9 the Deconstruction of Deconstruction: Prelude to a Metaphysics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

9 the Deconstruction of Deconstruction: Prelude to a Metaphysics 9 The Deconstruction of Deconstruction: Prelude to a Metaphysics It may seem that deconstruction emerging from Derrida’s texts as a schematic approach to evaluating philosophical theory has collapsed from unrecognized reliance on its own residual metaphysics. Derrida’s concerted regard for and attention to the history of philosophy and its effect on contemporary thought would not then have resulted in a position with sufficient stability to reveal untapped possibilities resident in that very history. But this summary and ultimately dismissive judgment is in a way premature. Even if the criticisms aimed at Derrida are accepted, the elements collectively standing as “deconstruction” hold out possibilities for additional inquiry and potential insight into the experience and articulation of traditional metaphysics. Chapter 9 addresses these attendant possibilities. The pivotal component is the notion named “trace.” In Chapter 6, we outlined and discussed Derrida’s complex and convoluted treatment of trace functioning as a key component in signification. But now we shall see that Derrida’s notion of trace can become an access to ways of looking at and thinking about “reality,” a code word for the subject of metaphysics. This access engages what should be countenanced from western metaphysics but then routes that engagement through a style of discourse which, at least by intent, reduces residual effects of having emerged from the terminology of metaphysics. The resulting language embraces what looks to be fresh and revelatory means of expression, or at least optimizes chances of eventually accessing such material. Although on the surface it may appear difficult, perhaps even impossible, to transcend the outermost limits of being as presence, we approach Derrida’s disposition of trace with a high degree of optimism regarding its potential for producing insight at this level. It may in the end remain viable to “do” metaphysics in something like the ways it has been done for the last three millennia. The notion of possibility identified in the terminology of classical metaphysics stands as both an underlying context and ongoing theme throughout this chapter. In general, a possibility may–or may not–be actualized. The reader should keep this broad tentativeness in view as the chapter derives an argument based on texts from deconstruction which leads gradually to positive results in metaphysical matters. In one respect, being as presence is and has been a continually closed and closing door; but in another respect, finalizing one set of possible outcomes found in and defined by the history of metaphysics may engender another set of entrances to new destinations. 270 The Deconstruction of Deconstruction: Prelude to a Metaphysics 9.1 Derrida’s Truth The scene is the arena of contemporary philosophy. That fundamental differences obtain between analytical and continental philosophy is a view commonly held by many practitioners of each mode of expression as they respectively pursue the love of wisdom. One of the most dramatic and intense examples of this difference emerged from exchanges between Jacques Derrida and John Searle on the topic of speech acts, especially as this concept was formulated and developed by John Austin. Derrida critically evaluated Austin on speech acts, Searle critiqued Derrida’s assessment with considerable energy and also an apparent lack of good will. For Derrida, Searle’s reply was not just laced with ill humor, it was also fundamentally wrong. Derrida said so, bluntly and unambiguously: Passage 9A The answer is simple enough: this definition of the deconstructionist is false (that’s right: false, not true) and feeble; it supposes a bad (that’s right: bad, not good) and feeble reading of numerous texts, first of all mine, which therefore must finally be read or reread. Then perhaps it will be understood that the value of truth (and all those values associated with it) is never con- tested or destroyed in my writings, but only reinscribed in more powerful, larger, more stratified contexts (LI, 146–italics in text). Philosophers often disagree with evaluations of their positions, whether negative reactions appear in print or are “live” at meetings, so in one respect Derrida’s blunt (if not apparently overwrought) rejoinder is not of special interest. If it were just a matter of intellectual biography (in what may be one of its more indecorous moments), then this episode is interesting to the extent that public idiosyncrasies of authors are interesting; however, if only this were at stake, little if anything illuminating for those philosophically inclined would remain from this fractious interchange. What is striking from a more dispassionate perspective is that Derrida’s response to Searle appears to be flatly inconsistent with Derrida’s canonic positions as they emerge from a plateau for interpreting texts based on deconstructionist principles. For Derrida, Searle’s reading of Derrida’s text is simply “false.” But if an articulated reading of a text is false, then it is reasonable to expect that another reading of the same text will be “true.” Yet on deconstructionist principles, how is a true reading possible? Derrida’s insistence on rightness in this case may have been only a momentary aberration (motivated by pique and aggrieved ego), a temporary deferral of dispassionate deconstructionist approaches to reading.115 115 In the Afterword to LI, written ten years after Derrida’s original reply to Searle, Derrida admits that this response “was not devoid of aggressivity” (LI, 113). However, he also insists that this mode of expression was consonant with the “violence” characterizing the context surrounding his work and Searle’s critique of it. Derrida says in the Afterword that he will return to “straightforward” discus- sion so that his observations “will thereby gain in clarity” (LI, 114). Whether Derrida’s “aggressivity” is read as a manifest instance of polemic depends on one’s taste in academic writing. But the more “As we speak....” 271 But if this appeal to rightness is indeed seriously intended, we ask: first, what conditions must obtain to enable the possibility of such a reading; second, are these conditions, if enunciated with sufficient clarity and comprehensiveness, compatible with deconstruction as an aggregation of interpretive principles aimed at evoking determinate ends? 9.2 “As we speak....” By way of preamble to an exploration of these joint concerns, let us review what is true of many linguistic contexts, intractably and stubbornly so, in ways which philosophers must acknowledge and incorporate into their reflection on the issues at hand. Consider as paradigmatic Dewey’s example, asking someone for something. This event happens now, not a few minutes ago, not later on. The event happens here, not there or anywhere else.The reader of this essay is doing so here and now, surrounded by a determinable number of entities or people, perhaps both. Generally speaking, an utterance such as, e.g., a request for a drink of water relates a speaker existing in this here and now to an auditor also existing in this here and now. The resultant meaning of linguistic sequence voiced within an environment circumscribed by such temporal and contextual constraints is straightforward, stable and unambiguous for all concerned participants. But following Derrida and deconstruction with its undifferentiated and comprehensively unified ensemble of interpretive strategies fully in place–a unity tacitly spanning all contexts and all dimensions of temporality–the theoretical possibility of securing such a meaning is necessarily out of bounds. However, the primary reason for this loss of stability has nothing to do with considerations relative to language proper. As argued in Chapter 8, the deconstructively motivated conclusion derives its theoretical force from reliance on metaphysics plain and simple–in fact, a continually ongoing rush of contexts and temporality, with this reality spreading in all possible directions from the confines of a single moment or definite duration and the equally determinate limits of a context with a necessary measure of givenness and limit. But this rampant Heracliteanism apparently does not extend to at least some of Derrida’s texts as well as to the readings which he himself produced and imposed on those texts. This fact must give us pause. important philosophical point is how any sense of “clarity” is possible in Derrida’s own writing given the deconstructive approach to linguistic structure exemplified in Derrida’s theoretical work and the interpretive assumption that the statement of deconstructionist theory in Derrida’s texts is itself fully self-referential. 272 The Deconstruction of Deconstruction: Prelude to a Metaphysics 9.3 Deconstruction and the Margins of Self-reference We assume that Derrida’s reaction to Searle is intended seriously and also that this seriousness can be justified philosophically. But how? The cogency of Derrida’s written reactions to what others say in texts about his texts presupposes the existence and reliability of a series of realities and principles based on those realities. First, the text in question must be identical for both the critic of that text and its defender. Furthermore, this text must remain identical during both (a) the process of criticism advanced by a reader of a text as well as (b) the defense raised against that criticism on behalf of the text’s apparent integrity. If the text is moving and unstable in its import, then it follows that the critic and defender may not be referring to the same ordered series of words as these words produce unity of signification. In addition, the defender must understand the text in a certain way, an understanding existing apart from the myriad possible ways in which the text could be taken by other readers. This separation of textual givenness and an understanding of that givenness is necessary in order to establish a condition for the possibility of rightness from the interpretive perspective of the defender; without this distance between text and understanding, the defender’s claim of rightness against alternate readings rests solely on what the defender believes to be the case.
Recommended publications
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Habermas's Politics of Rational Freedom: Navigating the History Of
    This is a repository copy of Habermas’s politics of rational freedom: Navigating the history of philosophy between faith and knowledge. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/162100/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Verovšek, P.J. (2020) Habermas’s politics of rational freedom: Navigating the history of philosophy between faith and knowledge. Analyse & Kritik, 42 (1). pp. 191-218. ISSN 0171-5860 https://doi.org/10.1515/auk-2020-0008 © 2020 Walter de Gruyter GmbH. This is an author-produced version of a paper subsequently published in Analyse and Kritik. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Habermas’s Politics of Rational Freedom: Navigating the History of Philosophy between Faith and Knowledge* Peter J. Verovšek† Department of Politics & International Relations University of Sheffield Elmfield, Northumberland Road Sheffield, S10 2TU United Kingdom [email protected] ABSTRACT Despite his hostility to religion in his early career, since the turn of the century Habermas has devoted his research to the relationship between faith and knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Derridean Deconstruction and Feminism
    DERRIDEAN DECONSTRUCTION AND FEMINISM: Exploring Aporias in Feminist Theory and Practice Pam Papadelos Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Discipline of Gender, Work and Social Inquiry Adelaide University December 2006 Contents ABSTRACT..............................................................................................................III DECLARATION .....................................................................................................IV ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ......................................................................................V INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................................... 1 THESIS STRUCTURE AND OVERVIEW......................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1: LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS – FEMINISM AND DECONSTRUCTION ............................................................................................... 8 INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................................... 8 FEMINIST CRITIQUES OF PHILOSOPHY..................................................................... 10 Is Philosophy Inherently Masculine? ................................................................ 11 The Discipline of Philosophy Does Not Acknowledge Feminist Theories......... 13 The Concept of a Feminist Philosopher is Contradictory Given the Basic Premises of Philosophy.....................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • TAKING AFRICANA EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY of EDUCATION SERIOUSLY Dwayne A
    TAKING AFRICANA EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY OF EDUCATION SERIOUSLY Dwayne A. Tunstall Grand Valley State University Africana existential philosophy, as a subfield of Africana philosophy, is a relatively recent phenomenon in North American, European, and African academic philosophy. Africana existential philosophy of education is an even more recent phenomenon in the field of educational theory. Given the nascent status of Africana existential philosophy in academia, many educators and philosophers of education might question whether an Africana existential philosophy of education has anything of lasting significance to contribute to educational theory. This worry is an unwarranted one, for Africana existential philosophy, as a mode of philosophical reflection, is centuries old, with roots in pre-colonial West African religious traditions.1 And, by extension, Africana existential philosophies of education can also trace their origins back to precolonial West African religious traditions. However, this essay will not be an exercise in tracing the origins of Africana existential philosophies of education back to precolonial West African religious traditions, since scholars such as Paget Henry, Clevis Headley, and Stephen Nathan Haymes have already contributed much to that project.2 Even though this essay does not trace the origins of Africana existential philosophies of education back to precolonial West African religious traditions, I think I should mention a couple of the similarities between these precolonial religious traditions and African
    [Show full text]
  • Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Political Philosopher1
    Günter Zöller Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Political Philosopher1 1. The First System of Freedom The philosophical work of Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1814) is political through and through. His thinking, no matter how abstract, arid and seemingly removed from current affairs, reflected the dramatic developments of his age: from the French Revolution through the European Empire of Napoleon Bonaparte to the German national uprising in the Liberation Wars against the Corse conqueror. The key concept of Fichte's eminently political philosophy was freedom: political freedom from oppression and domination, but also cognitive freedom from error and illusion, cultural freedom from foreign influences and manipulation, moral freedom from the dictates of selfish interests, social freedom from economic inequality and injustice, religious freedom from superstition and blind faith, and philosophical freedom from prejudice and presumption. But the multiform freedom pursued by Fichte was not merely negative and geared at the removal of obstacles and detractions. Freedom for Fichte meant primarily the positive freedom of self- determination, politically speaking of self-governance and of the deliberate subjection to rules of one's own making or consenting. Accordingly, freedom for Fichte essentially involved norms for the proper use of freedom – laws that guide its employment in the pursuit of ends set and means chosen. More yet, for Fichte freedom understood as autonomy also served as the final end of human existence, something to be pursued for its own sake and not trumped by any other aim or object. Fichte inherited the focus on freedom as the motor and goal of all worthy human life and as the chief concern of sustained philosophical reflection from Kant, who had devoted his mature philosophy to delimiting the conceptual space for freedom in a world otherwise governed by natural causal laws and their thoroughgoing determination of things and events.
    [Show full text]
  • Can We Trace Medical Concepts in the Philosophy of Plato? Christos Tsagkaris, Marko Dorosh, Dimitrios V
    History & Philosophy of Medicine 1 Can we trace medical concepts in the Philosophy of Plato? Christos Tsagkaris, Marko Dorosh, Dimitrios V. Moysidis, Anna Loudovikou, Andreas S. Papazoglou according to the philosopher, equals to mental disease and as Health seems to be an issue of prominent importance since a result, immorality “is contrary to nature” [1, 5]. st classical antiquity to the 21 century AD. Back in the 4th Nevertheless, there might be additional interpretations of century BC, the renowned philosopher Plato stated that “at- Plato’s approach. Putting the philosopher’s words in the con- tention to Health is life’s greatest hindrance” [1]. Even if this text of the modern perception of health, it is possible to statement sounds ambiguous to people who consider health a identify potential connections with contemporary concepts of blessing, this essay serves two precise points: to examine such individual and population health. Since 1948, health is a claim in relation to Plato’s philosophical worldview while discussing it in relation to contemporary attitude. perceived as a state of physical, mental and social wellbeing Plato has been one of the first scholars to - attempt to - [6]. provide a definition of health. His definition focuses on mental Essentially, a reiteration of Plato’s approach would em- health. According to Plato’s tripartite theory of the soul, the phasize on mental health and its social determinants. Mental soul consists of three different parts: the logistic, the high health disorders can disrupt social wellbeing at individual and spirited and the appetitive. “Health” is defined as a kind of community level.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Meaning and Existence: Toward the Development of a Measure of Existential Authenticity
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 5-2013 Understanding Meaning and Existence: Toward the Development of a Measure of Existential Authenticity Patrick Charles Carmody University of Tennessee, Knoxville, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Other Psychology Commons, and the Personality and Social Contexts Commons Recommended Citation Carmody, Patrick Charles, "Understanding Meaning and Existence: Toward the Development of a Measure of Existential Authenticity. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2013. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/1704 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by Patrick Charles Carmody entitled "Understanding Meaning and Existence: Toward the Development of a Measure of Existential Authenticity." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Psychology. John Lounsbury, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend
    [Show full text]
  • Anarchism and Existentialism
    CHAPTER 19 Anarchism and Existentialism Shane Wahl Introduction One way to approach the relationship between anarchist philosophy and exis- tentialist philosophy would be to trace the historical connections between the two and provide an account of how certain thinkers in both “schools” share philosophical and pragmatic concerns, questions, and maybe even answers. Such an approach has the merits of comprehensiveness and perhaps exhaus- tiveness on its side. This method would give ample breadth to the relationship and its philosophical underpinning, providing a full account of historical and theoretical connections. While this chapter is meant to give a solid overview along these lines, I am also mostly concerned with developing a “philosophy of the future” for anarchist-existentialists (or existentialist-anarchists). A key part of this, in my view, is to grapple with a major problem that confronts both the existentialist and the anarchist at the theoretical and practical level. This is the problem of the supposed (or maybe assumed) distinction—sometimes held to be hard and fast—between the “individual” and the “social.” Focusing on this particular issue will provide some depth to the discussion. Anarchism has varying degrees of “individualism” built-in theoretically, that is, there are different kinds of anarchists seeking different understandings of how anarchism is to operate in terms of individual liberty versus social cohe- sion, often with some strong skepticism for the possibility of the latter in an- archist theory and practice.1 The practical issue regarding the individual and social cannot be overlooked. A “common sense” understanding of anarchism as somewhat synonymous with “chaos” breeds an outlook of dismissal of any claims of it “working” in any kind of truly social setting.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Jonathan D. Kramer, Postmodern Music, Postmodern Listening (Bloomsbury, 2016)
    Gamut: Online Journal of the Music Theory Society of the Mid-Atlantic Volume 8 Issue 1 Article 9 April 2018 Review of Jonathan D. Kramer, Postmodern Music, Postmodern Listening (Bloomsbury, 2016) Philip Duker University of Delaware Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/gamut Recommended Citation Duker, Philip (2018) "Review of Jonathan D. Kramer, Postmodern Music, Postmodern Listening (Bloomsbury, 2016)," Gamut: Online Journal of the Music Theory Society of the Mid-Atlantic: Vol. 8 : Iss. 1 , Article 9. Available at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/gamut/vol8/iss1/9 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by Volunteer, Open Access, Library Journals (VOL Journals), published in partnership with The University of Tennessee (UT) University Libraries. This article has been accepted for inclusion in Gamut: Online Journal of the Music Theory Society of the Mid-Atlantic by an authorized editor. For more information, please visit https://trace.tennessee.edu/gamut. Review of Jonathan D. Kramer, Postmodern Music, Postmodern Listening (Bloomsbury, 2016). PHILIP DUKER or those of us influenced by Jonathan Kramer’s seminal The Time of Music, it is a delight F to see his last book in print. With his untimely death in 2004, this manuscript has taken quite a journey. From the whispers of drafts floating around in the hands of various students, to quotations and references showing up in various places, admirers of Kramer’s work have been longing for this final publication to become available. It is commendable that Robert Carl took on the role of editor and we should be grateful to Carl, Deborah Bradley-Kramer and Jann Pasler for seeing the work through to publication and for sharing Kramer’s ideas with the rest of the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Derrida, Lacan and Deconstruction
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Undergraduate Honors Theses Honors College 2012 Derrida, Lacan and Deconstruction Taylor Konieczka Follow this and additional works at: https://thekeep.eiu.edu/honors_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons DERRIDA, LAGAN, AND DECONSTRUCTION (TITLE) BY TAYLOR KONIECZKA UNDERGRADUATE THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS OF UNDERGRADUATE DEPARTMENTAL HONORS DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY, ALONG WITH THE HONORS COLLEGE, EASTERN ILLINOIS UNIVERSITY CHARLESTON, ILLINOIS 2012 YEAR I HEREBY RECOMMEND THIS UNDERGRADUATE THESIS BE ACCEPTED AS FULFILLING THE THESIS REQUIREMENT FOR UNDERGRADUATE DEPARTMENTAL HONORS 2 L'' \ 'L 7-/ DATE fo \i;'.4- L'' 7 f I ]._. \ '2-­ DA TE HONORS COORDINATOR DATE DEPARTMENT CHAIR Derrida, Lacan and Deconstruction Taylor Konieczka Eastern Illinois University Derrida, Lacan, and Deconstruction Derrida and Lacan are two French intellectuals who share many of the same key concepts. Derrida's work mainly includes deconstructing texts in order to understand the how of the text versus the what of the text. Lacan is a psychoanalysist that takes Freudian concepts and makes them accessible and understandable for the modern world. After researching both Derrida and Lacan, it is easy to see that they share the same ideas of an overall system of functions and the idea of signification. To start, in Of Grammatology, Derrida explains his system of deconstruction. In order to further explain this concept, Derrida defines the terms "book" and "text." For Derrida a book is a self-contained totality that has an author, and a beginning, middle and end. One reads a book in relation to the author's interpretation and the author's intended meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • Surviving in Between Neoliberalism and “Socialism with Chinese Characteristics”
    Surviving in between Neoliberalism and “Socialism with Chinese Characteristics”: Chinese Women in Negotiation with the Nation and Public Culture A dissertation presented to the faculty of the Scripps College of Communication of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy Xiaomeng Li August 2020 © 2020 Xiaomeng Li. All Rights Reserved. This dissertation titled Surviving in between Neoliberalism and “Socialism with Chinese Characteristics”: Chinese Women in Negotiation with the Nation and Public Culture by XIAOMENG LI has been approved for the School of Media Arts and Studies and the Scripps College of Communication by Eve Ng Associate Professor of Media Arts and Studies Scott Titsworth Dean, Scripps College of Communication ii Abstract LI, XIAOMENG, Ph.D., August 2020, Media Arts and Studies Surviving in between Neoliberalism and “Socialism with Chinese Characteristics”: Chinese Women in Negotiation with the Nation and Public Culture Director of Dissertation: Eve Ng People’s Republic of China under President Xi Jinping’s administration has demonstrated an intense agenda of nation-building, observable through the country’s ardent participation in the global economy on the one hand, and domestic propagation of national and cultural pride on the other. While new ideologies such as “Core Socialist Values” and “Chinese Dream” are prevailing in almost every aspect of Chinese people’s daily lives, women are largely overlooked as part of the “citizens” in the official discourses even though they
    [Show full text]