequent developments in both political theory and theology call Murray’s understanding of public discourse into question. This essay examines these challenges and argues that Murray’s reconciliation of moral truth and political choice is still an important resource for discussion of religious freedom and other moral issues in today’s polarized politics. INTRODUCTION ............................................................................... 25 I. MURRAY’S LEGACY .................................................................... 26 II. THE PUBLIC ARGUMENT ............................................................ 29 III. THE CASE FOR CONSENSUS ...................................................... 32 IV. IS IT GOOD? ............................................................................. 35 V. IS IT POLITICS? .......................................................................... 39 CONCLUSION ................................................................................... 43 INTRODUCTION From the late 1940s
    [Show full text]
  • Evaluating Public Philosophy in Higher Education: Lessons Learned Baking Philosophical Bread
    EVALUATING PUBLIC PHILOSOPHY IN HIGHER EDUCATION: LESSONS LEARNED BAKING PHILOSOPHICAL BREAD ANTHONY CASHIO (University of Virginia, Wise) & ERIC THOMAS WEBER (University of Kentucky) In the Last decade, there has been a resurgence of public phiLosophy. Many institutional structures and chalLenges impede or impose heavy costs on phiLosophers interested in public engagement. The American PhiLosophical Association has called for the development of tools for recognizing, evaLuating, supporting, and rewarding public phiLosophy. This essay offers a proposaL incLuding four concepts that couLd be usefuL for the fruitfuL evaLuation of pubLic phiLosophy in higher education: substance, accessibility, invitingness, and community-building. These concepts have arisen out of the authors’ experience with engaged public phiLosophy by means of the syndicated and award-winning PhiLosophy Bakes Bread radio show and podcast that Launched in January of 2017. The four concepts we propose for evaLuating public phiLosophy arise centraLLy in the work that we do and couLd offer a valuable starting point for the recognition and much needed support for public phiLosophical work in higher education. Volume 2 · Number 1 · Spring 2018 · Pages 72-94 Anthony Cashio & Eric Thomas Weber 73 n 2017, the American PhiLosophical Association released a statement drafted by its Committee on Public PhiLosophy calling I for members of the profession to encourage and reward quaLity work in public phiLosophy and to develop tools for evaLuating such work professionalLy.1 The need for evaLuating public phiLosophicaL work calls for systematic thinking about the vaLue of public phiLosophy and remains one of the movement’s challenges. While there are many nuanced forms of public phiLosophy and some usefuL considerations 1 APA Communications, “APA Statement on Valuing Public Philosophy,” The Blog of the APA, May 18, 2017, https://bLog.apaonLine.org/2017/05/18/apa-statement- on-vaLuing-pubLic-phiLosophy/.
    [Show full text]
  • Investigations of Worth: Towards a Phenomenology of Values Dale Hobbs Jr
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Dissertations (2009 -) Dissertations, Theses, and Professional Projects Investigations of Worth: Towards a Phenomenology of Values Dale Hobbs Jr. Marquette University Recommended Citation Hobbs, Dale Jr., "Investigations of Worth: Towards a Phenomenology of Values" (2017). Dissertations (2009 -). 740. http://epublications.marquette.edu/dissertations_mu/740 INVESTIGATIONS OF WORTH: TOWARDS A PHENOMENOLOGY OF VALUES by Dale (D.J.) Hobbs A Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School, Marquette University, in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Milwaukee, WI August 2017 ABSTRACT INVESTIGATIONS OF WORTH: TOWARDS A PHENOMENOLOGY OF VALUES Dale (D.J.) Hobbs Marquette University, 2017 The purpose of this dissertation is to provide a clear and compelling account of the existence and nature of values within a phenomenological context. Values such as beauty or virtue are certainly a major part of our experiential lives. After all, what would life be worth if we could never describe a painting as beautiful, for example, or a beverage as delicious? Nevertheless, understanding what these values are on their own terms has historically been a rather difficult task. Certainly, they are not ordinary objects that could be seen or heard, touched or tasted, like the physical objects to which they seem to be connected in some mysterious way. In this dissertation, I argue that a phenomenological approach enables us to give a solid account of the role that values play in experience. Working in dialogue with Husserl and other phenomenologists and related thinkers (especially Max Scheler and Nicolai Hartmann), as well as with recent commentary, I develop my own account of values as lying on the phenomenological “horizons” of experience.
    [Show full text]
  • From Knowledge to Ontological Awakening: Thinking Nature As Relatedness
    The Trumpeter ISSN: 0832-6193 Volume 28, Number 1 (2012) From Knowledge to Ontological Awakening: Thinking Nature as Relatedness To Alan, a great mentor, friend and mountain whisperer Introduction Many environmental scholars and activists have suggested the need of a profound shift of consciousness when it comes to our relationships with Nature (Naess 2008, Merchant 2005, Mathews 2005, Eckersley 2003, Goldsmith 1996). In addition of greening our political ideas, institutions and technologies, they suggest that we need to critically engage the paradigms by which we conceive Nature. The task of clarifying what we mean by Nature has however become increasingly difficult due to the supremacy of an epistemology hostile to metaphysical reflections (Hay 2007, Marsh and Furlong 2002), and the spread of a constructivist and relativistic understanding of the many ways in which humans comprehend Nature (Daly 2008, Dingler 2005, Soper 1995, Meyer 2001). Answering what Nature is has become a daring question, not only because of the supremacy of an epistemology increasingly de-anchored from ontology, but also following the various abuses generated by various essentialist interpretations of what Nature ought to be. As a result, many scholars now prudently claim to speak only about the social and political “effects” of evoking “Nature.” Others are ready to discard this notion altogether, assimilating what would be “Nature” into a cultural scheme prone to challenge all forms of dualism as arbitrary exclusion and all forms of monism as forced inclusion (Morton
    [Show full text]
  • A Personal Remembrance of Marjorie Grene
    Profile Marjorie, Matriarchy, and “Wretched Reflection”: A Personal Remembrance of Marjorie Grene Vassiliki Betty Smocovitis people were honored as presidents (including Marjorie) at its Departments of Biology and History inception. University of Florida I attended the summer meetings organized by Marjorie Gainesville, FL, USA and Dick, mostly because of the stunning list of luminaries. As bsmocovi@ufl.edu a graduate student in ecology and evolutionary biology, keen on paleobotany, I was just too dazzled by the likes of Stephen J. Gould and Niles Eldredge to remember much else (this was at the peak of “punk eek” mania), but I do vaguely recall Marjorie That’s wretched. I don’t want to think about who I am! and Dick sitting together in rickety wooden chairs near the — Marjorie Grene, Interview with Benjamin R. Cohen, front row in a room absolutely crowded with bodies. It was The Believer, March 2009 later, in the winter months, that I finally met Marjorie, face to face, in Karl Niklas’s office. They were meeting regularly In biological terms, the word “matriarch” is associated with to read Willi Hennig’s work—then all the rage—in German. a particular kind of social organization, one where the female As my doctoral advisor, Karl wanted me to meet someone he serves as leader of the group. For those keen on the natural described as a “legend in her own time.” I vividly remember world, it oftentimes conjures up a huge, lumbering elephant, that meeting—she was seated in a chair immediately opposite gently guiding and protecting her progeny with her trunk, fol- him looking like a caricature of the eternal Radcliffe graduate, lowed by a group of female relatives and adolescents (while or a character out of an Iris Murdoch novel from the 1950s: all the while, the males are off being “rogue”).
    [Show full text]