C. I. Lewis: History and Philosophy of Logic John Corcoran

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

C. I. Lewis: History and Philosophy of Logic John Corcoran C. I. Lewis: History and Philosophy of Logic John Corcoran Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy, Volume 42, Number 1, Winter 2006, pp. 1-9 (Article) Published by Indiana University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/csp.2006.0005 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/200088 [ This content has been declared free to read by the pubisher during the COVID-19 pandemic. ] C. I. Lewis (1883–1964) was the first major figure in history and philosophy of logic—a field that has come to be recognized as a sepa- rate specialty after years of work by Ivor Grat- tan-Guinness and others (Dawson 2003, 257). Lewis was among the earliest to accept the challenges offered by this field; he was the first who had the philosophical and mathematical C. I. Lewis talent, the philosophical, logical, and historical History and Philosophy background, and the patience and dedication of Logic to objectivity needed to excel. He was blessed with many fortunate circumstances, not least John Corcoran of which was entering the field when mathe- matical logic, after only six decades of toil, had just reaped one of its most important harvests with publication of the monumental Principia Mathematica. It was a time of joyful optimism which demanded an historical account and a sober philosophical critique. Lewis was one of the first to apply to math- ematical logic the Aristotelian dictum that we do not understand a living institution until we see it growing from its birth. He will always be regarded as a unique authority on the founding of mathematical logic because he began his meticulous and broadly informed study of its history when it had reached a certain maturity as a field, but before its later explosive develop- ment had a chance to cloud our understanding of its founding and formative years. Lewis’s judgment that Boole was the founder of mathe- matical logic, the person whose work began the continuous development of the subject, stands as a massive obstacle to revisionists whose philo- sophical or nationalistic commitments render this fact inconvenient. Lewis’s articles and books form an essential part not only of history and philosophy of logic, but of logic itself. His criticism of lapses in rigor in Principia Mathematica served to notify generations of logicians that proof was not to be identified with formalistic manipulation of esoteric formulas. TRANSACTIONS OF THE CHARLES S. PEIRCE SOCIETY Vol. 42, No. 1 ©2006 The welcome and long-awaited publication of Murray Murphey’s mas- terful intellectual biography C. I. Lewis: The Last Great Pragmatist (Albany: SUNY Press, 2005) is occasion to reexamine Lewis’s contribution to this field. Thankfully, Murphey saw fit to include ample discussion of the logi- cal aspect of Lewis’s wide-ranging thought—which in its full scope goes far beyond history and philosophy of logic. As Murphey indicates, logic was a small part of the Lewis legacy. He is regarded as a towering figure by many who have little or no appreciation of his great achievements in history and philosophy of logic. I cannot speculate on whether future philosophers will continue to give high marks to Lewis as an epistemologist, a metaphysician, or a value theorist, but I am confident that no historian of logic will be able TRANSACTIONS to ignore his work as a historian of logic, and I strongly suspect and hope that his stature as a philosopher of logic will only increase. Of course, even had he never written a word of history of logic or of philosophy of logic, as the founder of modern modal logic his status as a logician would have been secure. He has a permanent place in history of logic. This commentary does not begin to do justice to Murphey’s excellent treatment of Lewis’s logic and contribution to history and philosophy of logic. Rather it aims to complement Murphey’s book with comments inter- relating Lewis’s ideas and connecting them with those of others. It is a pleasure to write this commentary, not only as a tribute to Lewis’s contribu- tion to the field but also because I feel a deep affinity with him as a philoso- pher of logic. I think that Lewis had excellent logical instincts and that he was basically right on important and controversial issues that other “more sophisticated” philosophers of logic were impatient with. Other great philosophers of logic were sometimes dogmatic, cavalier, elitist, arrogant, scientistic, evasive, arbitrary, self-righteous, or dismissive of legitimate criti- cism; Lewis was humanistic, serious, patient, responsible, sensitive and open-minded. He always gives the impression that he would listen to any informed objection. Many of my views are developments, refinements, or variants of views Lewis held or would have held. I should say at the outset, however, that— contrary to Lewis—I was never attracted to the Frege-Russell logicism that held that all of mathematics is tautological. I could not accept the first step —the idea that number theory is composed exclusively of laws of logic. I could see that ambiguities would make it possible for an intelligent person to construe the equation “5 + 7 = 12” as tautological; but I could not see how such a thing could be said for an inequation such as “5 + 7 ≠ 13”. The view that inequations are tautological is one even Russell himself came to retract, but which Lewis never doubted (Lewis-Langford 1932, 211f, Murphey, 82). Logic Includes Formal Epistemology Before Boole, logic was focused on two central problems of logic as formal epistemology: how to show that a given conclusion follows from given prem- ises that formally imply it, and how to show that a given conclusion does not 2 follow from given premises that do not formally imply it. Aristotle wanted a ofC. I. Lewis: History and Philosophy Logic decisive test or criterion for determining if the conclusion follows, and a deci- sive test or criterion for determining if the conclusion does not follow. Using other equally traditional terminology, the two central problems were how to establish validity and how to establish invalidity of an arbitrary argument, no matter how many premises or how complicated its propositions. Aristotle did not solve the problem of formal epistemology in its full generality, nor did he claim to—contrary to what a few later authors seemed to have thought (Cohen-Nagel 1934, 110). Although he believed or even knew that he had completed “the logic of categorical propositions”, he never thought that he had completed logic. In the opinion of many logicians today, perhaps not a majority, the full problem has still not been solved (despite occasional enthusiastic statements that it has). Aristotle would never have written what Lewis wrote (1932, 72): “Given premises and con- clusion, logic can determine whether this conclusion follows”. This is one of many places where Lewis implicitly aligns himself with Aristotle and Boole by endorsing the traditional view that logic includes for- • mal epistemology, even though at the same time he over-estimates modern Corcoran John achievements. Elsewhere Lewis says that logic can be thought of as an “organon” of demonstrative knowledge or as a “canon of deductive infer- ence” (1932, 235 and Murphey, Ch. 3). As we will see, Lewis does not limit logic to formal epistemology, to the concern with determining validity or invalidity of premise-conclusion arguments. In this regard he agrees with Boole and disagrees with Aristotle. Nevertheless, he never wavers in his con- viction that logic includes formal epistemology at least as a part. In 1957, near the end of his career, he seems to revisit his view of logic as including formal epistemology when he writes: “Logic is concerned only with what is deducible from what . .” (Murphey, 319). Boole’s Thesis: Logic is Mathematical Perhaps the first Boolean Revolution was announced in his 1847 book The Mathematical Analysis of Logic (Cambridge: Macmillan). It was more boldly reit- erated on the last page of his 1848 article “The Calculus of Logic” (Cam- bridge and Dublin Mathematical Journal 3:183–198): The view which these enquiries present of the nature of language . exhibit it not as a mere collection of signs, but as a system of expression, the elements of which are subject to the laws of the thought which they represent. That those laws are as rigorously mathematical as are the laws which govern the purely quantitative conceptions of space and time, of number and magnitude, is a conclusion which I do not hesitate to submit to the exactest scrutiny. With even more confidence he returned to this theme on page 12 of his 1854 masterpiece Laws of Thought: “it is certain that [logic’s] ultimate forms and processes are mathematical”. He again emphasizes his thesis in the last 3 paragraph of the book. Perhaps Boole’s most revolutionary achievement was to persuade the world’s logicians that logical reality is mathematical, or at least that logic should be pursued mathematically. Lewis was one of the first philosophically trained logicians to be fully persuaded of what may be called in retrospect “Boole’s Thesis”: logic is mathematical. This view is a kind of converse of the equally revolutionary “Logistic Thesis” in the form “mathematics is logical”, also accepted by Lewis (Murphey, Ch. 1). Despite the fact that both theses tended to attract superficial or scientistic thinkers who, for example, denigrated the more humanistic or value-oriented side of philosophy, Lewis never lost touch with his deep concern with the human condition, nor was he ever tempted to exag- TRANSACTIONS gerate the importance of logic at the cost of other fields of philosophy (Mur- phey, Chs.
Recommended publications
  • Publications of John Corcoran OCT 04
    OCTOBER 2004 PUBLICATIONS OF JOHN CORCORAN I. Articles. MR indicates review in Mathematical Reviews. J indicates available at JSTOR. G indicates available at Google by entering John Corcoran plus the complete title. 1.J Three Logical Theories, Philosophy of Science 36 (1969) 153-77. 2. Logical Consequence in Modal Logic: Natural Deduction in S5 (co-author G. Weaver), Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 10 (1969) 370-84. 3. Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning I: Mathematical Reasoning and the Stratification of Language, Journal of Structural Learning 3 (1971) #1, 55-74. 4. Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning II: The Nature of a Correct Theory of Proof and Its Value, Journal of Structural Learning 3 (1971) #2, 1-16. 5. Discourse Grammars and the Structure of Mathematical Reasoning III: Two Theories of Proof, Journal of Structural Learning 3 (1971) #3, 1-24. 6. Notes on a Semantic Analysis of Variable Binding Term Operators (co-author John Herring), Logique et Analyse 55 (1971) 646-57. MR46#6989. 7. Variable Binding Term Operators, (co-authors Wm. Hatcher, John Herring) Zeitschrift fu"r mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 18 (1972) 177-82. MR46#5098. 8.J Conceptual Structure of Classical Logic, Philosophy & Phenomenological Research 33 (1972) 25-47. 9. Logical Consequence in Modal Logic: Some Semantic Systems for S4 (co-author G. Weaver), Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 15 (1974) 370-78. MR50#4253. 10, 11, and 12. Revisions of 3, 4 and 5 in Structural Learning II Issues and Approaches, ed. J. Scandura, Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, New York (1976).
    [Show full text]
  • Sentence, Proposition, Judgment, Statement, and Fact: Speaking About the Written English Used in Logic John Corcoran
    Sentence, Proposition, Judgment, Statement, and Fact: Speaking about the Written English Used in Logic John Corcoran Dedication: for Professor Newton da Costa, friend, collaborator, co-discoverer of the Truth-set Principle, and co-creator of the Classical Logic of Variable-binding Term Operators-on his eightieth birthday. abstract. The five ambiguous words|sentence, proposition, judg- ment, statement, and fact|each have meanings that are vague in the sense of admitting borderline cases. This paper discusses sev- eral senses of these and related words used in logic. It focuses on a constellation of recommended primary senses. A judgment is a pri- vate epistemic act that results in a new belief; a statement is a public pragmatic event involving an utterance. Each is executed by a unique person at a unique time and place. Propositions and sentences are timeless and placeless abstractions. A proposition is an intensional entity; it is a meaning composed of concepts. A sentence is a linguistic entity. A written sentence is a string of characters. A sentence can be used by a person to express meanings, but no sentence is intrinsically meaningful. Only propositions are properly said to be true or to be false|in virtue of facts, which are subsystems of the universe. The fact that two is even is timeless; the fact that Socrates was murdered is semi-eternal; the most general facts of physics|in virtue of which propositions of physics are true or false|are eternal. As suggested by the title, this paper is meant to be read aloud. 1 Introduction The words|sentence, proposition, judgment, statement, and fact|are am- biguous in that logicians use each of them with multiple normal meanings.
    [Show full text]
  • Winter 2011 Department of Philosophy
    Department of Philosophy Noûsletter Number 19 - Winter 2011 No. 19 · Fall 2011 noûsletter Page 2 Table of Contents IGERT Fellowship Work .................................................... 21 Letter from the Chair .............................................................. 3 Perry Awards for Best Dissertation ............................. 21 Letter from the Director of Graduate Studies ............ 5 2011 Steinberg Essay Prize Winners .......................... 22 In Remembrance ............................................................................ 6 2011 Whitman Scholarship Winner ............................ 22 Peter Hewitt Hare (1935-2008) ....................................... 6 People Who Made It Possible ............................................... 22 Kenneth Barber (1940-2008) ............................................ 7 The Peter Hare Award ........................................................ 22 Kenneth K. Inada (1924-2011) ......................................... 7 The Hourani Lectures ......................................................... 23 Faculty Updates .............................................................................. 8 The Steinberg Award........................................................... 25 Introducing David Braun ...................................................... 8 The Romanell Award ........................................................... 25 Introducing Richard Cohen ................................................. 8 The Perry Award ..................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 12, Number 5 May 2018
    Volume 12, Number 5 May 2018 thereasoner.org ISSN 1757-0522 matics and I realized that I had met his name some years earlier Contents when I had borrowed from the University Library of Patras his edition of George Boole’s “Laws of Thought”. Guest Editorial 37 Athanasios Christacopoulos Features 37 Hellenic Open University News 39 What’s Hot in . 41 Features Events 43 Courses and Programmes 43 Interview with John Corcoran Jobs and Studentships 44 Athanasios Christacopoulos: First of all I must say that it is an honour to have an interview with one of the leading personali- ties in logic. I would like to begin our conversation with your first scientific interests: those that shaped your way to research on logic –mathematical, historical, and philosophical– till the Guest Editorial moment you said to yourself “I have something new to say”. John Corcoran is an eminent John Corcoran: This sort of question would get different logician, philosopher, math- answers, all tentative, at different times. Today, I think back ematician, linguist, and his- to the late 1960s. My first published paper “Three logical the- torian of logic. He has ories”, offers rationales for logical-system properties such as been member of the IBM Re- weak completeness, strong completeness, deductive complete- search Center’s Linguistics ness, various forms of compactness, consistency, and sound- Group and teacher of logic ness, and the like. at the Universities of Cali- I wrote early drafts of what became “Three logical theories” fornia, Pennsylvania, Michi- for my graduate logic courses. One goal was to take the alien- gan, and Buffalo.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic in the 21St Century: Advice for Young Logicians
    Felsefe Arkivi Archives of Philosophy Felsefe Arkivi - Archives of Philosophy, Sayı/Issue: 51, 2019 DOI: 10.26650/arcp2019-5122 Deneme / Essay Logic in The 21st Century: Advice For Young Logicians John Corcoran1 ABSTRACT By logic I mean the subject Aristotle started in Prior Analytics. Logic studies demonstration and everything necessary for demonstration, and also many things that come to mind in the course of such studies—including axiomatic method as described in my short “Axiomatic method”. By young I mean less than about 40 years old. By logicians I mean people who have dedicated their lives to 1Prof. Dr., University of Buffalo, SUNY, Department of Philosophy, Buffalo, New advancing and criticizing logic: to discovering and establishing new additions and York, USA also to clarifying and correcting what has or had been accepted. More specifically, my advice is for people who have already embarked on their careers: from fresh ORCID: J.C. 0000-0001-7481-2894 PhDs, instructors, and assistant professors to young professors looking forward to reaping the fruits of their long years of study and research. My advice is for people Sorumlu yazar/Corresponding author: who have mastered logic and who want to improve their mastery. I would write John Corcoran, University of Buffalo, SUNY, Department of something very different for students, something along the lines of my “Logic Philosophy, Buffalo, New York, USA teaching in the 21st century”. E-mail/E-posta: [email protected] Some of the things I recommend you have already done. Please do not think that my recommending something suggests that I think you have not already done it.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of Ancient Logic in the Hellenistic Period
    Bibliography of Ancient Logic in the Hellenistic Period https://www.historyoflogic.com/biblio/logic-ancient-biblio-one.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Bibliography of Ancient Logic in the Hellenistic Period SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY ON HELLENISTIC LOGIC 1. Alessandrelli, Michele, and Nasti de Vincentis, Mauro, eds. 2009. La Logica Nel Pensiero Antico. Napoli: Bibliopolis. Atti del Colloquio, Roma, 28-29 novembre 2000. Indice: Mauro Nasti de Vincentis: Premessa 9; Francesco Ademollo: Un'interpretazione del Cratilo di Platone 15; Fabio Acerbi: Osservazioni sulle origini aritmetiche della teoria aristotelica del sillogismo 75; Luca Castagnoli: Sunártesis crisippea e tesi di Aristotele 105; Mauro Nasti de Vincentis: Dalla tesi di Aristotele alla tesi di Boezio: una tesi per l'implicazione crisippea? 165; Anna Maria Schiaparelli: La fallacia della composizione e della divisione in Aristotele e in Galeno 249; Indice delle fonti 281; Indice dei nomi antichi 291; Indice degli autori moderni 293-295. 2. Algra, Keimpe, Barnes, Jonathan, Mansfeld, Jaap, and Schofield, Malcolm, eds. 1999. The Cambridge History of Hellenistic Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Part II. Logic and language. Chapter 4: Introduction by Jonathan Barnes 65; Chapter 5: Logic by Jonathan Barnes, Susanne Bobzien and Mario Mignucci; 5.I The Peripatetics 77; 5.II The 'Megarics' 83; 5.II The Stoics; Chapter 6: Language by Dirk M. Schenkeveld; 6.I Linguistics 177; 6.II Rhetoric 216; 6.III Poetics 221-225. 3. Allen, James. 2001. Inference from Signs. Ancient Debates About the Nature of Evidence. New York: Oxford University Press. 4. Baldassarri, Mariano. 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • [email protected] 052815 JUNE 2015 a BIBLIOGRAPHY
    [email protected] 052815 JUNE 2015 A BIBLIOGRAPHY: JOHN CORCORAN’S PUBLICATIONS ON ARISTOTLE 1972–2015 By John Corcoran Indeed, one of the great strides forward in the modern study of Aristotle’s syllogistic was the realization that it is a system of natural deduction. —Kevin Flannery, SJ [2001, 219]. Corcoran […] has convincingly shown that the best formalization of Aristotle’s reductio ad impossibile is by means of a natural deduction system. —Mario Mignucci [1991, 12]. The most radical opponent of Lukasiewicz is J. Corcoran. —Tadeusz Kwiatkowski [1980, 188]. Contents Abstract I. Articles II. Abstracts III. Books IV. Reviews V. Discussions VI. Alternatives VII. Acknowledgements Abstract This presentation includes a complete bibliography of John Corcoran’s publications relevant to his research on Aristotle’s logic. Sections I, II, III, and IV list 21 articles, 44 abstracts, 3 books, and 11 reviews. It starts with two watershed articles published in 1972: the Philosophy & Phenomenological Research article from Corcoran’s Philadelphia period that antedates his Aristotle studies and the Journal of Symbolic Logic article from his Buffalo period first reporting his original results; it ends with works published in 2015. A few of the items are annotated as listed or with endnotes connecting them with other work and pointing out passages that in- retrospect are seen to be misleading and in a few places erroneous. In addition, Section V, “Discussions”, is a nearly complete secondary bibliography of works describing, interpreting, extending, improving, supporting, and criticizing Corcoran’s work: 8 items published in the 1970s, 23 in the 1980s, 42 in the 1990s, 56 in the 2000s, and 69 in the current decade.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Demonstrative Logic
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 30 (February 2009), 1–20 Aristotle’s Demonstrative Logic JOHN CORCORAN Department of Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA Received 17 December 2007 Revised 29 April 2008 Demonstrative logic, the study of demonstration as opposed to persuasion, is the subject of Aristotle’s two- volume Analytics. Many examples are geometrical. Demonstration produces knowledge (of the truth of propositions). Persuasion merely produces opinion. Aristotle presented a general truth-and-consequence conception of demonstration meant to apply to all demonstrations. According to him, a demonstration, which normally proves a conclusion not previously known to be true, is an extended argumentation beginning with premises known to be truths and containing a chain of reasoning showing by deductively evident steps that its conclusion is a consequence of its premises. In particular, a demonstration is a deduction whose premises are known to be true. Aristotle’s general theory of demonstration required a prior general theory of deduction presented in the Prior Analytics. His general immediate-deduction- chaining conception of deduction was meant to apply to all deductions. According to him, any deduction that is not immediately evident is an extended argumentation that involves a chaining of intermediate immediately evident steps that shows its final conclusion to follow logically from its premises. To illustrate his general theory of deduction, he presented an ingeniously simple and mathematically precise special case traditionally known as the categorical syllogistic. Introduction This expository paper on Aristotle’s demonstrative logic is intended for a broad audience that includes non-specialists. Demonstrative logic is the study of demonstration as opposed to persuasion.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Logic: General Survey and Introductory Readings
    Aristotle's Logic: General Survey and Introductory Readings https://www.historyoflogic.com/logic-aristotle.htm History of Logic from Aristotle to Gödel by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] Aristotle's Logic: General Survey and Introductory Readings A SUMMARY OF ARISTOTLE' SYLLOGISTIC "We have identified five aspects of Aristotle’s syllogistic to highlight the remarkable modernity of his logical investigations: 1) Aristotle took logic to be a formal part of epistemology. A logic is an instrument for establishing knowledge of logical consequence; this is a principal concern of the science of logic. 2) Prior Analytics is a metalogical treatise on the syllogistic deduction system. Aristotle exhaustively treated all possible combinations of elemental “syllogistic” argument patterns to determine which have only valid argument instances. 3) Aristotle recognised the epistemic efficacy of certain elemental argument patterns having only valid instances, and he explicitly formulated them as rules of natural deduction in corresponding sentences. 4) Prior Analytics is a proof-theoretic treatise in which Aristotle described a natural deduction system and demonstrated certain of the logical relationships among syllogistic rules. In fact, Aristotle modelled his syllogistic in a rudimentary way for this purpose. One important metasystematic result is to have established the independence of a set of deduction rules. Finally, 5) Aristotle worked with a notion of substitution sufficient for distinguishing logical syntax and semantics. In this connection he also distinguished validity from deducibility sufficiently well to note the completeness of his logic. Our reading of Prior Analytics takes Aristotle to have treated the process of deduction much as modern mathematical logicians do and not to have been confused about some fundamental matters of logic.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 JOHN CORCORAN, Aristotle's Underlying Logics
    JOHN CORCORAN, Aristotle’s Underlying Logics: A Three-hour Tutorial. Philosophy, University at Buffalo, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150 E-mail: [email protected] This tutorial on Aristotle’s underlying logics begins with a treatment of his demonstrative logic, the principal motivation for his interest in the field. It ends with a faithful translation of Aristotle’s categorical syllogistic into a Hilbert-style many-sorted logic. Demonstrative logic, or apodictics, studies demonstration as opposed to persuasion. It presupposes the Socratic knowledge/opinion distinction—between knowledge (beliefs that are known) and opinion (those that are not known). Every demonstration produces (or confirms) knowledge of (the truth of) its conclusion for every person who comprehends the demonstration. Persuasion merely produces opinion. Aristotle was the first to see that every demonstrative science presupposes for its deductions what Church called an underlying logic. Aristotle presented a general truth-and-consequence conception of demonstration meant to apply to all demonstrations not just to those that are complete categorical syllogisms. According to him, a demonstration is an extended argumentation that begins with premises known to be truths and involves a chain of reasoning showing by deductively evident steps that its conclusion is a consequence of its premises. For Aristotle, starting with premises known to be true and a conclusion not known to be true, the knower demonstrates the conclusion by deducing it from the premises. As Tarski emphasized, modern formal proof resulted from refinement and “formalization” of traditional Aristotelian demonstration. Aristotle’s general theory of demonstration required a prior general theory of deduction presented in the Prior Analytics.
    [Show full text]
  • THE STORY of PRAGMATISM* Hilary PUTNAM
    THE STORY OF PRAGMATISM* Hilary PUTNAM Abstract This paper examines the first of William James’ Lowell lectures, the lectures that became his famous book Pragmatism; A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, and particularly the way in which that lecture connects the idea of philosophy as a way of life with the important role of temperament in forming philosophical systems. The way in which Dewey left Idealism to become James’ successor as the leader of the pragmatist movement is then recounted, and the way in which Dewey was already a philosopher of education in his idealist period is emphasized. The essay closes by ex- plaining how neither James nor Dewey were «Rortian relativists», and by emphasizing James’ realism. Key words: James, Dewey, philosophy as a way of life, role of temperament, failings of rationalism. Dewey as James’ successor, Dewey as philosopher of education, realism, idealism, relativism. In Boston, in November and December of 1906, William James delivered the Low- ell Lectures which were published the following year under the title, Pragmatism: a New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. The opening Lowell lecture bears the dry title, «The present dilemma in philosophy». But that lecture is anything but dry; con- sidered on its literary merits alone, it must surely be one of the finest examples of philosophical prose written in this country. And its contents are certainly provocative. Yet it has received remarkably little discussion; even James’s most hostile critics, who might expect to be infuriated by it, generally pass over it in silence. I shall speculate about why this is the case.
    [Show full text]
  • Wholistic Reference, Truth-Values, Universe of Discourse
    CDD: 149.94 WHOLISTIC REFERENCE, TRUTH-VALUES, UNIVERSES OF DISCOURSE, AND FORMAL ONTOLOGY: TRÉPLICA TO OSWALDO CHATEAUBRIAND JOHN CORCORAN Philosophy Department, University of Buffalo, BUFFALO, NY 14260-4150 USA [email protected] Abstract: In its strongest unqualified form, the principle of wholistic reference is that in any given discourse, each proposition refers to the whole universe of that discourse, regardless of how limited the referents of its non-logical or content terms. According to this principle every proposition of number theory, even an equation such as “5 + 7 = 12”, refers not only to the individual numbers that it happens to mention but to the whole universe of numbers. This principle, its history, and its relevance to some of Oswaldo Chateaubriand’s work are discussed in my 2004 paper “The Principle of Wholistic Reference” in Essays on Chateaubriand’s “Logical Forms”. In Chateaubriand’s réplica (reply), which is printed with my paper, he raised several important additional issues including the three I focus on in this tréplica (reply to his reply): truth- values, universes of discourse, and formal ontology. This paper is self- contained: it is not necessary to have read the above-mentioned works. Key-words: Boole. Chateaubriand. Church. Frege. Gödel. Tarski. Who- listic. Refers. Denotes. Sentence. Proposition. Truth-value. Universe of discourse. Ontology. Epistemology. The principle of wholistic reference (PWR) was first put forth by George Boole in 1847 when he espoused a monistic fixed-universe viewpoint similar to the one Frege and Russell espoused throughout their careers. Later, Boole elaborated PWR in 1854 from the pluralistic multiple-universes perspective.
    [Show full text]