Fragmentability, a foundational systems concept

Löfgren, Lars

Published in: Cybernetics and systems 2000

2000

Link to publication

Citation for published version (APA): Löfgren, L. (2000). Fragmentability, a foundational systems concept. In R. Trappl (Ed.), Cybernetics and systems 2000 (Vol. 1, pp. 15-20). Austrian Society for Cybernetic Studies.

Total number of authors: 1

General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal

Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim.

LUND UNIVERSITY

PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 FRAGMENTABILITY, A FOUNDATIONAL SYSTEMS CONCEPT

LARS LÖFGREN

University of Lund

Printed in: Cybernetics and Systems 2000, edited by Robert Trappl, Austrian Society of Cybernetic Studies, Vienna, Vol. 1, 2000, pp. 15-20. ISBN 3-85206-151-2 A latest proof of the paper is what follows.

Fragmentability, a Foundational Systems Concept

Lars Loefgren (email: [email protected]) Systems Theory, University of Lund, Box 118, S–221 00 Lund

[Printed in: Cybernetics and Systems ’00, Vol. 1, pp 15-20 (2000). Editor: Trappl, R, University of Vienna and Austrian Society for Cybernetic Studies]

Abstract Fragmentation problem.Isnature in itself fragmentable, and thereby non- Fragmentation is a fundamental process, be- distortively describable, or, is it our linguis- neath the level of . Fragmentation oc- tic description processes which make nature curs in our most everyday activities. We appear fragmentable. analyse (literally, to break into fragments), describe, and interpret by performing frag- The involved notion of (non-)distortive may be clari- mentations. fied with an example from quantum mechanics. Con- We propose a linguistic concept of fragmen- sider an entangled EPR pair of particles. They may tation, namely a complementaristic whole have become light years apart, suggesting that the pair of “syntactic fragmentation” and “semantic is fragmented into two parts, the individual particles. fragmentation”, as foundational for Systems But such a fragmentation turns out distortive on the and, in particular, General Systems. pair as a quantum mechanical entity (where entangle- ment indicates an unbreakable quantum correlation between the particles). 1 Fragmentation and Unification Further examples of unbreakable wholes, i.e., wholes that will be distorted when operated upon by a clas- Every description, even a whole descriptive theory, is sical fragmentation, will be given subsequently. Lan- a description of something, not everything. Indeed, we guage itself will prove a prime example. do describe by making fragmentations. Were it not for The concept of nature, occurring in the Fragmenta- the remarkable property of nature that it seemingly tion Problem, is to be understood constructively, as allows fragmentation, as in our becoming conscious of in Linguistic Realism [L¨ofgren L, 1993]. Accordingly, a particular phenomenon as target for description, or we are open to a reality including human constructs – as in the isolation of a particular physical phenomenon as well as (complementaristically conceived; in an experimental -up for measuring an observable, see below). What may be distortive on this scale of every attempt at describing nature would fail. linguistic realism, requires an evolutionary perspec- Chew explaines further: tive. The fragmentary growth of knowledge, particularly [Chew G, 1968]. “A key discovery of Western into scientific disciplines, creates unification problems, culture has been the discovery that different like quests for disciplines with larger, unifying do- aspects of nature can be individually ‘un- mains. derstood’ in an approximate sense without everything’s being understood at once. All Unification Problem. Is there a unifying phenomena ultimately are interconnected, so understanding of fragmented scientific disci- an attempt to understand only a part neces- plines? sarily leads to some error, but the error is sufficiently small for the partial approach to A first natural proposal would be an interdisciplinary be meaningful. Save for this remarkable and understanding. This presupposes however a rather far from obvious property of nature, scientific classical part-whole view, as if various disciplines progress would be impossible.” (parts) can be joined together, possibly extended with new rules for previously not covered parts of the larger We may look upon this view as suggestive of a frag- domain of inquiry. Compare as well earlier, classical mentation problem. formulations of so called inductive rules of inference, where induction is looked at as some sort of general- both these extremes [the first referring to doctrine II, izing inference from particular observed facts. which is similar to I]. However, as we now think of induction, [L¨ofgren L, 1982], it is not an inference from particulars – but a Part-hole doctrine III. [Russell B, 1966, process bringing forth hidden properties of the lan- pages 333-334]: “Can we state all that we guage in use. That is, properties beyond analytic de- know without the use of any basic proposi- ductive accessibility within the . Such prop- tions of the form “P is part of W”? In ask- erties are acquired in the evolution of the language, ing this question it is supposed that “P” and in its adaptation to environments for which it works. “W” are proper names. It is assumed that They are accounted for in the complementaristic con- we can experience a whole W without know- ception of language (section 3). Complementaristic ing what its parts are, but that, by atten- conceivability will provide an answer to the unifica- tion and noticing, we can gradually discover tion problem as well as to a quest for noncumulative more and more of its parts. It is not assumed growth of knowledge. that this process must stop short of complete analysis, nor is it assumed that it can be car- 2 Fragmentability of Wholes; earlier ried to the point at which the parts that have insights been arrived at are incapable of further anal- ysis. But it is assumed that the whole W can By way of introduction to our complementaristic con- preserve its identity throughout the process cept of fragmentation (section 4) let us collect some of analysis: that, e.g., in perception we can earlier formulations of basic fragmentation hypothe- begin with “W!”, as an exclamatory use of ses and doctrines. an object-word, and arrive, by attention, at “P is part of W”, without any change in the In Russell’s chapter on Analysis in [Russell B, 1961], denotation of the name “W”. he writes: The following part-whole characterization is devel- “The operation by which, from examination oped in a wide evolutionary context, relevant for the of a whole W, we arrive at ’P is part of W’, so called systems movement (see [Klir G, 1991, chap- is called ’analysis’. It has two forms: logical ter 3]). analysis, and analysis into spatio-temporal parts.” Part-hole doctrine IV. Smuts 1926 Holism and Evolution,quotedin[Klir G, Russell’s categorical fragmentation here, the separa- 1991, page 29]: “A whole is a synthesis or tion of the two forms of analysis, indicates that he is unity of parts, so close that it affects the ac- on a classical (noncomplementaristic) ground allowing tivities and interactions of those parts, im- classical analysis of fragmentation. No complemen- presses on them a special character, and taristic relations between the two forms of analysis makes them different from what they would are hinted at. have been in a combination devoid of such unity or synthesis. That is the fundamental [ Part-hole doctrine, I. Russell B, 1961, element in the concept of the whole. It is a ] page 157 : “the parts of a complex whole are complex of parts, but so close and intimate, different, as combined in that whole, from so unified that the characters and relations what they would otherwise be.” and activities of the parts are affected and Part-Whole Doctrine II. [Russell B, 1966, changed.” ] page 327 “From the earliest times, many A fragmentation principle, which is often hidden philosophers have objected to analysis: they deep in foundational logical issues, is the principle of have maintained that analysis is falsification, compositionality. that a whole does not really consist of parts suitably arranged, and that, if we mention The principle of compositionality says any part singly, the act of isolation so alters that the semantic attributes of a complex it that what we have mentioned is not an expression are functions of the semantic at- organic part of the whole.” tributes of its constituent expressions.

[Russell B, 1966, page 327] also recalls a principle of The principle presupposes fragmentabilities on both atomicity “which may be said to forbid synthesis. Lin- syntactic and semantic levels and states a recursive- guistically, it forbids the giving of proper names to like correlation. complex wholes, at any rate when they are recognized [Hintikka J, 1996, page 106]: “Tarski had an early to be complex.” For my part, says Russell, I reject form of a categorical grammar. Any approach like categorical grammar presupposes certain things of the language in use. As if the language could be detached semantics of the language whose grammar it is supp- from the ideas we are talking about. Such impressions posed to be. It presupposes that the language in ques- fade away, however, when we try to objectify, or con- tion satisfies the requirement which linguists usually ceptualize, language. We then realize our linguistic call compositionality. Philosophers sometimes refer to predicament: to objectify language in language. it as the Frege principle, and Frege did indeed pay lip On the basis of several earlier investigations of lan- service to it. As usually formulated it says that the guage phenomena, from genetic language, through meaning of a complex expression is a function of the programming language, formal language, observation meanings of its constituent expressions. It is neverthe- language, inner cerebral language, to external com- less appropriate to extend the idea of compositionality munication language, we have come to the conclusion to say that all the relevant semantical attributes of an that there is a common concept of language, of which expression (and not only just its meaning or truth) all these phenomena are species. are functions of the semantical attributes of its con- stituent expressions (not just of its meaning). The Language, in its general conception, is a major impact of the principle of compositionality on whole of complementary description and in- logical and linguistic theorizing is to allow what is usu- terpretation processes. ally referred to as recursive definitions (or other kinds of recursive characterization) of the relevant semanti- The involved concept of complementarity, the linguis- cal properties. That is to say, we can specify the con- tic complementarity, is to be understood as follows. ditions for the applicability of the semantical attribute in question to the simplest possible expressions, and The linguistic complementarity. In general, com- then specify, step by step, for each operation of form- plementarity refers to holistic situations where (a clas- ing complex expressions out of the simpler ones, how sical) fragmentation into parts does not succeed. In applicability of that semantical attribute to the com- its complementaristic understanding, the phenomenon plex expression is derived on the semantical attributes of language is such a whole of description and inter- of its constituent expressions. ... pretation processes, yet a whole which has no such The real impact nevertheless has not been emphasized parts fully expressible within the language itself. In- in recent discussion. It is illustrated by the role of stead, within the language, the parts are complemen- the principle in facilitating recursive definitions of se- tary or tensioned (rather than classically contradic- mantical attributes. Such recursive definitions pro- tory). There are various related ways of looking at ceed from simpler expressions to more complicated the complementarity: ones. They are not possible unless the attribute to be defined is semantically speaking context independent. (i) as descriptional incompleteness: in no language The main function of the principle of compositionality can its process be completely de- is to secure such semantical context-independence.” scribed in the language itself; [Hintikka J and Sandu G, 1996] exhibit an “inde- pendence friendly” first order which violates the (ii) as a tension between describability and inter- principle of compositionality. The authors look at the pretability within a language: increased describa- semantical incompleteness of this logic as its most pro- bility implies decreased interpretability, and con- foundly revolutionary feature. versely;

Let us next, as a preliminary to the language-based (iii) as degrees of partiality of self–reference (in- fragmentation concept, recall the complementaristic trospection) within a language: complete self– concept of language [L¨ofgren L, 1992]. reference within a language is impossible; (iv) as a principle of “nondetachability of language”. 3 General Language – a Complement- aristic Whole The linguistic closure. Our thinking abilities are Phenomena of language are at the bottom of all hu- usually looked upon as free and unbounded. But man activity and are, indeed, at the roots of all forms when it comes to communicable thought, we are con- of life as genetic processes. The phenomena are ex- fined to some shared communication language. The tremely rich, and exceedingly difficult to conceptualize systemic wholeness, or the complementaristic na- without distorting them in the act. Yet, at the same ture, of this language implies a closure, or circum- time, our communication languages are so natural and scription, of our linguistic abilities – be they “pure easy for us to use that we hardly notice them. It is thoughts” communicable in a formal mathematical as if they were universal, as if what we are saying had language, or constructive directions for an experimen- an absolute meaning which were independent of the tal interpretation-domain of a physics language. The nature of this closure is not that of a classical bound- Carnap’s fragmentation thesis for ary of a capacity, like describability, or interpretabil- [Carnap R, 1942, page 9].Ifwe ity. It is a tensioned and hereditary boundary of the are analyzing a language, then we are con- systemic capacity of describability-and-interpretability cerned, of course, with expressions. But we admitting potentialities in two directions: need not necessarily also deal with speakers and designata. Although these factors are (a) The closure is tensioned. Within the language present whenever language is used, we may there is a tension between describability and inter- abstract from one or both of them in what we pretability (view (ii) of the linguistic complementar- intend to say about the language in question. ity), whereby it may be possible to increase the de- Accordingly, we distinguish three fields of in- scribability at the cost of a lowered interpretability, vestigation of languages [pragmatics, seman- and conversely. In other words, what the closure tics, syntax]. The whole science of language, bounds off is neither describability, nor interpretabil- consisting of the three parts mentioned, is ity, but their interactive whole as a linguistic unit of called semiotic. describability-and-interpretability. True that the assumed fragmentability may be de- (b) The closure is hereditary. Languages evolve, scribed in a , provided one such exists. and at a later time we can have access to another But “the whole science of language” is not a science shared communication language of greater communi- unless connected with a language (in which it is de- cation capacity. However, we are then back to the lin- scribed). That is, the actual language (with no appeal guistic predicament: ateachtimewetrytocommu- to some metalanguage; cf the linguistic predicament) nicate thoughts – even introspective thoughts about for which the fragmentation is supposed to hold. But, language and their evolution – we are confined to a by our analysis of language, this fragmentation cannot shared language, however evolved, and the linguistic be made within this language itself. What is miss- complementarity of that language restricts our com- ing in Carnap’s account of semiotics, as “the whole municability in the tensioned way according to (a). science of language”, is a complementaristic between the suggested parts. In other words, if Car- 4 Language-Based Fragmentation napian semiotics is considered the whole science of language, it is distortive of language as in linguistic A fragmentation of a whole produces parts (frag- realism. ments) of the whole. The parts must be distinguish- We suggest that semiotics be developed accordingly. able. Otherwise, by Leibniz’s principle, indistinguish- Also, that pragmatics be understood in terms of the able parts coalesce and the fragmentation of the whole processual nature of the description and interpretation is nullified. processes. Fragmentability is thus intimately connected with The complementaristic concept of language is a distinguishability, and distinguishability with describ- whole which satisfies the part-whole doctrines I, II, ability. See [L¨ofgren L, 1966] for distinguishability (of and IV (section 2). For example, the stipulation that elements in a domain) as describability (of the do- “the parts of a complex whole are different, as com- main). bined in that whole, from what they would other- Again, describability is complementaristically re- wise be”, holds for language. Its constituent inter- lated with interpretability. This means that fragmen- acting description and interpretation processes, pro- tation, visualized as occurring in the interpretation ducing descriptions and interpretations, are intuitively domain of a language, is nonseparable from a frag- clear in a classical global perspective (with descrip- mentation view in the description domain. tions as finitely representable, static, objects – with Fragmentation is objectifiable as a lin- meanings, or interpretations, beyond any such restric- guistic phenomenon, a whole of “syntactic tions). However, when these parts are made objects fragmentation” complementaristically inter- for investigation in the language itself, they become related with “semantic fragmentation”. non-classical tensioned objects. The assumption in doctrine III, “that we can expe- To help clarify the complementaristic nature of frag- rience a whole W without knowing what its parts are”, mentation, and of language, we want to mention a con- is satisfied by complementaristic conceivability, recog- trasting earlier understanding of language in terms of nizing human conception of description-interpretation semiotics, proposed by Carnap in the early 40’s (with wholes. beliefs in classical unification principles). He suggests The principle of compositionality is not assumed for a classical fragmentability of the whole science of lan- complementaristic language. Rather, the role of the guage (not reflecting any complementaristic quality of principle to secure semantical context-independence, language). seems more in line with a Carnapian fragmentability of semiotics, than with, say, the principle of nonde- This is indeed a genuine fragmentation problem. With tachability of language. the “pie” conceived as in linguistic realism, General Systems Theory ought to study presuppositions for 5 Systems Movements Towards sets and for systems, and to understand fragmentabil- Unifying Foundations ity accordingly. That may seem to require a General Systems Language with a complementaristic account [Klir G, 1991, chapter 3] provides an interesting ac- of such presuppositions and their fragmentability. count of movements towards unification as characteris- tic for the emergence of systems concepts and systems Traces of such a shift from theory to language may thinking. Klir notices that current systems thinking, be seen in Rosens first remark on “ systems”. in studying the relationship between wholes and parts, Recall how G¨odel, in his revised conception of a “for- goes far beyond thinking molded from either reduc- mal system” includes with the “pure” syntax also a tionism or holism. He points at the recognition of complementary semantic appeal to Turing machines interdisciplinary domains as a step towards recogniz- (whereby a proof-regress is avoided; cf [L¨ofgren L, ing systemhood, elaborated in [Rosen R, 1986] in a 1998]). foundational setting. In our view, there is an undisputable unifying ef- 5.2 On Spencer-Brown’s Laws of Form fect in foundational studies. Various disciplins recog- nize different domains of inquiry, and work with differ- [Spencer Brown G, 1969, page v]:“The theme ent presuppositions create unification problems. The of this book is that a universe comes into be- more the presuppositions can be explicitly revealed, ing when a space is severed or taken apart. the better can an interdisciplinary communication be ... developed. Revelation of presuppositions is an act of By tracing the way we represent such a sev- introspection in the language in which a discipline is erance, we can begin to reconstruct, with an – inductively and deductively – developed. Such in- accuracy and coverage that appear almost trospective acts are what we usually call foundational. uncanny, the basic forms underlying linguis- Deep foundational studies do not merely refer to dis- tic, mathematical, physical, and biological ciplines as context dependent. They take the context science, and can begin to see how the familiar all the way to language as the ultimate frame of ref- laws of our own experience follow inexorably erence for communicable knowledge (cf the linguistic from the original act of severance.” closure for the general complementaristic concept of language). Here we have an attempt at fragmentation (severance, Let us very briefly comment on some steps in the taking apart) as a foundational concept, inviting com- movements towards system out from fragmentability parison with linguistic fragmentation as a complemen- as a foundational systems concept. taristic whole of “syntactic fragmentation” and “se- mantic fragmentation”, By contrast, Spencer Brown 5.1 On Rosen’s Critical Comparison of works with a compositionality that reduces to syntac- Systemhood with Sethood tic forms. Attempting to answer the question what a system is, To say “that a universe comes into being when a [ ] Rosen R, 1986 compares the concept of system with space is severed or taken apart” obviously presupposes that of set. In spite of many parallels, Rosen crit- an already existing linguistic fragmentability. Spencer ically distinguishes between “systemhood” and “set- Brown works with fragmentability as unproblematic, ness” and suggests that: as if perfect fragmentations can always be made (“dis- “since the axiom systems in terms of which tinction is perfect continence”). Such presuppositions set-ness is characterized are themselves sys- may be defended in strictly discrete universes. tems, it may well be that attempts to define But consider a language, say a mathematical lan- systemhood in terms of set-ness is cart be- guage, where for example choice processes occur. fore horse. ... Even though these can be partially axiomatized, as The task of General Systems Theory is a choice functions beyond rules, they show up as inde- large one. It is not only to characterize pendent . Mathematical reasoning in a math- and study the notion of systemhood, and the ematical language may well use processes which are properties which depend only upon it. More beyond full syntactical description in the language. than this, it is up to General Systems The- To understand language, as the complementaristic ory to divide the pie between what we have phenomenon it is, in terms of fragmentation it is neces- called thinghood, set-ness and systemhood, sary to recognice also fragmentation as as complemen- and study the hybrid properties which de- taristic phenomenon. A pure syntactic fragmentation pend on more than one of these primitives.” will not suffice, not even for pure mathematics. 5.3 On Self-Reference [Klir G, 1991] Facets of Systems Science. New York: [Varela F, 1975] attempts an extension of the calcu- Plenum Press. lus of indications of Spencer Brown “to encompass all [L¨ofgren L, 1966] “Explicability of Sets and Transfi- occurrences of self-referential situations”. nite Automata.” In Caianiello, E, ed., Automata However, reference is centrally linguistic, and self- Theory. New York: Academic Press, 251–268. reference refers to (features of) the language in which it occurs. Complete self-reference is impossible (view [L¨ofgren L, 1982] “Methodologies and the Induction iii of the linguistic complementarity). Self-reference is Problem.” In Trappl R, Klir G and Pichler F, eds. always partial. For a study of this partiality we refer Progress in Cybernetics and Systems Research,vol to [L¨ofgren L, 1990]. 8. Washington, New York, London: Hemisphere, Varela does not refer to language, and not to the 15–22. necessary partiality of self-reference. However, in his [L¨ofgren L, 1990] “On the Partiality of Self-Refer- conclusions, he refers to a separation between observer ence.” Pp 47-64 in Heylighen F, Rosseel E, De- and observed. He suggests that: meyere F, eds., Self-Steering and in Com- [Varela F, 1975, page 22] “In contrast with plex Systems. New York: Gordon and Breach. what is commonly assumed, a description, [L¨ofgren L, 1992] “Complementarity in Language: when carefully inspected, reveals the prop- Toward a General Understanding.” Pp 113-153 in erties of the observer. We observers, dis- Carvallo M, ed., Nature, Cognition and System II. tinguish ourselves precisely by distinguishing Dordrecht: Kluwer. what we apparently are not, the world.” [L¨ofgren L, 1993] “Linguistic Realism and Issues in In [L¨ofgren L, 1996, page 335] we have explained var- Quantum .” In Laurikainen K and Mon- ious presuppositions needed to make this formulation tonen C, eds., Symposia on the Foundations of Mod- (of “post-objectivity” in second-order cybernetics) ap- ern Physics 1992 : the Copenhagen Interpretation preciable. and Wolfgang Pauli. Singapore-NewJersey-London- 5.4 Time HongKong: World Scientific, 297-318. For a recent study of the fragmentation problem for [L¨ofgren L, 1996] “Shadows of Language in Physics time we refer to [L¨ofgren L, 2000]. and Cybernetics.” Systems Research, 13, 329-339. [ ] 6 Conclusion L¨ofgren L, 1998 “Nonseparability of Inferribility and Measurability General System, in contrast to more disciplinary do- in Quantum Mechanics as a Systema Magnum.” Pp mains, is supposed not to overlook problems of syn- 113-118 in Trappl R, ed., Cybernetics and Systems thesis – which usually are abstracted away in reduc- ’98, vol. 1. Vienna: Austrian Society for Cybernetic tionistic studies towards “disciplinary foundations”. Studies. Yet, to understand General Systems, we are forced to perform fragmentations that are tied with descrip- [L¨ofgren L, 2000] “Understandings of Time in Com- tions and interpretations of the subject. The com- plementaristic Language.” Chapter 3, pp 37-51, in plementaristic concept of fragmentation is proposed Baert, Patrick, editor, Time in Contemporary In- as foundational for Systems, in particular for General tellectual Thought. Amsterdam: Nort-Holland, El- Systems. sevier Science. [Rosen R, 1986] “Some Comments on Systems and References System Theory”. Int J General Systems, 13,1-3. [Carnap R, 1942] Introduction to Semantics and For- [Russell B, 1961] Our Knowledge of the External malization of Logic. Cambridge, Massachusetts: World. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. First Harward University Press. published in 1914. [Chew G, 1968] “Bootstrap: a Scientific Idea?” Sci- [Russell B, 1966] An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth. ence, 161, 762-765. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. First pub- [Hintikka J, 1996] The Principles of Mathematics Re- lished in 1940. visited. Cambridge, Mass.: Cambridge University [Spencer Brown G, 1969] Laws of Form. London: Press. Lowe and Brydone. [Hintikka J and Sandu G, 1996] [Varela F, 1975] “A Calculus for Self-Reference.” Int A Revolution in Logic? Nord. J. Philos. Log., 1, J General Systems, 2, 5-24. 169-183.