Complicity, Cause and Blame: a Study in the Interpretation of Doctrine
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Criminal Procedure in England and the United States: Comparisons in Initiating Prosecutions
Fordham Law Review Volume 49 Issue 1 Article 8 1980 Criminal Procedure in England and the United States: Comparisons in Initiating Prosecutions Irving R. Kaufman Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Digital Par t of the Law Commons Commons Network Recommended Citation Logo Irving R. Kaufman, Criminal Procedure in England and the United States: Comparisons in Initiating Prosecutions, 49 Fordham L. Rev. 26 (1980). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol49/iss1/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Criminal Procedure in England and the United States: Comparisons in Initiating Prosecutions Cover Page Footnote Circuit Judge, United States Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit; Chief Judge (1973-1980). District Court Judge (1949-1961) and Assistant United States Attorney (1935-1940) in the Southern District of New York. Chairman of the Executive Committee and former President of the Institute of Judicial Administration. This article is available in Fordham Law Review: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol49/iss1/8 CRIMINAL PROCEDURE IN ENGLAND AND THE UNITED STATES: COMPARISONS IN INITIATING PROSECUTIONS IRVING R. KAUFMAN* THE legal institutions of Great Britain have long served as the well-spring of American law. In drafting the Federal Constitution, the framers embellished British conceptions of a government of sepa- rated powers,' and drew on the enactments of Parliament. -
A Rationale of Criminal Negligence Roy Mitchell Moreland University of Kentucky
Kentucky Law Journal Volume 32 | Issue 2 Article 2 1944 A Rationale of Criminal Negligence Roy Mitchell Moreland University of Kentucky Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj Part of the Criminal Law Commons, and the Torts Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits you. Recommended Citation Moreland, Roy Mitchell (1944) "A Rationale of Criminal Negligence," Kentucky Law Journal: Vol. 32 : Iss. 2 , Article 2. Available at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/klj/vol32/iss2/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Kentucky Law Journal by an authorized editor of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A RATIONALE OF CRIMINAL NEGLIGENCE (Continued from November issue) RoY MOREL A D* 2. METHODS Op DESCRIBING THE NEGLIGENCE REQUIRED 'FOR CRIMINAL LIABILITY The proposed formula for criminal negligence describes the higher degree of negligence required for criminal liability as "conduct creating such an unreasonable risk to life, safety, property, or other interest for the unintentional invasion of which the law prescribes punishment, as to be recklessly disre- gardful of such interest." This formula, like all such machinery, is, of necessity, ab- stractly stated so as to apply to a multitude of cases. As in the case of all abstractions, it is difficult to understand without explanation and illumination. What devices can be used to make it intelligible to judges and juries in individual cases q a. -
Disclosure and Accuracy in the Guilty Plea Process Kevin C
Hastings Law Journal Volume 40 | Issue 5 Article 2 1-1989 Disclosure and Accuracy in the Guilty Plea Process Kevin C. McMunigal Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Kevin C. McMunigal, Disclosure and Accuracy in the Guilty Plea Process, 40 Hastings L.J. 957 (1989). Available at: https://repository.uchastings.edu/hastings_law_journal/vol40/iss5/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Hastings Law Journal by an authorized editor of UC Hastings Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Disclosure and Accuracy in the Guilty Plea Process by KEVIN C. MCMUNIGAL* Consider the following disclosure problem. The government indicts a defendant on an armed robbery charge arising from a violent mugging. The prosecution's case is based entirely on the testimony of the victim, who identified the defendant from police photographs of persons with a record of similar violent crime. With only the victim's testimony to rely on, the prosecutor is unsure of her ability to obtain a conviction at trial. She offers the defendant a guilty plea limiting his sentencing exposure to five years, a significant concession in light of the defendant's substantial prior record and the fact that the charged offense carries a maximum penalty of fifteen years incarceration. As trial nears, the victim's confi- dence in the identification appears to wane. The robbery took place at night. He was frightened and saw his assailant for a matter of seconds. -
Liability Without Fault: Logic and Potential of a Developing Concept
University at Buffalo School of Law Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law Journal Articles Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1970 Liability without Fault: Logic and Potential of a Developing Concept Janet S. Lindgren University at Buffalo School of Law Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/journal_articles Part of the Criminal Law Commons Recommended Citation Janet S. Lindgren, Liability without Fault: Logic and Potential of a Developing Concept, 1970 Wis. L. Rev. 1201 (1970). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/journal_articles/789 Copyright 1970 by The Board of Regents of the University of Wisconsin System; Reprinted by permission of the Wisconsin Law Review. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Journal Articles by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. LIABILITY WITHOUT FAULT: LOGIC AND POTENTIAL OF A DEVELOPING CONCEPT I. INTRODUCTION The imposition of criminal liability for an unlawful act without a required showing of mental state (often termed "strict liability" or "liability without fault") has been resorted to increasingly in the last 70 years.' In the broad context of the historical development of criminal liability, in which emphasis has been placed on moral blameworthiness, liability without fault has been viewed alter- nately as an illogical development 2 or as distinguishable in theory from the "true crimes of the classic law."' 3 This comment will dem- onstrate that, whatever may be one's emotional response to liability without fault, a rational and logical analysis of criminal liability can be made which accepts the imposition of criminal liability without a showing of fault. -
Criminal Law -- Homicide -- Application of Felony-Murder Rule When Non-Felon Kills Felon, 34 N.C
NORTH CAROLINA LAW REVIEW Volume 34 | Number 3 Article 10 4-1-1956 Criminal Law -- Homicide -- Application of Felony- Murder Rule When Non-Felon Kills Felon James P. Crews Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation James P. Crews, Criminal Law -- Homicide -- Application of Felony-Murder Rule When Non-Felon Kills Felon, 34 N.C. L. Rev. 350 (1956). Available at: http://scholarship.law.unc.edu/nclr/vol34/iss3/10 This Note is brought to you for free and open access by Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in North Carolina Law Review by an authorized editor of Carolina Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NORTH CAROLINA LAW REVIEW (Vol. 34 ideas by words, pictures, or drawings; and that to uphold the Post- master General's revocation would be saying that Congress granted him the power of censorship, or the power to alone determine whether a publication is good or bad for the public to read. This, said the court, would be a radical change from the other standards regarding classifica- tions, and "such a power is so abhorrent to our traditions that it '2 6 should not be easily inferred. The Postmaster General in Esquire relied on the holding of Mil- waukee Publishing Company, but as has been pointed out the matter involved in the latter case was completely nonmailable. It appears then that anything which the Postmaster General may properly declare non- mailable, he may exclude from the second-class without denying mailing privileges entirely, but where the matter involved is mailable he must objectively apply the standards set by Congress. -
A Look at Complicity by Omission Domestically and Abroad
\\server05\productn\B\BIN\22-2\BIN205.txt unknown Seq: 1 14-JAN-05 14:12 LOOKING ABROAD TO PROTECT MOTHERS AT HOME: A LOOK AT COMPLICITY BY OMISSION DOMESTICALLY AND ABROAD I. INTRODUCTION ............................................ 425 R II. COMPLICITY BY OMISSION FOR MURDER IN THE U.S.: A CASE STUDY OF PEOPLE V. PETERS ....................... 430 R A. Background ........................................... 430 R B. The Law .............................................. 431 R III. DOMESTIC GUIDANCE ..................................... 432 R A. Domestic Federal Guidance ............................ 432 R B. Further Domestic Guidance: U.S. Model Penal Code ... 433 R IV. THE INTERNATIONAL PERSPECTIVE ........................ 435 R A. English Criminal Law ................................. 435 R B. Canadian Criminal Law ............................... 438 R C. French Criminal Law .................................. 439 R D. Analysis ............................................... 442 R V. CONCLUSION .............................................. 446 R “A person may cause evil to others not only by his actions but by his inaction, and in either case he is justly accountable to them for the injury.”1 – John Stewart Mill I. INTRODUCTION For most crimes two elemens need to be proven: the actus reus and the mens rea. Generally, the actus reus of an offense consists of a voluntary act that causes social harm.2 In cases where the defendant has an affirma- tive duty to act, however, a defendant’s omission of that duty may serve as a substitute for the voluntary act.3 Affirmative duties to protect are 1 JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY 11 (Elizabeth Rapaport ed., Hackett Publ’g Co. 1985) (1859). 2 For a thorough discussion of the two elements, see JOSHUA DRESSLER, UNDERSTANDING CRIMINAL LAW 81-142 (3d ed. 2001). These generalizations are based on American law, and differences in the international law, if any, will be discussed within the relevant section. -
IN the SUPREME COURT of CANADA (On Appeal from the Court of Appeal of Alberta)
S.C.C. File No. 32912 IN THE SUPREME COURT OF CANADA (On Appeal from the Court of Appeal of Alberta) Between: MICHAEL ERIN BRISCOE Appellant (Respondent) - and - HER MAJESTY THE QUEEN Respondent (Appellant) FACTUM OF THE CROWN RESPONDENT ATTORNEY GENERAL OF ALBERTA PURSUANT TO RULE 42 OF THE RULES OF THE SUPREME COURT OF CANADA JAMES C. ROBB, Q.C. and HENRY S. BROWN, Q.C. TAMARA FRIESEN Cowling Lafleur Henderson LLP Appeals Branch, Alberta Justice Suite 2600, 160 Elgin Street 3rd Floor North Bowker Bldg. Ottawa, ON 9833 - 109 Street KIP lC3 Edmonton, AB Tel: (613) 233-1781 T5K 2E8 Fax: (613) 563-9869 Tel: (780) 427-5042 email: i~ewy.bro~vn@,~li~igs.c.om Fax: (780) 422-1 106 email: james.robb~gov.ab.ca Counsel for the Respondent Ottawa Agent for the Respondent ALEXANDER D. PRINGLE, Q.C. JEFFREY BEEDELL Pringle, Peterson, MacDonald & Bottos Lang Michener LLP Barristers & Solicitors Barristers & Solicitors 100 Street Place 300, 50 O'Connor Street 300, 10150 - 100 Street Ottawa, ON KIP 6L2 Edmonton, AB T5J OP6 Tel: (613) 232-7171 Phone: (780) 424-8866 Fax: (613) 231-3191 Fax: (780) 426-1470 email: jbeedellG$lanm~ichener.ca email: apringle($p&leandassociates.coin Counsel for the Appellant Ottawa Agent for the Appellant TABLE OF CONTENTS PAGE PART I: STATEMENT OF FACTS .................................................................................1 (0 Overview of Case .......................................................................................1 .. (11) Evidence at Trial ........................................................................................2 -
Law Culpable Homicide Substantive Criminal
LAW SUBSTANTIVE CRIMINAL LAW CULPABLE HOMICIDE Quadrant-I (B) Description of Module: Description of Module Subject Name Law Paper Name Substantive Criminal Law Module Name/Title Culpable Homicide Not Amounting to Murder Module Id Module 05 Pre-requisites A foundational understanding of the basic principles of criminal law. Objectives To understand culpable homicide and how it differs from murder Keywords Homicide, murder, knowledge Quadrant – II – e-Text CULPABLE HOMICIDE Introduction Some crimes are creations of statutes. These are called statutory offences. Other crimes come from years of judicial decisions together with legal principles founded on Institutional Writers. These are called common law offences. Murder and culpable homicide are both common law offences. Most common law offences require two essential elements before there can be a conviction. There must be a guilty act (called actus reus) and a guilty mind (mens rea). The degree and extent of the guilty mind can vary from crime to crime. For a conviction for any common law offence however there must be some degree of guilty mind (mensrea). Homicide means the killing of a human being by a human being1. Homicide is the highest order of bodily injury that can be inflicted on a human body. Since it is considered as a most serious harm which may be inflicted upon another person, it bags maximum punishment. Under Indian law and US law imposes death penalty2 and in English law proposes mandatory life imprisonment. However in every case of homicide the culprit is not culpable. There may be cases where a law will not punish a man for committing homicide. -
What Does Intent Mean?
WHAT DOES INTENT MEAN? David Crump* I. INTRODUCTION ................................................................. 1060 II. PROTOTYPICAL EXAMPLES OF INTENT DEFINITIONS......... 1062 A. Intent as “Purpose” ..................................................... 1062 B. Intent as Knowledge, Awareness, or the Like ............ 1063 C. Imprecise Definitions, Including Those Not Requiring Either Purpose or Knowledge .................. 1066 D. Specific Intent: What Does It Mean?.......................... 1068 III. THE AMBIGUITY OF THE INTENT DEFINITIONS.................. 1071 A. Proof of Intent and Its Implications for Defining Intent: Circumstantial Evidence and the Jury ........... 1071 B. The Situations in Which Intent Is Placed in Controversy, and the Range of Rebuttals that May Oppose It................................................................... 1074 IV. WHICH DEFINITIONS OF INTENT SHOULD BE USED FOR WHAT KINDS OF MISCONDUCT?....................................... 1078 V. CONCLUSION .................................................................... 1081 * A.B. Harvard College; J.D. University of Texas School of Law. John B. Neibel Professor of Law, University of Houston Law Center. 1059 1060 HOFSTRA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 38:1059 I. INTRODUCTION Imagine a case featuring a manufacturing shop boss who sent his employees into a toxic work environment. As happens at many job sites, hazardous chemicals unavoidably were nearby, and safety always was a matter of reducing their concentration. This attempted solution, however, may mean that dangerous levels of chemicals remain. But this time, the level of toxicity was far higher than usual. There is strong evidence that the shop boss knew about the danger, at least well enough to have realized that it probably had reached a deadly level, but the shop boss disputes this evidence. The employees all became ill, and one of them has died. The survivors sue in an attempt to recover damages for wrongful death. -
Rethinking Complicity and Survival in Paula Vogel's How I Learned to Drive
Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University English Theses Department of English 5-8-2020 “SHE’S A SLY ONE:” RETHINKING COMPLICITY AND SURVIVAL IN PAULA VOGEL’S HOW I LEARNED TO DRIVE Mary Ann Barfield Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_theses Recommended Citation Barfield, Mary Ann, "“SHE’S A SLY ONE:” RETHINKING COMPLICITY AND SURVIVAL IN PAULA VOGEL’S HOW I LEARNED TO DRIVE." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2020. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/english_theses/252 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of English at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in English Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. “SHE’S A SLY ONE:” RETHINKING COMPLICITY AND SURVIVAL IN PAULA VOGEL’S HOW I LEARNED TO DRIVE by MARY ANN BARFIELD Under the Direction of Matthew Roudané ABSTRACT In an early 1998 interview, playwright, Paula Vogel, sat in conversation with Arthur Holmberg to discuss the ambivalent victim-perpetrator power dynamics in her critically- acclaimed play, How I Learned to Drive, explaining that “there are two forgivenesses in the play. one forgiveness for Peck, but the most crucial forgiveness would be Li’l Bit’s forgiving Li’l Bit. Li’l Bit as an adult looking at and understanding her complicity.” Since the Holmberg interview, critics have made only passing references to Vogel’s discussion of complicity in play reviews and critical essays. This thesis represents the first sustained engagement with complicity as an ethical subject to argue that Li’l Bit’s dependence upon her uncle for emotional and sometimes physical survival exempts her from moral scrutiny in the course of his abuse. -
1 the Corporate Agent in Criminal
1 THE CORPORATE AGENT IN CRIMINAL LAW – AN ARGUMENT FOR COMPREHENSIVE IDENTIFICATION MARK DSOUZA* The doctrine of identification is often used to explain how corporations can commit criminal offences in their own right. Courts identify the natural persons who can be said to personify the corporation, and attribute their conduct and mental states to the corporation. However, current versions of the doctrine of identification suffer from several well-documented shortcomings. This paper sets out, and gives serious consideration to, a reformulated version of the identification doctrine that has the potential to addresses many of these shortcomings. In Section I, I explain how the doctrine of identification promotes the sociological legitimacy of corporate criminal law by allowing it to piggyback on the sociological legitimacy of the criminal law as it applies to natural persons. Next, in Section II, I describe the existing versions of the doctrine of identification, and the problems with them. In Section III, I argue that because the various alternatives to the identification doctrine might tend to undermine the sociological legitimacy of corporate criminal law, a suitably reformulated rule of identification would be preferable to abandoning identification altogether. Section IV describes such a reformulation, viz. comprehensive identification (CI). CI would attribute to corporations both the actions, and the mental states, of each of its employees acting in the course of their employment, that is to say, within the scope of their real or ostensible authority. While it would vastly expand the scope of corporate criminal liability, I demonstrate that it would also correct or ameliorate many of the problems that existing versions of the identification doctrine generate. -
Complicity with Evil M
Boston College Law School Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School Boston College Law School Faculty Papers October 2003 Complicity with Evil M. Cathleen Kaveny Boston College Law School, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/lsfp Part of the Common Law Commons, Criminal Law Commons, and the Ethics in Religion Commons Recommended Citation M. Cathleen Kaveny. "Complicity with Evil." Criterion (2003): 20-29. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Boston College Law School Faculty Papers by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Boston College Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. COMPLICITY WITH EVIL M. Cathleen Kaveny hen asked what project I am working on while on leave at the Martin Marty Center during the 2002–2003 academic year, the short response I usually give is “complicity with evil.” That response is perfect for cocktail parties in the big city and receptions at large academic conferences. It appears to be glamorous, dangerous, sexy—and hopelessly vague. Unfortunately, like many phenomena at such parties and receptions, the surface impression is actually quite deceptive. The issues that I actually deal with are her contemplated action in light of its connection with the highly specific, and can range from the riveting and heart- wrongful action of another? What considerations should be breaking to the sadly mundane. involved in her decision whether or not to go ahead with The topic of complicity encompasses the following her action? dilemma: Should Sophie Zawistowska, the title character in The more theoretical elaboration of the problem reveals William Styron’s unforgettable novel Sophie’s Choice, have a structural similarity between the two concrete dilemmas accepted the SS physician’s offer to allow her to decide described above.