Mcnulty, Jake

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mcnulty, Jake Logic in Hegel’s Logic Jacob McNulty Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2019 © 2019 Jacob McNulty All rights reserved ABSTRACT Logic in Hegel’s Logic Jacob McNulty My dissertation concerns Hegel’s mature theoretical philosophy. I focus on the role of logic, meant here in a much more conventional sense of the term than is usually thought relevant to Hegel’s thought. I argue that Hegel’s main achievement in logic is to attempt a noncircular derivation of its laws and materials. Central to my interpretation is a sympathetic treatment of Hegel’s claim that Kant did not have a comparably rigorous justification for logic. In Hegel’s view, the critical philosophy’s pervasive reliance on logic precludes it from evaluating the latter in a non-question-begging way. As a result, Kant is forced to ground logic psychologically (though not “psychologistically” in Frege’s sense). For Hegel, Kant’s critical philosophy is insufficiently self-critical with respect to its own logical foundations. It is therefore vulnerable to criticism on logical grounds — especially from a Hegelian direction. As I also hope to show, Hegel rejects Kant’s critique of metaphysics, arguing that its logical presuppositions are unfounded. Once those presuppositions are overhauled, the true source of the metaphysical tradition’s impasses becomes apparent, and a non-Kantian-idealist, metaphysical solution is at hand. The lesson is that metaphysics is an enduring possibility, provided it is based on secure logical foundations. Table of Contents Abbreviations iv Acknowledgments vii Introduction. Philosophy of Logic in Kant, German Idealism (and after) 1 i. Logic in Hegel’s Logic ii. What justifies a law of logic? A dilemma iii. Jäsche’s observation iv. Marburg Neo-Kantianism v. German Idealism v. Heidegger and Hegel: logic and the “question of Being” vi. Overview of the argument vii. “Logic and metaphysics coincide” (Pippin) I. Hegel and the Logic of the Aristotelian tradition 42 i. Presuppositionless knowing: natural science, mathematics, formal logic and religion ii. Hegel and the logic of the Aristotelian tradition iii. Two forms of finitude iv. “Irrational cognition of the rational”: Hegel’s critique of Aristotelian logic v. From formal to speculative logic vi. Conclusion: Kant as minor post-Aristotelian? II. Hegel and Transcendental Logic 72 i. Kant’s Analytic: Marburg Neo-Kantian v. German Idealist readings ii. Hegel’s swimming objection reconsidered: defending a logical interpretation iii. Surmounting the swimming objection 1: Reinhold, Fichte !i iv. Surmounting the swimming objection 2: Hegel v. Conclusion: The ontological argument as “the true critique of the categories and reason” III. Hegel’s Critique of Metaphysics 122 i. Introduction: Hegel and Kant on the problem of dogmatism ii. The role of formal logic in pre-critical metaphysics a) Predicative judgment b) Syllogistic Inference iii. The role of religion (Christianity) iv. Truth in formal and speculative logic v. Overcoming dogmatism: the dialectic vi. A pre-predicative Absolute? vii. Conclusion: Bowman’s Hegel IV. Hegel’s Response to Kant’s Critique of Metaphysics 147 i. Finite and infinite categories ii. Responding to Kant’s critique of Rational Psychology: Paralogisms iii. Responding to Kant’s critique of Rational Cosmology: Antinomies iv. Responding to Kant’s critique of Rational Theology: the Ideal v. Conclusion: Post-Kantian Idealism as Spinozism/monism V. Hegel on the Laws of Logic 185 i. Longuenesse’s Hegel ii. Two methods of justifying the laws of logic iii. Hegel on the laws of logic in the Leibniz/Wolff tradition !ii a) The law of identity b) Identity of indiscernibles (PII) c) Non-contradiction (PNC) d) Excluded middle e) Sufficient reason (PSR) iv. Conclusion: Dialetheism, Hylomorphism and Modality VI. Hegel on Concept, Judgment and Syllogism 234 i. What is Hegel’s argument for conceptual realism? The Kreines Stern debate ii. The Doctrine of Being: regress problems iii. The Doctrine of Essence: circularity problems iv. The Doctrine of the Concept v. Judgment and syllogism vi. Conclusion: was Hegel a Brandomian inferentialist? Conclusion. Analysis, Synthesis, Dialectic 278 i. The Self-Comprehension of Hegel’s Science of Logic ii. From the Concept to the Idea: (Finite) Knowledge iii. From (Finite) Knowledge to Absolute Knowledge: Aristotle Again Epilogue. Absolute Idealism for the 21st Century 290 i. Is Absolute Idealism “the science without contrary”? A Spinozist rejoinder to Rödl ii. “Logic and metaphysics coincide” (again) Works Cited 302 !iii Abbreviations Throughout this work, both in the body and in the footnotes, I provide references to the German and English versions of primary texts by Kant, Fichte and Hegel. The following are the abbreviations that I use; Hegel There are two editions of Hegel’s complete works in German, Suhrkamp and Meiner. My references refer to the Meiner edition, (1968- Gesammelte Werke, Deutsche Forschungsgemainschaft. Hamburg: Meiner) except where otherwise indicated. References to the English translations refer to titles from the series, “Cambridge Hegel Translations” edited by Michael Bauer. I have occasionally referred to other translations of works by Hegel not yet available in this series. The Science of Logic is cited by volume and page number for the German, and just page number for the English. The Encyclopedia is cited by section number (§) followed, where relevant, by an A for the Anmerkungen (remarks) and/or a Z for the Zusätze (additions). The 1831 lectures on logic are cited by the corresponding section number in the Encyclopedia, and the page number in the English translation. The Lectures in the History of Philosophy are cited only by the English section name and sub-section name, e.g., “Aristotle: Logic.” !iv EL = Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse Teil 1: Logik. Werke vol. 13/Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences in Outline: Part 1, Science of Logic. 2010. Edited and translated by Brinkmann, Klaus and Dahlstrom, Daniel O. New York: Cambridge University Press. VL/LL =Vorlesungen über die Logik, Berlin 1831. 2001. Transcribed by K. Hegel. Edited by U. Rameil and H. C. Lucas. Hamburg: Meiner/Lectures on Logic, Berlin, 1831. 2008. Trans. by C. Butler. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. VGP/LHoP = Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophy. Werke vol. 30/Lectures on the History of Philosophy. 1995. 3 vols. Translated by E. S. Haldane and Frances H. Simson. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. WdL/SoL = Wissenschaft der Logik. Werke vols. 21, 11, 12/Hegel’s Science of Logic. 2010. Translated by di Giovanni, George. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kant References to the German are all to the Akademie Ausgabe (Immanuel Kant: Gesamelte Schriften. 1902-. 29 vols. Berlin: De Gruyter). I use the English translations from the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant, except where otherwise noted. For the first critique, I use the standard A/B page references to refer to the first (1781) and second (1787). editions of the work. !v A/B = Kant, I. Kritik der Reinen Vernunft. Ak vol. 3-4/Kant, I. Critique of Pure Reason. Ed. and Trans. by Guyer P. and Wood A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. P = Kant, I. Ak. Prolegomena zu einer jeden künftigen Metaphysik Ak. vol. 4/Kant, I. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Edited and Translated by Hatfield, G. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. JL = Kant, I. “Jäsche Logik” Ak. vol. 9/Kant., I. “Jäsche Logic” In: Kant’s Lectures on Logic, ed. and trans. J. Michael Young, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Fichte German references are to the version of Fichte’s complete works edited by his son, I.H. Fichte. Fichtes Werke. 1971. ed. Immanuel Hermann Fichte. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter and Co. This is not the favored edition, but I refer to it because many of the English translations have references to it in the Margins. English references are to what were, at the time of this writing, the most recent English translation. References to the first Wissenschaftslehre are by volume and page number (German), or just page number (English). WL/SoK - Fichte, J.G. Wissenschaftslehre (1794-5). Werke vol. 1/Fichte, J.G. Science of Knowledge. Ed. and Trans. Heath, J. Lachs, P. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. !vi Acknowledgments It would not have been possible for me to complete this dissertation without the support of a great many people, some of whom I would like to acknowledge here. A number of these people provided comments on this dissertation which led me to make important changes. Still, I take full responsibility for any errors it may contain. I would like to begin with my committee, whose guidance at every stage of the process was invaluable. My advisor, Fred Neuhouser, provided detailed written feedback on numerous drafts of the chapters which appear in this dissertation. Before the dissertation phase, attending Fred’s courses was a formative experience. It not only laid the foundation for all of my subsequent work on German philosophy but also decisively shaped my conception of the practice of philosophy itself. All throughout graduate school, I looked to Fred’s writings as a model of how to bring clarity and rigor to scholarly discussions of difficult authors like Hegel and Fichte. Yet I am perhaps most grateful of all to Fred for his broader approach to advising which I believe is unique. Fred left space for me to become the best version of myself rather than a duplicate of him. What is more, he seemed excited by the prospect. Beyond his role as my advisor, Fred has been an example for me to emulate in my own life. His intellectual humility, conscientiousness, and humaneness are often on my mind. A true eclectic, Wolfgang-Rainer Mann is the intellectual kindred spirit of this dissertation.
Recommended publications
  • Note: This Is a Pre-Print, Draft Manuscript of Toby Svoboda, Duties Regarding Nature: a Kantian Environmental Ethic (Routledge, 2016)
    Note: This is a pre-print, draft manuscript of Toby Svoboda, Duties Regarding Nature: A Kantian Environmental Ethic (Routledge, 2016). If citing, please consult the published version, which contains substantial revisions. Duties Regarding Nature: A Kantian Environmental Ethic Draft of Complete Manuscript Toby Svoboda Table of Contents • Introduction: Kant and Environmental Ethics • Chapter 1: Traditional Approaches to Environmental Ethics • Chapter 2: Kantian Approaches to Animal Ethics and Environmental Ethics • Chapter 3: Indirect Duties, Moral Perfection, and Virtuous Dispositions • Chapter 4: Teleology and Non-Human Flourishing • Chapter 5: A Kantian Environmental Virtue Ethic • Conclusion: Advantages of the Kantian Environmental Virtue Ethic • References Introduction, 1 Introduction: Kant and Environmental Ethics Why Environmental Ethics? I have set out in this book to develop and defend a Kantian approach to environmental ethics. This immediately raises a question: why should we want an environmental ethic at all, much less a Kantian one? Human beings face serious environmental problems, such as those associated with climate change, loss of biodiversity, and air pollution.1 It seems clear that these problems have various ethical dimensions, given that they threaten to increase human mortality rates, cause substantial harm to present and future generations, and exacerbate socio-economic injustice.2 Moreover, the impact of human activities on the environment, such as ocean acidification due to anthropogenic emissions of greenhouse
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Assertoric Syllogistic and Modern Relevance Logic*
    Aristotle’s assertoric syllogistic and modern relevance logic* Abstract: This paper sets out to evaluate the claim that Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic is a relevance logic or shows significant similarities with it. I prepare the grounds for a meaningful comparison by extracting the notion of relevance employed in the most influential work on modern relevance logic, Anderson and Belnap’s Entailment. This notion is characterized by two conditions imposed on the concept of validity: first, that some meaning content is shared between the premises and the conclusion, and second, that the premises of a proof are actually used to derive the conclusion. Turning to Aristotle’s Prior Analytics, I argue that there is evidence that Aristotle’s Assertoric Syllogistic satisfies both conditions. Moreover, Aristotle at one point explicitly addresses the potential harmfulness of syllogisms with unused premises. Here, I argue that Aristotle’s analysis allows for a rejection of such syllogisms on formal grounds established in the foregoing parts of the Prior Analytics. In a final section I consider the view that Aristotle distinguished between validity on the one hand and syllogistic validity on the other. Following this line of reasoning, Aristotle’s logic might not be a relevance logic, since relevance is part of syllogistic validity and not, as modern relevance logic demands, of general validity. I argue that the reasons to reject this view are more compelling than the reasons to accept it and that we can, cautiously, uphold the result that Aristotle’s logic is a relevance logic. Keywords: Aristotle, Syllogism, Relevance Logic, History of Logic, Logic, Relevance 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Forthcoming in the Kant Yearbook, Vol. 11 (2019) Final Draft – Please Cite the Published Version for Correct Pagination
    Forthcoming in The Kant Yearbook, Vol. 11 (2019) Final Draft – Please cite the published version for correct pagination Can there be a Finite Interpretation of the Kantian Sublime? Sacha Golob (King’s College London) Abstract Kant’s account of the sublime makes frequent appeals to infinity, appeals which have been extensively criticised by commentators such as Budd and Crowther. This paper examines the costs and benefits of reconstructing the account in finitist terms. On the one hand, drawing on a detailed comparison of the first and third Critiques, I argue that the underlying logic of Kant’s position is essentially finitist. I defend the approach against longstanding objections, as well as addressing recent infinitist work by Moore and Smith. On the other hand, however, I argue that finitism faces distinctive problems of its own: whilst the resultant theory is a coherent and interesting one, it is unclear in what sense it remains an analysis of the sublime. I illustrate the worry by juxtaposing the finitist reading with analytical cubism. §1 – Introduction Kant’s account of the sublime makes frequent reference to infinity. The “intuition” of the sublime “carries with it the idea of...infinity”; apprehension “can progress to infinity” [kann…ins Unendliche gehen]; imagination “strives to progress towards infinity” [ein Bestreben zum Fortschritte ins Unendliche]; reason demands that we “think the infinite as a whole” (KU 5:255, 252, 250, 254).1 It is obvious that the infinite played a central role in Kant’s own presentation of the problem. It is less clear whether such references are 1 References are to the standard Akademie edition of Kant’s gesammelte Schriften (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1900–; abbreviated as Ak.): Anth: Anthropologie in pragmatischer Hinsicht (Ak.
    [Show full text]
  • Dr. Theodore George Professor and Head Department of Philosophy
    Dr. Theodore George Professor and Head Department of Philosophy Texas A&M University [email protected] Areas of specialization: Gadamer, contemporary hermeneutics, contemporary continental ethics, philosophy of art and aesthetics, Hegel, German Idealism and Romanticism Areas of competence: continental European philosophy since Kant, the history of Western philosophy Education: Ph.D. in Philosophy, Villanova University, 2000 Dissertation: “Hegel’s Speculative Theory of Political Life: Community and Tragedy in the Phenomenology of Spirit” Committee: Dr. Dennis Schmidt (Director), Dr. Walter Brogan, Dr. Julie Klein Fulbright Fellow, Eberhard Karls University of Tübingen, 1998–1999 Host: Prof. Dr. Günter Figal M.A. in Philosophy, Villanova University, 1997 B.A. in Philosophy and German (double major), Whitman College, 1993 Cum Laude, with honors and distinction in Philosophy and with distinction in German Thesis: “The Structure of Rebirth in Walden: A Connection with Thus Spoke Zarathustra” Appointments: Head, Department of Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2015–present (Research leave 2018–2019; Interim Head 2014–2015) Professor of Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2020–present Associate Professor of Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2007–2020 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Texas A&M University, 2001–2007 Honorary Appointment: Senior Researcher, College of Fellows, Philosophy Research Institute, Western Sydney University, Sydney, Australia, 2016–present Editorial Positions: Editor, Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy, 2012–present
    [Show full text]
  • Hegel's Philosophy of Biology?
    Article title: Hegel’s Philosophy of Biology? A Programmatic Overview Short title: Hegel’s Philosophy of Biology? Article type: Research article Authors: Andrea Gambarotto (corresponding) & Luca Illetterati Affiliation: Institut Supérieur de Philosophie, UC Louvain, Belgium Email: [email protected] Abstract: This paper presents what we call ‘Hegel’s philosophy of biology’ to a target audience of both Hegel scholars and philosophers of biology. It also serves to introduce a special issue of the Hegel Bulletin entirely dedicated to a first mapping of this yet to be explored domain of Hegel studies. We submit that Hegel’s philosophy of biology can be understood as a radicalization of the Kantian approach to organisms, and as prefiguring current philosophy of biology in important ways, especially with regard to the nature of biological organization, the role of teleology in biological explanation, and the relation between life and cognition. 1 I. Introduction The concept of life is a key concept of classical German philosophy as a whole and it would be reductive to think of it only in biological terms. The attention to the notion of life in the post-Kantian debate has a critical function with respect to all forms of dualism that have marked modern philosophy: those between soul and body, thought and world, and therefore, of course, spirit and nature. Life is, in fact, for post-Kantian philosophers, an embodied soul or an animated body, a mind that is never entirely separated from nature. From the very beginning of his philosophical quest, Hegel’s work presents itself as a ‘philosophy of life’, that is a philosophy that must do justice to the multiform experience of life, without falling into the abstract image provided by the intellect (Verstand), where the dynamism and vitality (Lebendigkeit) of concrete reality gets lost.
    [Show full text]
  • Eligible Journals (PDF)
    Last Update: 2021-07-08 CUP Open Access Agreement UNIVIE 2020-01-01 until 2022-12-31 Eligible Journals Acta Neuropsychiatrica Acta Numerica Advances in Archaeological Practice Africa African Studies Review Ageing & Society Agricultural and Resource Economics Review AI EDAM AJIL Unbound American Antiquity American Journal of International Law American Journal of Law & Medicine American Political Science Review Americas Anatolian Studies Ancient Mesoamerica Anglo-Saxon England Animal Health Research Reviews Annals of Actuarial Science Annals of Glaciology Annual Review of Applied Linguistics Antarctic Science Antimicrobial Stewardship & Healthcare Epidemiology Antiquaries Journal Antiquity ANZIAM Journal Applied Psycholinguistics APSIPA Transactions on Signal and Information Processing Arabic Sciences and Philosophy Archaeological Dialogues Archaeological Reports Architectural History arq: Architectural Research Quarterly Art Libraries Journal Asian Journal of Comparative Law Asian Journal of International Law Asian Journal of Law and Society ASTIN Bulletin: The Journal of the IAA Australasian Journal of Special and Inclusive Education page 1 of 8 Australian Journal of Environmental Education Australian Journal of Indigenous Education Austrian History Yearbook Behaviour Change Behavioural and Cognitive Psychotherapy Behavioural Public Policy Bilingualism: Language and Cognition Biological Imaging Bird Conservation International BJHS Themes BJPsych Advances BJPsych Bulletin BJPsych International BJPsych Open Brain Impairment Britannia British
    [Show full text]
  • For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Emory University, [email protected]
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 4 | Issue 1 Article 3 2018 For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Emory University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/fpq Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, European History Commons, Feminist Philosophy Commons, History of Philosophy Commons, Other Feminist, Gender, and Sexuality Studies Commons, Race, Ethnicity and Post-Colonial Studies Commons, and the Women's Studies Commons Recommended Citation Huseyinzadegan, Dilek. 2018. "For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon." Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 4, (1). Article 3. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/fpq/vol4/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Feminist Philosophy Quarterly by an authorized editor of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Huseyinzadegan: For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? For What Can the Kantian Feminist Hope? Constructive Complicity in Appropriations of the Canon Dilek Huseyinzadegan Abstract As feminist scholars, we hope that our own work is exempt from structural problems such as racism, sexism, and Eurocentrism, that is, the kind of problems that are exemplified and enacted by Kant’s works. In other words, we hope that we do not re-enact, implicitly or explicitly, Kant’s problematic claims, which range from the unnaturalness of a female philosopher, “who might as well have a beard,” the stupid things that a black carpenter said “because he was black from head to foot,” the poor women “living in the greatest slavery in the Orient,” to the “sheep-like existence of the inhabitants of Tahiti.” In this piece, I argue that we cannot simply hope to avoid these problems unless we are vigilant about incorporating the full picture of Kant’s and Kantian philosophy into our feminist appropriations.
    [Show full text]
  • Dr Andrew Stephenson
    CV (short) DR ANDREW STEPHENSON Trinity College Email: [email protected] Oxford OX BH Website: www.acstephenson.com AOS: KANT AOC: Mind, Epistemology, Religion, Post- Kantian Philosophy, Wittgenstein EMPLOYMENT Apr - Apr Leverhulme Research Fellow, Humboldt University, Berlin Oct - Mar Career Development Lecturer, Trinity College, Oxford EDUCATION - D.Phil. in Philosophy (cont.), University of Oxford - Leave of Absence due to serious spinal injury – fully recovered - Language Student, Stiftung Maximilianeum and LMU, Munich - D.Phil. in Philosophy, University of Oxford - B.Phil. in Philosophy, University of Oxford - B.A. in Philosophy, Cardiff University RESEARCH Articles • Kant, the Paradox of Knowability, and the Meaning of ‘Experience’, Philosophers’ Imprint (forthcoming) • Imagination and Phenomenal Character, in Kant and the Philosophy of Mind (Oxford University Press, forthcoming) • Kant on the Object-Dependence of Intuition and Hallucination, The Philosophical Quarterly () • Kant’s Deduction from Apperception?, Studi Kantiani (), - • Kant on Non-Veridical Experience, Kant Yearbook (), - Book (editor) • Kant and the Philosophy of Mind: New Essays on Consciousness, Judgement, and the Self, co-edited with Anil Gomes, Oxford University Press (forthcoming) Under Review (available from website or on request) • Kant, A Priori Knowability, and Tacit Knowledge Some Recent/Upcoming Presentations • Kant and the Logic of Knowability, Sept , International Kant Congress, Vienna • Kant’s Manifest Realism?, Sept , Colloquium
    [Show full text]
  • Kierkegaard's Socrates: a Venture in Evolutionary Theory.” Modern Theology 17(4): 442-473
    1 THE PROBLEM OF KIERKEGAARD ’S SOCRATES DANIEL WATTS This essay re-examines Kierkegaard’s view of Socrates. I consider the problem that arises from Kierkegaard’s appeal to Socrates as an exemplar for irony. The problem is that he also appears to think that, as an exemplar for irony, Socrates cannot be represented. And part of the problem is the paradox of self-reference that immediately arises from trying to represent x as unrepresentable. On the solution I propose, Kierkegaard does not hold that, as an exemplar for irony, Socrates is in no way representable. Rather, he holds that, as an exemplar for irony, Socrates cannot be represented in a purely disinterested way. I show how, in The Concept of Irony , Kierkegaard makes use of ‘limiting cases’ of representation in order to bring Socrates into view as one who defies purely disinterested representation. I also show how this approach to Socrates connects up with Kierkegaard’s more general interest in the problem of ethical exemplarity, where the problem is how ethical exemplars can be given as such, that is, in such a way that purely disinterested contemplation is not the appropriate response to them. Socrates … this puzzling, uncategorizable, inexplicable phenomenon (Nietzsche) A plausible general hypothesis about Kierkegaard is that he modelled his work as an author on Socrates. This supposition helps to explain many features of his work: his self- withdrawing and maieutic gestures, his focus on ethical self-knowledge, his eye for paradoxes, his animus against those he regarded as modern-day sophists, his professions of ignorance. 1 Further, 1 This hypothesis has long guided Kierkegaard studies, going back at least to David Swenson’s way of introducing Kierkegaard to Anglophone readers, in the 1940s, as a “Danish Socrates” (1983 [1941]).
    [Show full text]
  • Final Draft Jury
    Freedom in Conflict On Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason Jonas Gerlings Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Florence, 24 February 2017. European University Institute Department of History and Civilization Freedom in Conflict On Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason Jonas Gerlings Thesis submitted for assessment with a view to obtaining the degree of Doctor of History and Civilization of the European University Institute Examining Board Prof. Dr. Martin van Gelderen, EUI, Lichtenberg-Kolleg – The Göttingen Institute for Advanced Study (Supervisor) Dr. Dr. h.c. Hans Erich Bödeker, Lichtenberg-Kolleg – The Göttingen Institute for Advanced Study Prof. Stéphane Van Damme, European University Institute Senior Lecturer, Dr. Avi Lifschitz, UCL © Jonas Gerlings, 2016 No part of this thesis may be copied, reproduced or transmitted without prior permission of the author Researcher declaration to accompany the submission of written work Department of History and Civilization - Doctoral Programme I Jonas Gerlings certify that I am the author of the work Freedom in Conflict – Kant’s Critique of Medical Reason I have presented for examination for the Ph.D. at the European University Institute. I also certify that this is solely my own original work, other than where I have clearly indicated, in this declaration and in the thesis, that it is the work of others. I warrant that I have obtained all the permissions required for using any material from other copyrighted publications. I certify that this work complies with the Code of Ethics in Academic Research issued by the European University Institute (IUE 332/2/10 (CA 297).
    [Show full text]
  • Spirit's Embeddedness in Nature: Hegel's Decentring of Self-Legislation
    doi:10.1017/hgl.2020.33 Hegel Bulletin, Page 1 of 20 © The Hegel Society of Great Britain, 2021 Spirit’s Embeddedness in Nature: Hegel’s Decentring of Self-Legislation Heikki Ikäheimo Abstract A recently widely accepted view has it that the nature-spirit distinction in Hegel is to be understood as a distinction between a space or realm that is not normative, or does not involve norms, and one that is or does. Notwithstanding the merits of this view, it has tended to create a separation between nature and spirit which is both philosophically troubling and difficult to reconcile with the picture of Hegel as the arch enemy of abstract or unreconciled dualisms. In this paper I aim to show that the defining phenomenon for this view—collective self-government by norms—is on Hegel’s account both dependent on living nature that involves normativity broadly conceived all the way down and also subject to the ultimate normative or evaluative principle of Hegel’s Philosophy of Spirit —concrete freedom—the essence of spirit according to him. This is to say that for Hegel the normativity of collectively administered norms is neither the most basic nor the highest form of normativity. I. Introduction The view according to which Geist or ‘spirit’ in Hegel stands for some metaphys- ically suspicious, spooky entity, transcendent principle behind the appearing world, or a neo-Platonic One whose emanation the world is, has been out of favour for quite some time now. The recently widely accepted view, one that has demarcated itself against the first mentioned one, is that ‘spirit’ in fact stands for the Sellarsian ‘space of reasons’, or as it is often put the ‘space or realm of norms’ or the ‘nor- mative realm’.
    [Show full text]
  • Morganna F. Lambeth Department of Philosophy [email protected] Purdue University 773-682-2320 West Lafayette, in 47907-2098
    Morganna F. Lambeth Department of Philosophy [email protected] Purdue University 773-682-2320 West Lafayette, IN 47907-2098 Current Position 2018-2021 Purdue University, Postdoctoral Fellow in Philosophy and Cornerstone Fall 2018 Instruction: PHIL 111: Ethics (2 x 35 students) Spring 2019 Instruction: SCLA 101: Transformative Texts (30 students) PHIL 411: Modern Ethical Theories (35 students) Education 2011-2018 Northwestern University, Doctoral Program in Philosophy Ph.D. in Philosophy Dissertation: Rethinking the Structure of Events: Heidegger on Kant and the Concept of Cause Committee: Cristina Lafont (Chair), Rachel Zuckert, Mark Wrathall ABSTRACT: I draw on Heidegger’s interpretation of Kant to argue that Kant overestimates the role that causality plays in structuring our experience. Heidegger suggests that Kant’s analysis of experience mistakenly universalizes a fraction of our experience: the experience of mechanical objects. I defend the merits of this suggestion by offering a careful reconstruction of Heidegger’s controversial interpretation of the imagination and applying this interpretation in detail to one of the most debated segments of the Critique of Pure Reason: the Second Analogy. In this chapter, Kant suggests that we must employ the concept of cause in order to be aware that an event (i.e. a change in states) has occurred. While Kant’s mechanical account of events captures our experience of mechanical objects, I argue that his analysis does not capture our experience of events initiated by humans. I suggest that we experience human events rather as components of an overarching project oriented toward some goal. 2009-2011 University of California at Riverside, Doctoral Program in Philosophy M.A.
    [Show full text]