The Philosophy of Logic of Hugh Maccoll John Spencer the Philosophy of Logic of Hugh Maccoll

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Philosophy of Logic of Hugh Maccoll John Spencer the Philosophy of Logic of Hugh Maccoll ·. THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC OF HUGH MACCOLL JOHN SPENCER THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC OF HUGH MACCOLL Department of Philosophy Ph.D. Candidate The Introduction to this study sketches the history of propositional modal logic from Aristotle to the nineteenth century. MacColl's life and influences are also described. The first chapter traces out the development of the concept of implication in MacColl. Bince implication is central to MacColl's logic, this chapter also serves as a commentary on the development of his logic as a whole. A quasi-axiomatic system is presented which represents MacColl's completed system. In developing his system, MacCol1 divided statements into true, false, certain, impossible and variable. The second chapter examines in detail these categories of statements. Chapter Three examines MacColl's theory of logical existence. MacCol1 divided the universe of discourse into the sub-universes of realities and unrealities. By doing so he created a two-sorted theory of quantification. He adrnitted into the uni verse of discourse possible though non-existent objects. The conclusion com­ pares sorne of C.I. Lewis's central views in logic with those of MacColl. It is argued that MacCol1 anticipated a great deal of Lewis and that it is not implausible to suggest that MacCol1 directly influenced Lewis. It is suggested that MacCol1 should be regarded as one of the founders of modern modal logic. THE PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC OF HUGH MACCOLL BY JOHN R. SPENCER A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. Department of Philosophy McGill University ..... ,', . ., •. _ ._" 1 - -- .:' : ••\ ......J 1 . -, cv J obn R. Spencer 1973 PREFACE This thesis is submitted in partial require­ ment for the Ph.D. Degree at McGi11 University. It is the first full-Iength study of the logic of Hugh MacColl. After a detailed exarnination of MacColl's logic, it is argued that he is one of the founders of modern modal logic. This thesis was prepared under the direction of Professor John Trentrnan to whom l would like to express my appreciation for his advice and encouragement. Professor Harry Bracken also read drafts of the thesis and made many helpful suggestions. TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page Introduction i xvi 1- Implication 1 2. Division of Statements 58 3. Existential Import 94 4. MacColl's Influence 118 Bibliography 132 " INTRODUCTION Hugh MacColl developed a symbolic modal logic in the last quarter of the nineteenth century. Although his work was highly original it does fit squarely into a tradition dating from antiquity, a tradition of which MacColl was almost totally ignorant. In the following few pages this tradition will be briefly sketched, touching only on those points which relate directly to MacColl. Modal logic begins, as does formaI logic itself, as a general and systematic science, with Aristotle. In chapters twelve and thirteen of De Interpretationel Aristotle considers the relations between 'possible to bel and 'possible not to bel, 'necessary' and 'impossible' and 'admissible' and 'not admissible'. He first attempts to arrive at the proper negation for 'possible to bel. He considers 'possible not to bel as the negation of 'possible to bel but this is rejected since it is clearly possible for the same thing to be and possibly not to be. If these were contradictory expressions they could not apply to the same thing; hence, 'possibly not to bel cannot be the contradiction of 'possibly to bel. Similarly with 'admissible to bel, 'necessary' and 'impossible' whose negations are 'not admissible to bel, 'not necessary' and 'not impossible'. The 1 Aristotle's Cate ories and De Inter retatione Translated by J. L. Ackrl.ll. Oxford: Clarendon Pres,s, 1963). negation of 'possible not to bel is 'not possible not to bel. After noting this Aristotle then writes: This is why 'possible to bel and 'possible not to bel may be thought actually to follow from one another. For it is possible for the same thing to be and not to be; such statements are not contradictories of one another. But 'possible to bel and 'not possible to bel never hold together, because they are opposites.2 This is important since it is clear that simply from the fact that 'possible to bel and 'possible not to bel are not contradictories it does not follow that they follow from one another. Aristotle then raises the question of whether 'possible to bel follows from ' necessary to bel. If it does not then 'not possible to bel would, reasons Aristotle. But, he notes, it cannot be the case that if something is necessary it is not possible. Therefore, 'possible to bel would appear to follow from 'necessary to bel. But Aristotle has already stated that 'possible not to bel follows from 'possible to be'; hence, 'possible not to bel would follow from 'necessary to bel which is absurd and which would also conflict with Aristotle's claim that "what is of necessity is in actuality".3 2 Ibid., p. 61 3 Ibid., p. 68 -iii- Aristotle does not successfully resolve this difficulty in De Interpretatione; he does not see clearly that he is dealing with two senses of possible, one of which expresses the concept of contingency, the other of not being impossible. He is, however, aware that there is a problem here. In the Prior Analytics Aristotle clears up this confusion somewhat by noting that there are two senses of 'possible'; a proposition is possible if it is not necessary and, being assumed, results in nothing impossible, and a proposition is possible if it simply follows from one which is necessary.4 He then notes that the expressions lit is not possible to belong', lit is impossible to belong' and 'i-c is necessary not to belong' are either idential or follow from one another. Likewise with the expressions lit is possible to belong', lit is not impossible to belong' and lit is not necessary not to belong'. He then adds "That which is possible then will be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible".5 This indicates that the sense of 'possible' Aristotle is working with is that often expressed by 'contingent' rather than that expressed by simply 'not impossible'. 4 Aristotle, Analytica Priora. The Works of Aristotle Translated into English ed. W. D. Ross. Vol. 1. (London: Oxford University Press, 1928) 32a, 18-21 5 Ibid., 32a, 21. - iv- Although the treatment of modal syllogisms found in the Prior Analytics is mainly beside the point for the purposes of this study (since it is primarily concerned with the development, in MacColl, of a propositional modal logic), several theses of interest to it are found in De Interpretatione. For instance, from 'not possible not to bel follows 'necessary to bel; and from 'not possible to bel, 'impossible to be,.6 These theses are at the center of the first systematic working out of the relations among modal concepts. The Megarian and Stoic logicians also attempted to work out certain modal ideas and gave definitions of implication using modal concepts. According to Boethius Diodorus gave the following account of modal concepts: Diodorus defines the possible as that which either is or will be • • • the impossible as that which, being false, will not be true • . • the necessary as that which, being true, will not be false • and the non-necessary as ~hat which either is already or will be false. The above definitions carry a strong temporal flavour which is also found in MacColl's earliest comments on modal con- cepts. As is the case with MacColl's early work there is a strong tendency in Diodorus to collapse the distinctions between necessarily true and (merely) true and impossible and 6 Ibid., 22a 7 William Kneale and Martha Kneale, The Development of Logic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968) p. 117. - v - (merely) false. This temporal interpretation is also carried over to the conclusion of Diodorus's Master Argument which is "nothing is possible which neither is nor will be true". 8 Boethius gives the following account of Philo's views which differ greatly from those of Diodorus. Philo says that the possible is that which by the intrinsic nature of the assertion admits of truth • • • , as when, for example l say that l shall read the Bucolics of Theocritus again today. If no external circumstances prevent·· this, then considered in itself ••• the thing can be affirmed truly. In the same way this same Philo defines the necessary as that which, being true, can never, considered in itself, admit of falsity. The non-necessary he explains as that which, considered in itself, can admit of falsity, and the impossible as that which by itsg intrinsic nature • • • can never admit of truth. The views expressed here are very close to what is found in MacColl's later writing. Here the modal concepts are defined without the aid of temporal notions and, as Kneale points out, it would appear that possibility, defined as self-consistency, is the basic modal idea while the others are defined in terms of it. For the purposes of this study one of the most interesting debates in ancient logic was that over the proper 8 Ibid., p. 119 9 Ibid., p. 122 -vi- analysis of conditional propositions. IO Philo defined an implication as a conditional which is true when and only when it does not have a true antecedent and a false consequent. This concept of implication, which is the same as what is now usually referred to as "material implication", appeared paradoxical to several ancient authors just as it did to MacColl in the nineteenth century.
Recommended publications
  • How Peircean Was the “'Fregean' Revolution” in Logic?
    HOW PEIRCEAN WAS THE “‘FREGEAN’ REVOLUTION” IN LOGIC? Irving H. Anellis Peirce Edition, Institute for American Thought Indiana University – Purdue University at Indianapolis Indianapolis, IN, USA [email protected] Abstract. The historiography of logic conceives of a Fregean revolution in which modern mathematical logic (also called symbolic logic) has replaced Aristotelian logic. The preeminent expositors of this conception are Jean van Heijenoort (1912–1986) and Don- ald Angus Gillies. The innovations and characteristics that comprise mathematical logic and distinguish it from Aristotelian logic, according to this conception, created ex nihlo by Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) in his Begriffsschrift of 1879, and with Bertrand Rus- sell (1872–1970) as its chief This position likewise understands the algebraic logic of Augustus De Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), Charles Sanders Peirce (1838–1914), and Ernst Schröder (1841–1902) as belonging to the Aristotelian tradi- tion. The “Booleans” are understood, from this vantage point, to merely have rewritten Aristotelian syllogistic in algebraic guise. The most detailed listing and elaboration of Frege’s innovations, and the characteristics that distinguish mathematical logic from Aristotelian logic, were set forth by van Heijenoort. I consider each of the elements of van Heijenoort’s list and note the extent to which Peirce had also developed each of these aspects of logic. I also consider the extent to which Peirce and Frege were aware of, and may have influenced, one another’s logical writings. AMS (MOS) 2010 subject classifications: Primary: 03-03, 03A05, 03C05, 03C10, 03G27, 01A55; secondary: 03B05, 03B10, 03E30, 08A20; Key words and phrases: Peirce, abstract algebraic logic; propositional logic; first-order logic; quantifier elimina- tion, equational classes, relational systems §0.
    [Show full text]
  • Hugh Maccoll After One Hundred Years
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 15-1 | 2011 Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years Amirouche Moktefi and Stephen Read (dir.) Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/351 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.351 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 April 2011 ISBN: 978-2-84174-551-7 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Amirouche Moktefi and Stephen Read (dir.), Philosophia Scientiæ, 15-1 | 2011, “Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years” [Online], Online since 01 April 2011, connection on 15 January 2021. URL: http:// journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/351; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/philosophiascientiae. 351 This text was automatically generated on 15 January 2021. Tous droits réservés Preface Amirouche Moktefi LHSP, Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), Nancy-Université & IRIST (EA 3424), Université de Strasbourg, France Stephen Read Department of Logic and Metaphysics, University of St. Andrews, Scotland “It all turns upon that little word if, Mr. Burton.” [MacColl 1891, 955] This volume is devoted to the life and work of Hugh MacColl (1837- 1909), the Scottish mathematician, philosopher and novelist. Although MacColl is nowadays remembered mainly for his contributions to the science of logic, his work covers many other domains and witnesses the richness and variety of his intellectual interests. MacColl’s early writings (from 1861 onwards) were devoted to mathematics, notably geometry, algebra and the theory of probabilities. In the late 1870s and early 1880s, he published several papers on logic that brought him to the attention of his contemporaries. In these writings, he expressed his preference for propositional calculus instead of the term/class approach, widespread in his day.
    [Show full text]
  • A Survey of the Life of Hugh Maccoll (1837-1909)
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 15-1 | 2011 Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years A survey of the life of Hugh MacColl (1837-1909) Michael Astroh, Ivor Grattan-Guinness and Stephen Read Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/357 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.357 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 April 2011 Number of pages: 7-29 ISBN: 978-2-84174-551-7 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Michael Astroh, Ivor Grattan-Guinness and Stephen Read, « A survey of the life of Hugh MacColl (1837-1909) », Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 15-1 | 2011, Online since 01 April 2014, connection on 03 November 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/357 ; DOI : https:// doi.org/10.4000/philosophiascientiae.357 Tous droits réservés A survey of the life of Hugh MacColl (1837-1909) Michael Astroh Institut für Philosophie, Universität Greifswald, Germany Ivor Grattan-Guinness Middlesex University, England Stephen Read Department of Logic and Metaphysics, University of St. Andrews, Scotland [Editors’ note: This article appeared first in the journal History and Philosophy of Logic, 22, 2001, 81–98. It is reprinted here with the kind permis- sion of the authors and the publisher. The original article can be consulted on the journal’s web site at: www.informaworld.com. The French abstract below has been provided by the editors.] [Résumé : Le logicien écossais Hugh MacColl est bien connu pour ses contri- butions innovantes aux logiques modales et non-classiques. Cependant, jusque- là, nous disposions de peu d’informations biographiques sur son cheminement académique et culturel, sa situation personnelle et professionnelle, et sa po- sition au sein de la communauté scientifique de la période victorienne.
    [Show full text]
  • Hugh Maccoll and Lewis Carroll: Crosscurrents in Geometry and Logic
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by OpenEdition Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 15-1 | 2011 Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years Hugh MacColl and Lewis Carroll: Crosscurrents in geometry and logic Francine F. Abeles and Amirouche Moktefi Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/362 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.362 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 April 2011 Number of pages: 55-76 ISBN: 978-2-84174-551-7 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Francine F. Abeles and Amirouche Moktefi, « Hugh MacColl and Lewis Carroll: Crosscurrents in geometry and logic », Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 15-1 | 2011, Online since 01 April 2014, connection on 19 April 2019. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/362 ; DOI : 10.4000/ philosophiascientiae.362 Tous droits réservés Hugh MacColl and Lewis Carroll: Crosscurrents in geometry and logic Francine F. Abeles Kean University, NJ, USA Amirouche Moktefi LHSP, Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), Nancy-Université & IRIST (EA 3424), Université de Strasbourg, France Résumé : Dans une lettre adressée à Bertrand Russell, le 17 mai 1905, Hugh MacColl raconte avoir abandonné l’étude de la logique après 1884, pendant près de treize ans, et explique que ce fut la lecture de l’ouvrage de Lewis Carroll, Symbolic Logic (1896), qui “ralluma le vieux feu qu’il croyait éteint”. Dès lors, il publie de nombreux articles contenant certaines de ses innova- tions majeures en logique. L’objet de cet article est de discuter la familiar- ité de MacColl et son appréciation du travail de Carroll, et de comprendre comment cela l’amena à réinvestir le domaine de la logique.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Hugh Maccoll and the Tradition of Logic
    INTRODUCTION Throughout the short history of modern logic, Hugh MacColl’s (1837–1909) pioneering achievements have scarcely been received with adequate esteem. In 1877, two years before the Begriffsschrift, he pub- lished the first purely symbolical presentation of a variant version of propositional logic. J. M. Boche´nski,one of the few scholars familiar with his early system, judged it to be “the climax of mathematical logic before Frege”. Towards the end of the century MacColl developed the first modal system in the history of modern logic. Twenty years before Lewis, he defined the concept of strict implication, and earlier than Peano he accounted for inclusion by means of implication. In spite of some benevolent acknowledgements, neither MacColl’s contributions to the development of logic nor the philosophical context in which they came forth have been investigated with appropriate at- tention. Only during the second half of the 20th century have MacColl’s major domains of research, i.e. modal and non-classical logic, gradually turned into acclaimed fields of interest. By then, however, their explo- ration could rely on methodological standards that for MacColl were not within reach. In addition to such general reasons, specific obstacles have hindered serious efforts to investigate his account of logic. Most of MacColl’s articles and books are not readily available. A reliable and comprehensive bibliography has not been published. Had MacColl benefited from an ordinary academic career his works would most likely have come down to us in a more accessible form. The colloquium on Hugh MacColl and the Tradition of Logic, held at the Ernst-Moritz-Arndt University of Greifswald from 29 March to 1 April 1998, was designed with the intention of initiating serious re- search on this author whose predominant intent was “to bridge the gulf between Symbolic Logic and the Traditional”.
    [Show full text]
  • Hugh Maccoll and the Birth of Logical Pluralism
    HUGH MACCOLL AND THE BIRTH OF LOGICAL PLURALISM Shahid Rahman and Juan Redmond INTRODUCTION Hugh MacColl (1837-1909) was a mathematician and logician who was born, raised and educated in Scotland and after a few years working in different areas of Great Britain moved to Boulogne-sur-Mer (France), where he developed the greater part of his work and went on to become a French citizen. Hugh MacColl was well known in his time for his innovative contributions to logic. Despite the fact that one can hardly say that his work satisfies the standards of rigour of Frege's phi- losophy of mathematics and logic it might represent one of the first approaches to logical pluralism. His first contribution to the logical algebras of the 19 th century was that his calculus admits not only a class interpretation (as in the algebra of Boole) but also a propositional one. Moreover, MacColl gave preference to the propositional interpretation because of its generality and called it pure logic. The main connective in his pure logic is the conditional and accordingly his algebra contains a specific operator for this connective. In Symbolic Logic and its Applica- tions (1906) MacColl published the final version of his logic(s) where propositions are qualified as either certain, impossible, contingent, true or false. After his death his work suffered a sad destiny. Contrary to other contemporary logicians such as L. Couturat, G. Frege, W.S. Jevons, J. Venn, G. Peano, C. S. Pierce, B. Russell and E. Schr5der, who knew MacColl's work, his contributions seem to have received neither the acknowledgement nor the systematic study they certainly deserve.
    [Show full text]
  • Fiction, Creation and Fictionality : an Overview Matthieu Fontaine, Shahid Rahman
    Fiction, Creation and Fictionality : An Overview Matthieu Fontaine, Shahid Rahman To cite this version: Matthieu Fontaine, Shahid Rahman. Fiction, Creation and Fictionality : An Overview. Metho- dos : savoirs et textes, Savoirs textes langage - UMR 8163, 2010, 10.4000/methodos.2343. halshs- 01227945 HAL Id: halshs-01227945 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01227945 Submitted on 12 Nov 2015 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Fiction, Creation and Fictionality An Overview Matthieu Fontaine and Shahid Rahman (Université Lille3, UFR Philosophie, UMR 8163) Abstract The philosophical reflection on non-existence is an issue that has been tackled at the very start of philosophy and constitutes since the publication in 1905 of Russell’s “On Denoting” one of the most thorny and heated debates in analytic philosophy. However the fierce debates on the semantics of proper names and definite descriptions which took off after the publication of Strawson’s ‘On Referring’ in 1950 did not trigger a systematic study of the semantics of fiction. In fact, the systematic development of a link that articulates the approaches to fiction of logic; philosophy and literature had to wait until the work of John Woods, who published in 1974 the book Logic of Fiction : : A Philosophical Sounding of Deviant Logic .
    [Show full text]
  • Some Arguments for Propositional Logic: Maccoll As a Philosopher
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 15-1 | 2011 Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years Some arguments for propositional logic: MacColl as a philosopher J.-M. C. Chevalier Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/368 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.368 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 April 2011 Number of pages: 129-147 ISBN: 978-2-84174-551-7 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference J.-M. C. Chevalier, « Some arguments for propositional logic: MacColl as a philosopher », Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 15-1 | 2011, Online since 01 April 2014, connection on 02 November 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/368 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/ philosophiascientiae.368 Tous droits réservés Some arguments for propositional logic: MacColl as a philosopher J.-M. C. Chevalier Université Paris-Est (Val-de-Marne) & LHSP, Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), Nancy-Université, France Résumé : L’article examine les raisons philosophiques, plutôt que mathé- matiques ou logiques, pour lesquelles MacColl a pu vouloir développer une logique propositionnelle. Nous trouvons des éléments de réponse dans le refus discret d’endosser une logique des choses, dans l’anti-psychologisme nuancé de MacColl, et dans une subtile épistémologie de la certitude liée à un usage méthodique de la grammaire. Abstract: The paper considers the philosophical, rather than mathematical or logical, reasons why MacColl decided to develop a propositional logic. We find some answers in a discrete refusal to countenance a logic of things, in MacColl’s qualified anti-psychologism, and in a subtle epistemology of cer- tainty linked to the methodical use of grammar.
    [Show full text]
  • Hugh Maccoll---Victorian
    Stein Haugom Olsen HUGH MACCOLL—VICTORIAN In addition to his work on logic and Man’s Origin, Destiny, and Duty, MacColl also published two novels, Mr Stranger’s Sealed Packet (1889) and Ednor Whitlock (1891), both of which give the impression that MacColl, in spite of his innovative work in logic, had conservative attitudes and opinions when it came to central questions of the day such as faith and doubt, the role of women, etc. In the following the background against which MacColl’s fictional work as well as his defence of Christianity must be understood, is explored, and his fictional works are re- lated to this background. MacColl’s conception of the issues and the arguments of the time as well as his attitudes to these is- sues will be compared to those of other “eminent Victorians”, in particular those of men of letters and writers of fiction. The value of such an analysis is not only that it fills out our picture of MacColl, but that it gives insight into what attitudes an intelli- gent and enlightened Victorian intellectual, whose specialization in logic would well equip him for clear thought, could have of attitudes to and opinions on important questions of the day. I. Hugh MacColl was born in 1837, the year of Queen Victoria’s ac- cession to the throne of England. He died in 1909, eight years after the Queen’s reign had ended. In that year he published Man’s Origin, Destiny, and Duty (Williams and Norgate, London, 1909), a defence of a theistic position on the Christian faith against the onslaught of materialist science and evolutionary biology.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantifiers and Ontological Fluctuations
    ArtefaCToS. Revista de estudios de la ciencia y la tecnología eISSN: 1989-3612 Vol. 9, No. 2 (2020), 2.ª Época, 51-77 DOI: https://doi.org/10.14201/art2020925177 Quanti!ers and Ontological Fluctuations: A Dialogical and Dynamical Point of View of Existence Cuanti!cadores y "uctuaciones ontológicas: un punto de vista di- alógico y dinámico de la existencia Juan REDMOND Universidad de Valparaíso, Chile [email protected] Recibido: 15/09/2020. Revisado: 20/10/2020. Aceptado: 21/10/2020 Abstract "e objective of this article is, from the notion of existence as a function of choice, to propose a dynamic quanti!er capable of capturing ontological slides or #uctuations within a logical proof. Indeed, we call ontological sliding the pas- sage from indetermination to the ontological determination of the singular terms involved in a proof. Both notions will be presented in the pragmatic approach of Dialogics that, due to its dual semantics, allows to handle both questions in an optimal fashion. Keywords: dialogic; dynamic; quanti!er; existence; !ctions. Resumen El objetivo del presente artículo es, a partir de la noción de existencia como función de elección, proponer un cuanti!cador dinámico capaz de capturar los deslizamientos ontológicos dentro de una prueba lógica. En efecto, llamamos deslizamiento ontológico al paso de la indeterminación a la determinación on- tológica de los términos singulares involucrados en una prueba. ambas nociones serán presentadas en el enfoque pragmático de la dialógica que por su semántica dual permite llevar ambas cuestiones de manera idónea. Palabras clave: dialógica; dinámica; cuanti!cador; existencia; !cciones. Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / ddddd ArtefaCToS, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • Maccoll's Modes of Modalities
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 15-1 | 2011 Hugh MacColl after One Hundred Years MacColl’s Modes of Modalities Fabien Schang Publisher Editions Kimé Electronic version Printed version URL: http:// Date of publication: 1 avril 2011 philosophiascientiae.revues.org/510 Number of pages: 149-188 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.510 ISBN: 978-2-84174-551-7 ISSN: 1775-4283 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Fabien Schang, « MacColl’s Modes of Modalities », Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 15-1 | 2011, Online since 01 April 2014, connection on 30 September 2016. URL : http:// philosophiascientiae.revues.org/510 ; DOI : 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.510 The text is a facsimile of the print edition. Tous droits réservés MacColl’s Modes of Modalities Fabien Schang Technische Universität Dresden, Institut für Philosophie, Germany LHSP, Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), Nancy-Université, France Résumé : Hugh MacColl est présenté d’ordinaire comme un pionnier des logiques modales et multivalentes, suite à son introduction de modalités qui vont au-delà de la simple vérité et fausseté. Mais un examen plus attentif montre que cet héritage est discutable et devrait tenir compte de la façon dont ces modalités procédaient. Bien que MacColl ait conçu une logique modale au sens large du terme, nous montrerons qu’il n’a pas produit une logique multivalente au sens strict. Sa logique serait comparable plutôt à une « logique non-fregéenne », c’est-à-dire une logique algébrique qui effectue une partition au sein de la classe des vérités et faussetés mais n’étend pas pour autant le domaine des valeurs de vérité.
    [Show full text]
  • Irving H. Anellis 1. Introduction. Charles Sanders Peirce
    PEIRCE’S TRUTH-FUNCTIONAL ANALYSIS AND THE ORIGIN OF TRUTH TABLES Irving H. Anellis Abstract. We explore the technical details and historical evolution of Charles Peirce’s articulation of a truth table in 1893, against the background of his investigation into the truth-functional analysis of propositions involving implication. In 1997, John Shosky discovered, on the verso of a page of the typed transcript of Bertrand Russell’s 1912 lecture on “The Philosophy of Logical Atomism” truth table matrices. The matrix for negation is Russell’s, alongside of which is the matrix for material implication in the hand of Ludwig Wittgenstein. It is shown that an unpublished manuscript identified as composed by Peirce in 1893 includes a truth table matrix that is equivalent to the matrix for material implication discovered by John Shosky. An unpublished manuscript by Peirce identified as having been composed in 1883-84 in connection with the composition of Peirce’s “On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation” that appeared in the American Journal of Mathematics in 1885 includes an example of an indirect truth table for the conditional. MSC2010 subject classifications: primary: 03B05, 03B35, 03-03; secondary 01A55-01A60 Key words and phrases: Peirce, propositions, truth-functional analysis; truth tables 1. Introduction. Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) undertook a study of the conditions for the truth of propositions that continued through his entire career as a logician. The centerpiece of his work was the analysis of illation,
    [Show full text]