Causality and Becoming: Scotistic Reflections Abstract

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Causality and Becoming: Scotistic Reflections Abstract Causality and Becoming: Scotistic Reflections Liran Shia Gordon / The Van Leer Jerusalem Institute Abstract: Becoming is a process in which a thing moves from one state to another. In Section 1, the study will elaborate on the discussion of the Aristotelian causes taken broadly, primarily focusing on the relation between efficient and final causes. In Section 2, the study discusses the implications of Scotus’s conception of contingency and freedom, as they are reflected in the relation of the future to the past, for the efficient and final causalities. Similarly in Section 3 an examination of Scotus’s conception of matter is conducted. Based on the ideas established in these sections, the study attempts to present an initial Scotistic view of becoming. Becoming is a process in which a thing moves from one state to another. Following Aristotle, the Scholastics spoke of four types of causes that describe the process of becoming: material, formal, efficient, and final.1 The material cause refers to what the thing is made of while the formal produces what is formed, the role of efficient causality is to produce transformations in matter or move things from their initial place to another, and final causality pertains to an end.2 In Section 1, the study will elaborate on the discussion of the Aristotelian causes taken broadly, primarily focusing on the relation between efficient and final causes. In Section 2, the study discusses the implications of Scotus’s conception of contingency and freedom, as they are reflected in the relation of the future to the past, for the efficient and final causalities. Similarly in Section 3 an examination of Scotus’s conception of matter is conducted. Based on the ideas established in Abbreviations: Lect. = Ioannis Duns Scoti, Lectura: Prologue, I-Iii, ed. Commissio Scotistica, vol. XVII-XXI, Opera Omnia (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, XVII:1966, XVIII:1982, XIX:1993, XX:2003, XXI:2004). Ord. = Ordinatio, Prologue, I-Iv, ed. Commissio Scotistica, vol. I-XIV, Opera Omnia (Città del Vaticano: Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis, I:1950, II:1950, III:1954, IV:1956, V:1959, VI:1963, VII:1973, VIII:2001, IX:2006, X:2007, XI:2008, XII:2010, XIII:2011, XIV:2013). Quodl. = Quaestiones Quodlibetales [God and Creatures: The Quodlibetal Questions (1975)], trans. Felix Alluntis and Allan Wolter, vol. 12, Ioannis Duns Scoti Doctoris Subtilis Ordinis Minorum Opera Omnia (Lyons: Wadding, 1639). QM. = Quaestiones Super Libros Metaphysicorum Aristotelis, Libri I–Ix, vol. 3-4, Opera Philosophica (Franciscan Institute Publ. St. Bonaventure University, 1997). Rep. I-A = John Duns Scot, Reportatio I-a, Prologue, D. 1-48: Latin Text and English Translation, trans. Allan B. Wolter and O. V. Bychkov, vol. 1-2(St. Bonaventure, NY: Franciscan Institute, 2004, 2008). Rep. IV-A = John Duns Scotus, The Report of the Paris Lecture, Reportatio Iv-A(Franciscan Institute Publications, 2016). 1 For further discussion of the Aristotelian and Medieval discussion of causes, and the difference between them, see Jakob Leth Fink, "Introduction," in Suárez on Aristotelian Causality(Brill, 2015), 6-17. 2 Following Aristotle, Aquinas defines final causality in the following way: ‘And since, as Aristotle says in book 2 of the Metaphysics, everything that acts, acts only by intending something, there must be some fourth thing: namely, that which is intended by that which is acting. And this is said to be the end’. Thomas Aquinas, De principiis naturae 3.351, in Opuscula philosophica, ed. R.M. Spiazzi (Turin and Rome, 1954), 123. 1 these sections, the study attempts to present an initial Scotistic view of becoming. Through an integration of key Scotistic conclusions from previous elaborations, this study will primarily deal with extrinsic causes and will not present an exhaustive discussion of Scotus’s understanding of causality, e.g., the distinction between essential and accidental causes.3 §1 Preliminary Consideration of Causality Though the four causes doctrine has had a long and varied history, its interpreters, for example Aquinas and Suarez, did not stray much from the spirit of Aristotle’s works. As the Scholastics of the late 13th century were well acquainted with the thought of Aristotle, they used the four causes as an integral part of their discussions. In contrast to Suarez who devoted disputations 12- 27 to a discussion of causality, and in particular the four causes (13-14 material causality, 15-16 formal causality, 17-22 efficient causality and 23-24 final causality), Duns Scotus uses the four causes throughout his investigations as an integral part of his examinations. As this study does not intend to present a detailed discussion of Scotus’s conception of the four causes doctrine but rather to examine how conclusions from previous elaborations shed new light on the understanding of causality and the question of becoming, the following does not rely solely on Scotus’s statements but also bases itself on those of his contemporaries, such as Thomas Aquinas. In addition, Scotus’s statements will be used to focus on points that are relevant for our examination, particularly on our attempt to develop new insights. Aquinas explains that while material and formal causes ‘are called “intrinsic” to the thing, because they are parts constituting the thing’, final and efficient causes ‘are called “extrinsic” because they are outside the thing’.4 Whereas all the four causes bring about change, only the efficient cause addresses how the change takes place: The material cause is responsible for change in that it is the item that persists through and underlies the change; the formal cause is the characteristic which the changing thing comes to possess; and the final cause is that for the sake of which the change occurs. But 3 A discussion on this matter can be found in Richard Cross, Duns Scotus on God, Ashgate Studies in the History of Philosophical Theology (Aldershot, Hants, England ; Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing, 2005), 17-28. 4 Thomas Aquinas, De principiis naturae 3.352, in Opuscula philosophica, ed. R.M. Spiazzi (Turin and Rome, 1954), 124. See also Suarez’s Metaphysical Disputations 17.1.6. 2 in addition to these three, something more is needed to account for how the change actually comes to take place.5 Whereas the modern mechanistic understanding of efficient causality is concerned with the delivery of motion or momentum from the cause to the effect, the Aristotelian tradition identified efficient causality not solely with the transmitted change but emphasized that what makes an efficient cause a cause is the fact that the change originated from it: it is that from ‘where’ the change begins. In the Physics, Aristotle explains that the ‘where’ of the efficient cause is both a ‘where the origin of the motion [comes] from,’6 that designates the location where the change begins, as well as, and even more importantly, the source of origination or beginning of the motion.7 By holding that efficient causality is that from where the motion of a change begins, efficient causality must be understood from the point of view of agency, not simply as transmitting motion, as the mechanistic billiard-ball view of the universe understands it, but rather as something that actualizes the motion. This origination of change needs to be understood both insofar as the agency uses instruments to exercise causality and insofar as quantity cannot originate an act of its own volition but requires an agency to actualize the quantity in a certain manner. In the first instrumental respect Scotus explains that “cutting apart” insofar as it is an action does not come from the saw. For if cutting apart is a locomotion, then the saw does not actively move [anything], but merely is moved passively by the principal agent. … the saw does not of itself possess [the capacity for] cutting apart, but the motion that is imparted by the hand, as well as the cutting apart that follows, are two effects of an agent that acts according to a certain order. … Therefore neither the saw nor the ax acts with efficient causality, but only passively, insofar as each is moved by an agent.8 Instruments are used passively by the agency to bring about the change. In the second respect, because quantity alone cannot effect efficient cause, Scotus explains: 5 Thomas M. Tuozzo, "Aristotle and the Discovery of Efficient Causation," in Efficient Causation: A History, ed. Tad M Schmaltz, Oxford Philosophical Concepts (NY: Oxford, 2014), 25. 6 Aristotle, Physics 243a33-34. 7 Tuozzo, "Aristotle and the Discovery of Efficient Causation," 25. 8 Rep. IV, d. 1, n. 28 3 [A]ctual quantity is not a principle of any action… how does food nourish by its substantive power? … in the food itself there is no efficient cause for growth; rather this is to be found in the living [organism] converting the food.9 Aristotle did not attribute the ‘where’ of origination only to efficient causality. In the same place in the Physics he spoke of the ‘where’ of origination as both efficient and final causalities.10 This dual attribution is an expression of the fact that final and efficient causes cause together and that this co-causation forms a hierarchy in which final causality governs efficient causality. Final causality does not cause in the manner efficient causality causes, i.e., by bringing things into existence but rather ‘the causality of the final cause is to move the efficient cause to act’.11 Scotus thus does not understand the four causes as being distinct from one another but rather as co-causing in an essentially ordered and unified causation: The four kinds of causes are essentially ordered in their causation of one and the same thing. … how then will they [the four causes] produce the same thing if they do not at least cause together? Insofar as they are causing the effect, then, they possess a unity of order.
Recommended publications
  • Types of Causes in Aristotle and Sankara
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Religious Studies Honors Theses Department of Religious Studies 9-11-2006 Types of Causes in Aristotle and Sankara Brandie Martinez-Bedard Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/rs_hontheses Recommended Citation Martinez-Bedard, Brandie, "Types of Causes in Aristotle and Sankara." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2006. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/rs_hontheses/3 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Religious Studies at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Religious Studies Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TYPES OF CAUSES IN ARISTOTLE AND SANKARA by BRANDIE MARTINEZ BEDARD Under the Direction of Kathryn McClymond and Sandra Dwyer ABSTRACT This paper is a comparative project between a philosopher from the Western tradition, Aristotle, and a philosopher from the Eastern tradition, Sankara. These two philosophers have often been thought to oppose one another in their thoughts, but I will argue that they are similar in several aspects. I will explore connections between Aristotle and Sankara, primarily in their theories of causation. I will argue that a closer examination of both Aristotelian and Advaita Vedanta philosophy, of which Sankara is considered the most prominent thinker, will yield significant similarities that will give new insights into the thoughts
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF Lecture 5 a REVOLUTION
    Founders of Western Philosophy: Thales to Hume a 12-lecture course by DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF Edited by LINDA REARDAN, Ph.D. Lecture 5 A REVOLUTION: THE BIRTH OF REASON, PART II A Publication of CONTENTS Preface iv 1. Aristotle’s Teleology 2 2. The Unmoved Mover 8 3. Refutation of Zeno’s Paradoxes 15 4. Aristotle’s Psychology: The Natural Soul 17 5. Psychology Continued: Sense-Perception and Reason 22 6. Prime Matter and the Levels of Reality 29 7. Aristotle’s Ethics: Self-Realization and the Golden Mean 35 8. Political Philosophy 57 9. Conclusion 61 Study Questions 65 iii Lecture 5 A REVOLUTION: THE BIRTH OF REASON, PART II Last week we surveyed Aristotle’s epistemology and some of the essentials of his metaphysics. In regard to metaphysics, we said that reality for Aristotle is this world, the world in which we live, the world of concrete individual things as perceived through man’s senses. We said that for Aristotle each individual object, each primary substance, is comprised of two elements: a univer- salizing element, which constitutes the basis for our putting it into a certain class and ascribing to it a certain nature; and an individuating element, which constitutes the basis of its unique- ness and makes it a this. Aristotle’s technical terms for these two elements, you recall, are “form” and “matter.” Matter is the stuff or material compris- ing a thing; form represents its structure or organization. In these terms, change, we said, is the process of matter taking on new form, so that change in no way involves a contradiction; it is eminently logical, rational, scientifically intelligible.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Criticism of the Platonic Forms As Causes in De
    PEITHO / EXAMINA ANTIQUA 1 ( 7 ) / 2016 Aristotle’s Criticism of the Platonic Forms as Causes in De Generatione et Corruptione II 9. A Reading Based on Philoponus’ Exegesis* MELINA G. MOUZALA / Patras / In De Generatione et Corruptione II 9 Aristotle treats of the four causes of things gene- rable and perishable and expounds his own doctrine of the efficient cause. He especially focuses on the confirmation of his theory of the necessity of the efficient cause. Within the frame of this theory he grasps the opportunity to set out his criticism, on the one hand of those who ignored the efficient cause, and on the other hand, those who wron- gly attributed the efficient cause to other kinds of causality. My reading of this chapter is * An earlier version of this paper was presented at the III International Congress of Greek Philosophy, Lisbon, April 20–22, 2016. 124 Melina G. Mouzala / Patras / based on Philoponus’ exegesis which contributes significantly, not only to the clarifica- tion of Aristotle’s thinking but also to the manifestation of the arguments articulated in defence of the Platonic theory of Forms, which came under attack by Aristotle. 1. The method for the investigation of the four causes Aristotle begins this chapter with an instruction on the method we have to follow in our investigation in order to discover, concerning all generation alike, how many principles there are of it and what they are. He states that we shall in this way be able more easily to study particular cases, namely, when we have first obtained a grasp of the things which are universal.1 We can see here a reversal of the typical and proper method of natural science and more generally of scientific knowledge, introduced by Aristotle2 at least in the Physics I 1, the Posterior Analytics I 2, and the Metaphysics VII 3.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysics of Agency: Avicenna and His Legacy
    The Metaphysics of Agency: Avicenna and his Legacy by Kara Richardson A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto ©Copyright by Kara Richardson 2008 The Metaphysics of Agency: Avicenna and his Legacy Doctor of Philosophy, 2008 Kara Richardson Department of Philosophy University of Toronto Abstract This dissertation begins with the Islamic philosopher Avicenna, who transforms Aristotle’s conception of the efficient cause in the Metaphysics of his Shifā’. Its first goal is to examine the arguments which constitute Avicenna’s metaphysical account of agency. Its second goal is to examine Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents that arise in connection with his view. In its final chapter, it relates Medieval debates about efficient causality to Descartes’ account of the causal powers of bodies. One of the original features of Avicenna’s account of agency is his argument for the claim that the existence of contingent things requires an efficient cause. This aspect of his view was influential in the Latin West. Avicenna also holds that the cause of the existence of contingent things is an incorporeal principle, which he describes as an agent who “bestows forms”. I argue that Avicenna fails to resolve the tension between this claim and his commitment to an Aristotelian account of generation. This failure sets the stage for Avicenna’s role in Scholastic disputes about the causal powers of natural agents in cases of generation. Both Aquinas and Suarez attribute to Avicenna the view that generation requires the creation of form.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Natural Philosophy
    Aristotle’s Natural Philosophy Waseda University, SILS, Introduction to History and Philosophy of Science LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Aristotle The Hellenic World, 500-300 BCE LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Aristotle The Atomists § The early atomists, Leucippus & Democratus (around 5th BCE) § Nothing comes to be at random (accidentally), but all things from reason and by necessity. § Reason and necessity are the same. § There can be no real chance or purpose. § The later atomists, Epicurus (4th BCE) & Lucretius (around 1st CE) § The atoms swerve from their course by spontaneous chance. § Most things follow laws, but there is some underlying chance. § There is also free-will. LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Aristotle Plato (5th BCE) The Timaeus: § The universe is the combination of a divine creator, The Craftsman, who is a purposeful being acting on an underlying nature, which is brute. § The Craftsman, desires the good and brings order. He works with extant things, matter, to produce the best possible world. He makes the universe a living being in which there are other gods. § The universe is the result of the combination of Reason and Necessity, the “errant cause.” § Reason provides the form, purpose and meaning to the universe. § Necessity is the material substance of the elements without any form, reason or purpose. § There is no omnipotent god. There is no real chance, only Reason and Necessity, which are contrary to one another. LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Aristotle Aristotle of Stagira A short biography of Aristotle:1 § Born 384 BCE, medical family in Macedon. § Athens: 367–347.
    [Show full text]
  • Why the Five Ways? Aquinas’S Avicennian Insight Into the Problem of Unity in the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina
    Why the Five Ways? Aquinas’s Avicennian Insight into the Problem of Unity in the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina Daniel D. De Haan Abstract: This paper will argue that the order and the unity of St. Thomas Aquinas’s five ways can be elucidated through a consideration of St. Thomas’s appropria- tion of an Avicennian insight that he used to order and unify the wisdom of the Aristotelian and Abrahamic philosophical traditions towards the existence of God. I will begin with a central aporia from Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Aristotle says that the science of first philosophy has three different theoretical vectors: ontology, aitiology, and theology. But how can all three be united into a single Aristotelian science? In his Metaphysics of the Healing, Avicenna resolved the impasse by tak- ing the ontological vector as the subject of metaphysics. He then integrated the question of the four first causes into the penultimate stage of his demonstration for the existence of God, thereby placing aitiological and theological questions among the ultimate concerns of a unified Aristotelian metaphysics. In the five ways, St. Thomas integrated Avicenna’s Aristotelian search for the first four causes into the last four of his five ways, by showing that each of the four aitiological orders terminate in an ultimate first cause that we call God. Finally, by appending the proof from the Physics to the beginning of the five ways, St. Thomas was able to show that the ultimate aim of both natural philosophy and metaphysics is the divine first principle, which is the beginning and subject of sacra doctrina.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2018 Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studia Graeco-Arabica, Vol 8 (2018): 287-304. Publisher link. © 2018 Pacini Editore. Used with permission. Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C. Taylor Abstract Prophecy is conspicuous by its complete absence from all three of the commentaries on De Anima by Averroes. However, prophecy and philosophical metaphysics are discussed by him in his Commentary on the Parva Naturalia, a work written before his methodological work on philosophy and religion, the Faṣl al-maqāl, generally held to have been written ca. 1179-1180. The analyses and remarks of Averroes presented in that Commentary have been characterized by Herbert Davidson as “extremely radical” to the extent that “The term prophet would, on this reading, mean nothing more than the human author of Scripture; and the term revelation would mean a high level of philosophical knowledge”. In the present article I discuss Averroes on method in matters of religion and philosophy as well as prophecy in philosophically argumentative works and in dialectical works, with particular consideration of the reasoning of his Commentary on the Parva Naturalia. I conclude that Averroes found in philosophy and its sciences the most complete and precise truth content and highest levels of knowledge and understanding and from them constructed his worldview, while he found prophecy and religion to be like an Aristotelian practical science in that they concern good and right conduct in the achievement of an end attained in action, not truths to be known for their own sake.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Physics
    Aristotle’s Physics: The Metaphysics of Change, Matter, Motion and Time Philipp Blum, [email protected] Hauptseminar, autumn term Seminar admin Semester plan Topics: .. Introduction I: Aristotle’s concept of natural science, explanation and causation in relation to his metaphysics .. Introduction II: Aristotelian time + Aristotelian space = Aristotelian space-time? .. no meeting (St. Leodegar) .. Physics I, II.-: Beginnings and Causes .. Physics, II.-: Forms and natures .. Physics II.-: Chance, Necessity and Teleological Explanation .. Physics III: Motion and the Infinite .. Physics IV.-: Place and the Void .. Physics IV.-: Time .. Physics V+VI: Motions .. Physics VII: Movings .. Physics VIII: The First Motion and the First Mover .. The Aristotelian theory of relations and reciprocal powers .. Aristotelian process ontology and the ontological status of lesser entities Editions, introductions Editions: I find the bilingual German edition by Hans Günter Zekl in the Meiner Verlag (Aristoteles , ) very useful. In the Clarendon Aristotle Series, only five books have been edited: • Books I and II: Charlton (, ) • Books III and IV: Hussey (, ) • Book VIII: Graham () The greek text isavailable in the Loeb ClassicalLibrary: https://www.loebclassics.com/view/LCL228/ 1957/volume.xml, Thomas Aquinas’ commentary is here: http://dhspriory.org/thomas/Physics. htm. Among the entries on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (generally a very good resource) I found useful are the following: • https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle/, by
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 6.2: Change, Potentiality and Causes Rorty UCSC Substances
    Lecture 6.2: Change, Potentiality and Causes Rorty UCSC Substances: We talked Tuesday about Aristotle’s basic constituents of reality: substances. To be a substance, in A’s terminology, is to be an individual—a ‘this such’, capable of being designated in some way; and independent—a thing whose being is not dependent upon something else being modified in some way or another, a non-parasitical thing. The first and plainest examples of substances are animals and plants; and as we saw in Zeta, artifacts, things made. [Aristotle in some of the texts we are not reading seems to consider not only artifacts, but perhaps the heavenly bodies (sun, moon and stars) as substances.] As Barnes puts it, “perceptible things--middle-sized material objects—are the furniture of Aristotle’s world.” Matter and form: Tuesday I attempted (with what success only you know) to give you one tool of analysis by which to understand the nature of a substance: the analytic correlative tools of “matter” and “form.” They go together: something is ‘matter’ or indeterminate with respect to the ‘form’ which determines what kind of thing it is. The brass is the matter out of which a vase is made. The yarn is the matter out of which Aunt Leslie forms a scarf. The matter is called so relatively to the form which gives it further determination. [What I mean to say by calling them ‘analytic tools’ is that you can perform the same operation with them on, for instance, the brass itself, or the yarn: brass is a combination of copper and iron in a certain proportion.
    [Show full text]
  • AS Level Religious Studies Candidate Exemplar Work
    Qualification Accredited AS LEVEL Candidate Exemplars RELIGIOUS STUDIES H173 For first teaching in 2016 Philosophy of Religion - Candidate exemplars (H173/01) Version 1 www.ocr.org.uk/religiousstudies AS Level Religious Studies Candidate Exemplars Contents Introduction 3 Candidate A 4 Assess the effectiveness of Aristotle’s four causes in explaining the world 4 Examiner commentary 5 Candidate B 6 ‘Individual religious experience does not make sense of belief in God.’ Discuss 6 Examiner commentary 7 2 © OCR 2017 AS Level Religious Studies Candidate Exemplars Introduction We asked students to answer questions from the Sample Question Paper for H173/01 Philosophy of Religion: http://www.ocr.org.uk/Images/242914-unit-h173-01- philosophy-of-religion-sample-assessment-material.pdf. The sample answers in this resource have been extracted from original candidate work to maintain their authenticity. They are supported by examiner commentary, both in annotations and in summary at the end of the document. Please note that this resource is provided for advice and guidance only and does not in any way constitute an indication of grade boundaries or endorsed answers. Whilst a senior examiner has provided a possible level for each Assessment Objective when marking these answers, in a live series the mark a response would get depends on the whole process of standardisation, which considers the big picture of the year’s scripts. Therefore the level awarded here should be considered to be only an estimation of what would be awarded. How levels and marks correspond to grade boundaries depends on the Awarding process that happens after all/ most of the scripts are marked and depends on a number of factors, including candidate performance across the board.
    [Show full text]
  • Avicenna and Aquinas: Essence, Existence, and the Esse of Christ
    Avicenna and Aquinas: Essence, Existence, and the Esse of Christ R. E. Houser Center for Thomistic Studies University of St. Thomas, Houston For centuries, Aristotle was considered the primary source of the thought of Br. Thomas of Aquino, OP. Beginning with the historical researches of Etienne Gilson in the 1920s, scholars began to recognize the important influence of Islamic and Jewish thinkers. While it is still true to say that Aquinas was an Aristotelian, historical research has made it necessary to address the question: just what kind of Aristotelian was he? In this essay, I argue that he is best understood as an Avicennian kind of Aristotelian. The argument proceeds in three steps: Aquinas adopted Avicennian metaphysical principles; he then adopted some Avicennian metaphysical conclusions about God; and, finally, he made use of his Avicennian-inspired doctrine of being (esse), to formulate a consistent doctrine of the esse of Christ. I. Introduction Students of the philosophy and theology of Br. Thomas of Aquino, OP, have long recognized the need to consult his intellectual predecessors in order to understand his thought. For centuries, Aristotle was considered the primary source, whose philosophy Thomas ‘baptized.’ Beginning with the historical researches of Etienne Gilson in the 1920s, scholars began to recognize the important influence of Islamic and Jewish thinkers. While it is still true to say that Aquinas was an Aristotelian, broadly construed, historical research has made it necessary to address the question: just what kind of Aristotelian was he? In this essay, I argue that he is best understood as an Avicennian kind of Aristotelian.
    [Show full text]