The Frame Problem --- a GENERAL STATEMENT of the FRAME PROBLEM

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Frame Problem --- a GENERAL STATEMENT of the FRAME PROBLEM The Frame Problem --- A GENERAL STATEMENT OF THE FRAME PROBLEM --- The frame problem is the problem of representing change in a complex world where the rules (dynamics of the environment, “laws of nature”) of the world make it so that actions have many unintended as well as intended consequences. ---EXAMPLE: THE YALE SHOOTING PROBLEM--- --- BACKGROUND: AI problem solving and planning --- A problem solver has an internal model the model can represent states of the world operations on the model correspond to actions and and actions take the world to new states --- BACKGROUND: AI problem solving and planning --- Actions can be tried out "in thought experiments" before trying them out in the real world (search in a problem space) --- BACKGROUND: AI problem solving and planning --- Intelligent systems characterized by two components: Knowledge base (KB) - Rich internal representation Heuristics - Smart heuristics, not brute-force exhaustive search --- BACKGROUND: AI problem solving and planning --- Consequently, two ways of being smart: Janlert (TRD p.3) "It is tempting to speculate on a general trade-off between modeling and heuristics. Some problem solvers may rely on having a very rich and accurate model of the world, and then they don't have to be very clever, because all they have to do is consult the model for answers. But some problem solvers may rely on their cleverness - what they don't know they can always figure outv-vand so manage without much explicit knowledge of the world." --- BACKGROUND: AI problem solving and planning --- You can have a very big model with explicit (relevant consequences) in which case the heuristics need not be very smart - combinatorial explosion and need to address novelty means you could need too much explicit knowledge - expert systems do not generalize across domains? Or you can have a very smart heuristic component and a compact world model - you need to be able to assess only the relevant consequences without needing to assess the relevance of the consequence - need to address novelty and the holistic nature of relevance could mean you can't "tag" the relevance of a consequence in a context insensitive manner --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (I) The original frame problem (II) The persistence problem (III) The ramifications and qualifications problem (IV) The metaphysical problem --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (I) The original frame problem Doing away with frame axioms. Representing the effect of actions in situation calculus, you represent the world at a time as a situation, a set of sentences (axioms) in predicate logic. Then an action's effects will be represented by updating the situation, by deriving the logical consequences. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- An example of a frame axiom: (x) (s) (Block(x)[s] --> Block(x)[GRASP[s]]). In words: If x is a block in situation s, then x will still be a block if you grasp it, in the situation that is the result of the Grasp-action having been applied to x in situation s. You don't want to specify IF F is true in s and E occurs in s, THEN F is true in s+1 for each F, s and E separately. How do you represent non-change as a rule (and change as the exception) compactly, without the need for frame axioms? --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- Logically, anything could happen as I turn the light switch (think of living in a Douglas Adams world). I can represent it happening. That it doesn't happen in this world has to be known. That means it has to be in the axioms of the KB. In original situation calculus, all effects AND NON- EFFECTS of actions need to be represented individually, as separate axioms concerning the world. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (x)(y)(c)(s) (True_in(s, Color(x,c)) --> True_in(result(s,go(x,y)), Color(x,c)))) Where x is an object, y is a location, c is a color and s is a situation. You will need a lot of frame axioms. Too many. Most axioms describing the (meta)physics of the world (how actions affect situations) will be frame axioms like this - stating non-changes. Since most actions don't change most things. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- Turning on the light will cause the bulb to illuminate. Turning on the light does not cause measles. Turning on the light does not cure measles...and it should not even occur to you that it might (i.e. you should not spend cognitive resources assessing the possibility) They seem unnecessary or wasteful to list, to human intuition; if you could instead state generally that, by and large, things don't change, you could save a lot of code. The facts about measles belong to the background of facts that need not be explicitly considered (by a human), since common sense assumes them to remain unaffected. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- The original problem, then, is how to represent default non-change economically. "[W]hether you can infer that something is still true given what you know has happened since it became true.". – McDermott, TDD p.116 This would appear to be a "technical problem." Result of an unfortunate feature of representing change in situation calculus. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- Technical problems admit technical solutions. (If you define your frame problem broadly, the "philosophers' frame problem" or "the epistemological frame problem", then this is a more restriced problem (but perhaps still a symptom of the larger one!)). --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (II) The persistence problem (representing common sense law of inertia) A somewhat more general frame problem is representing the common sense law of inertia - most actions don't change most things - not just in situation calculus, but logicist AI generally, succinctly. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- The classical example: Painting does not change location and moving does not affect color: the original solution was to define these frames of reference for each action (hence the name), motion and color are outside each others' frames. Grasping, pushing, pulling etc. only affect properties in the motion frame but not the color frame. The background forms a static frame of reference for each action against which their likely consequences stand out. If you could define the frames, then everything else, all predicates outside the frame, would not need to be considered as candidates for updating (and, incidentally, you could learn new ones without the need to update all actions). --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- The sleeping dogs strategy is to consider stasis the default case, that is only assumed to be violated if there is sufficient cause. What you want is: IF F is true is s and E occurs in s AND E is irrelevant with respect to the truth of F, generally or in s, THEN F is true in s+1 and thereafter, UNLESS you can prove from the axioms it doesn't. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- "For unclear reasons, [philosophers] have seen a special obstacle to the sleeping dogs idea.“ - Drew McDermott, TRD .116 "Letting sleeping dogs lie", you will assume that things do not change unless you can show them to change (explicitly mentioned in the action, or derivable as a consequence from KB). The problem then becomes defining this common sense law of inertia precisely. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (III) The ramifications and qualifications problem (handling side effects and preconditions in causal reasoning) "The frame problem arises in keeping temporary knowledge up to date, when there are side effects; more specifically, it concerns how a system can ignore most conceivable updating questions and confront only 'realistic' possibilities.“ - John Haugeland TRD pp.82-83 --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- When an action is performed, many beliefs need to be updated because actions can have long-run consequences (ramifications). When an action is performed, what intended and unintended effects it has, depends on situational context (qualifications) --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- An action will cause a change ceteris paribus (if background conditions hold), and will also change other things. This is to do with holism of the world represented: can we frame the relevant background conditions a priori or do we need to consult all our knowledge to predict the consequeces of any action? --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- The Qualifications and Ramifications problem - cheap test solution: find representation and heuristic that allows you to check many potential updates quickly - sleeping dogs solution: assume things need not be updated unless there is an explicit reason to do so --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- The original problem was, that for each action you needed to separately specify its effects and non- effects. Now, this would not be a problem if the effects actually outweighed, or were even comparable, to non- effects. If the metaphysics of world were such that when you took an action it had all sorts of repercussions all over. Then this would be the only sensible thing to do. But in fact the world is such that when you take an action, most things aren't affected at all, and the problem is to be able to take advantage of this. To be able to say "let sleeping dogs lie", precisely rather than metaphorically. --- THE ORIGINAL FRAME PROBLEM AND SOME GENERALIZATIONS --- (IV) The metaphysical problem Janlert: TRD p.7-8 "[T]he problem of finding a representational form permitting a changing, complex world to be efficiently and adequately represented." Dennett: TRD p.42 "I think [...] that it is a new, deep epistemological problem .
Recommended publications
  • The Dramatic True Story of the Frame Default
    The Dramatic True Story of the Frame Default Vladimir Lifschitz University of Texas at Austin Abstract This is an expository article about the solution to the frame problem pro- posed in 1980 by Raymond Reiter. For years, his “frame default” remained untested and suspect. But developments in some seemingly unrelated areas of computer science—logic programming and satisfiability solvers—eventually exonerated the frame default and turned it into a basis for important appli- cations. 1 Introduction This is an expository article about the dramatic story of the solution to the frame problem proposed in 1980 by Raymond Reiter [22]. For years, his “frame default” remained untested and suspect. But developments in some seemingly unrelated ar- eas of computer science—logic programming and satisfiability solvers—eventually exonerated the frame default and turned it into a basis for important applications. This paper grew out of the Great Moments in KR talk given at the 13th Inter- national Conference on Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning. It does not attempt to provide a comprehensive history of research on the frame problem: the story of the frame default is only a small part of the big picture, and many deep and valuable ideas are not even mentioned here. The reader can learn more about work on the frame problem from the monographs [17, 21, 24, 25, 27]. 2 What Is the Frame Problem? The frame problem [16] is the problem of describing a dynamic domain without explicitly specifying which conditions are not affected by executing actions. Here is a simple example. Initially, Alice is in the room, and Bob is not.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Dreyfus' Frame Problem Argument Cannot Justify Anti
    Why Dreyfus’ Frame Problem Argument Cannot Justify Anti- Representational AI Nancy Salay ([email protected]) Department of Philosophy, Watson Hall 309 Queen‘s University, Kingston, ON K7L 3N6 Abstract disembodied cognitive models will not work, and this Hubert Dreyfus has argued recently that the frame problem, conclusion needs to be heard. By disentangling the ideas of discussion of which has fallen out of favour in the AI embodiment and representation, at least with respect to community, is still a deal breaker for the majority of AI Dreyfus‘ frame problem argument, the real locus of the projects, despite the fact that the logical version of it has been general polemic between traditional computational- solved. (Shanahan 1997, Thielscher 1998). Dreyfus thinks representational cognitive science and the more recent that the frame problem will disappear only once we abandon the Cartesian foundations from which it stems and adopt, embodied approaches is revealed. From this, I hope that instead, a thoroughly Heideggerian model of cognition, in productive debate will ensue. particular one that does not appeal to representations. I argue The paper proceeds in the following way: in section I, I that Dreyfus is too hasty in his condemnation of all describe and distinguish the logical version of the frame representational views; the argument he provides licenses problem and the philosophical one that remains unsolved; in only a rejection of disembodied models of cognition. In casting his net too broadly, Dreyfus circumscribes the section II, I rehearse Dreyfus‘ negative argument, what I‘ll cognitive playing field so closely that one is left wondering be calling his frame problem argument; in section III, I how his Heideggerian alternative could ever provide a highlight some key points from Dreyfus‘ positive account of foundation explanatorily robust enough for a theory of a Heideggerian alternative; in section IV, I make my case cognition.
    [Show full text]
  • Answers to Exercises
    Appendix A Answers to Exercises Answers to some of the exercises can be verified by running CLINGO, and they are not included here. 2.1. (c) Replace rule (1.1) by large(C) :- size(C,S), S > 500. 2.2. (a) X is a child of Y if Y is a parent of X. 2.3. (a) large(germany) :- size(germany,83), size(uk,64), 83 > 64. (b) child(dan,bob) :- parent(bob,dan). 2.4. (b), (c), and (d). 2.5. parent(ann,bob; bob,carol; bob,dan). 2.8. p(0,0*0+0+41) :- 0 = 0..3. 2.10. p(2**N,2**(N+1)) :- N = 0..3. 2.11. (a) p(N,(-1)**N) :- N = 0..4. (b) p(M,N) :- M = 1..4, N = 1..4, M >= N. 2.12. (a) grandparent(X,Z) :- parent(X,Y), parent(Y,Z). 2.13. (a) sibling(X,Y) :- parent(Z,X), parent(Z,Y), X != Y. 2.14. enrolled(S) :- enrolled(S,C). 2.15. same_city(X,Y) :- lives_in(X,C), lives_in(Y,C), X!=Y. 2.16. older(X,Y) :- age(X,M), age(Y,N), M > N. 2.18. Line 5: noncoprime(N) :- N = 1..n, I = 2..N, N\I = 0, k\I = 0. Line 10: coprime(N) :- N = 1..n, not noncoprime(N). © Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019 149 V. Lifschitz, Answer Set Programming, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-24658-7 150 A Answers to Exercises 2.19. Line 6: three(N) :- N = 1..n, I = 0..n, J = 0..n, K = 0..n, N=I**2+J**2+K**2.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporal Projection and Explanation
    Temporal Projection and Explanation Andrew B. Baker and Matthew L. Ginsberg Computer Science Department Stanford University Stanford, California 94305 Abstract given is in fact somewhat simpler than that presented in [Hanks and McDermott, 1987], but still retains all of the We propose a solution to problems involving troublesome features of the original. In Section 3, we go temporal projection and explanation (e.g., the on to describe proposed solutions, and investigate their Yale shooting problem) based on the idea that technical shortcomings. whether a situation is abnormal should not de• The formal underpinnings of our own ideas are pre• pend upon historical information about how sented in Section 4, and we return to the Yale shooting the situation arose. We apply these ideas both scenario in Section 5, showing that our notions can be to the Yale shooting scenario and to a blocks used to solve both the original problem and the variant world domain that needs to address the quali• presented in Section 2. In Section 6, we extend our ideas fication problem. to deal with the qualification problem in a simple blocks world scenario. Concluding remarks are contained in 1 Introduction Section 7. The paper [1987] by Hanks and McDermott describing 2 The Yale shooting the Yale shooting problem has generated such a flurry of responses that it is difficult to imagine what another The Yale shooting problem involves reasoning about a one can contribute. The points raised by Hanks and sequence of actions. In order to keep our notation as McDermott, both formal and philosophical, have been manageable as possible, we will denote the fact that some discussed at substantial length elsewhere.
    [Show full text]
  • The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem
    The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem Using Theorem Proving to Generate Plans Literature z Malik Ghallab, Dana Nau, and Paolo Traverso. Automated Planning – Theory and Practice, section 12.2. Elsevier/Morgan Kaufmann, 2004. z Murray Shanahan. Solving the Frame Problem, chapter 1. The MIT Press, 1997. z Chin-Liang Chang and Richard Char-Tung Lee. Symbolic Logic and Mechanical Theorem Proving, chapters 2 and 3. Academic Press, 1973. The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 2 1 Classical Planning z restricted state-transition system Σ=(S,A,γ) z planning problem P=(Σ,si,Sg) z Why study classical planning? • good for illustration purposes • algorithms that scale up reasonably well are known • extensions to more realistic models known z What are the main issues? • how to represent states and actions • how to perform the solution search The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 3 Planning as Theorem Proving z idea: • represent states and actions in first-order predicate logic • prove that there is a state s • that is reachable from the initial state and • in which the goal is satisfied. • extract plan from proof The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 4 2 Overview Propositional Logic z First-Order Predicate Logic z Representing Actions z The Frame Problem z Solving the Frame Problem The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 5 Propositions z proposition: a declarative sentence (or statement) that can either true or false z examples: • the robot is at location1 • the crane is holding a container z atomic propositions (atoms): • have no internal structure • notation: capital letters, e.g.
    [Show full text]
  • The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem the Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem •Using Theorem Proving to Generate P
    The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem Using Theorem Proving to Generate Plans The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem •Using Theorem Proving to Generate Plans 1 Literature z Malik Ghallab, Dana Nau, and Paolo Traverso. Automated Planning – Theory and Practice, section 12.2. Elsevier/Morgan Kaufmann, 2004. z Murray Shanahan. Solving the Frame Problem, chapter 1. The MIT Press, 1997. z Chin-Liang Chang and Richard Char-Tung Lee. Symbolic Logic and Mechanical Theorem Proving, chapters 2 and 3. Academic Press, 1973. The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 2 Literature •Malik Ghallab, Dana Nau, and Paolo Traverso. Automated Planning – Theory and Practice, section 12.2. Elsevier/Morgan Kaufmann, 2004. •Murray Shanahan. Solving the Frame Problem, chapter 1. The MIT Press, 1997. •Chin-Liang Chang and Richard Char-Tung Lee. Symbolic Logic and Mechanical Theorem Proving, chapters 2 and 3. Academic Press, 1973. •for propositional and first-order logic 2 Classical Planning z restricted state-transition system Σ=(S,A,γ) z planning problem P=(Σ,si,Sg) z Why study classical planning? • good for illustration purposes • algorithms that scale up reasonably well are known • extensions to more realistic models known z What are the main issues? • how to represent states and actions • how to perform the solution search The Situation Calculus and the Frame Problem 3 Classical Planning •restricted state-transition system Σ=(S,A,γ) •finite, fully observable, deterministic, and static with restricted goals and implicit time •planning problem P=(Σ,si,Sg)
    [Show full text]
  • CS 343 Artificial Intelligence
    CS 343 Artificial Intelligence Gordon S. Novak Jr. Department of Computer Sciences University of Texas at Austin Austin, Texas 78712 (512) 471-9569 [email protected] http://www.cs.utexas.edu/users/novak Copyright c Gordon S. Novak Jr. 1 Artificial Intelligence as Science Intelligence should be placed in the context of biology: Intelligence connects perception to action to help an organism survive. Intelligence is computation in the service of life, just as metabolism is chemistry in the service of life. Intelligence does not imply perfect understanding; every intelligent being has limited perception, memory, and computation. Many points on the spectrum of intelligence-versus-cost are viable, from insects to humans. AI seeks to understand the computations required for intelligent behavior and to produce computer systems that exhibit intelligence. Aspects of intelligence studied by AI include perception, motor control, communication using human languages, reasoning, planning, learning, and memory. 2 Scientific Goals of AI AI seeks to understand the working of the mind in mechanistic terms, just as medicine seeks to understand the working of the body in mechanistic terms. The mind is what the brain does. { Marvin Minsky The strong AI position is that any aspect of human intelligence could, in principle, be mechanized. 3 A.I. as Engineering How can we make computer systems more intelligent? • Perception to get input directly from the real world. • Autonomy to perform tasks that currently require human operators without human intervention or monitoring. • Flexibility in dealing with variability in the environment. • Ease of use: computers that are able to understand what the user wants from limited instructions in natural languages.
    [Show full text]
  • 1988-Why Things Go Wrong: a Formal Theory of Causal Reasoning
    From: AAAI-88 Proceedings. Copyright ©1988, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. Why Things Go Wrong: A Formal Theory of Causal Reasoning Leora Morgenstern and Lynn Andrea Stein Department of Computer Science Brown University Box 1910, Providence, RI 02912 Abstract 19861 [Shoham, 19871, [Kautz, 19861, [Lifschitz, 19861 [Lif- schitz, 19871, [Haugh, 19871). All of these solutions, how- This paper presents a theory of generalized tem- ever, while adequate for the Yale Shooting Problem itself, poral reasoning. We focus on the related prob- handle either forward or backward projection incorrectly, lems of and/or work only within a very limited temporal ontol- 1. Temporal Projection-determining all the ogy. Thus, they cannot serve as the basis for a theory of facts true in a chronicle, given a partial de- generalized temporal reasoning. scription of that chronicle, and In this paper, we present a solution to the problems 2. Explanation-figuring out what went wrong of both forward and backward temporal projection, based if an unexpected outcome occurs. upon the concept that actions happen only if they have to happen. We then show how our model lends itself to a We present a non-monotonic temporal logic based very natural characterization of the concept of an adequate on the notion that actions only happen if they explanation for an unexpected outcome. are motivated. We demonstrate that this the- In the next section, we survey the solutions that have ory handles generalized temporal projection cor- been proposed to the YSP, and explain why they can- rectly, and in particular, solves the Yale Shooting not handle general temporal projection accurately.
    [Show full text]
  • Heuristics, Concepts, and Cognitive Architecture: Toward Understanding How the Mind Works
    Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository 4-20-2011 12:00 AM Heuristics, Concepts, and Cognitive Architecture: Toward Understanding How The Mind Works Sheldon J. Chow The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Dr. Christopher Viger The University of Western Ontario Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree in Doctor of Philosophy © Sheldon J. Chow 2011 Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd Part of the Philosophy of Mind Commons Recommended Citation Chow, Sheldon J., "Heuristics, Concepts, and Cognitive Architecture: Toward Understanding How The Mind Works" (2011). Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository. 128. https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/etd/128 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarship@Western. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Western. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HEURISTICS, CONCEPTS, AND COGNITIVE ARCHITECTURE: TOWARD UNDERSTANDING HOW THE MIND WORKS (Spine title: Heuristics, Concepts, and Cognitive Architecture) (Thesis format: Monograph) by Sheldon Chow Graduate Program in Philosophy A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy The School of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies The University of Western Ontario London, Ontario, Canada c Sheldon Joseph Chow 2011 THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Title of Dissertation: FRAME PROBLEMS
    ABSTRACT Title of dissertation: FRAME PROBLEMS, FODOR‟S CHALLENGE, AND PRACTICAL REASON Erich C. Deise, Doctor of Philosophy, 2008 Dissertation directed by: Professor Peter Carruthers Department of Philosophy By bringing the frame problem to bear on psychology, Fodor argues that the interesting activities of mind are not amenable to computational modeling. Following exegesis of the frame problem and Fodor‟s claims, I argue that underlying Fodor‟s argument is an unsatisfiable normative principle of rationality that in turn commits him to a particular descriptive claim about the nature of our minds. I argue that the descriptive claim is false and that we should reject the normative principle in favor of one that is at least in principle satisfiable. From this it follows, I argue, that we have no reason for thinking the activities of our minds to be, as a matter of principle, unmodelable. Drawing upon Baars‟ Global Workspace theory, I next outline an alternative framework that provides a means by which the set of engineering challenges raised by Fodor might be met. Having sketched this alternative, I turn next to consider some of the frame problems arising in practical reason and decision-making. Following discussion of the nature of emotion and its influence on practical reason and decision- making, I argue that consideration of emotion provides one means by which we might contend with some of the frame problem instances that arise in that domain. FRAME PROBLEMS, FODOR‟S CHALLENGE, AND PRACTICAL REASON By Erich C. Deise Dissertation submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Maryland, College Park, in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy 2008 Advisory Committee: Professor Peter Carruthers, Chair Professor Christopher Cherniak Professor Michael Dougherty Professor Jeff Horty Professor Paul Pietroski © Copyright Erich C.
    [Show full text]
  • 1993-The Frame Problem and Knowledge-Producing Actions
    From: AAAI-93 Proceedings. Copyright © 1993, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. ame Proble Richard B. Scherl* and Hector J. Levesquet Department of Computer Science University of Toronto Toronto, Ontario Canada M5S 3A6 email: [email protected] [email protected] Abstract knowledge-producing actions, that is, actions whose ef- fects are to change a state of knowledge. This paper proposes a solution to the frame prob- A standard example of a knowledge-producing ac- lem for knowledge-producing actions. An example tion is that of reading a number on a piece of pa- of a knowledge-producing action is a sense opera- per. Consider the problem of dialing the combination tion performed by a robot to determine whether of a safe [McCarthy and Hayes, 1969; Moore, 1980; or not there is an object of a particular shape Moore, 19851. If an agent is at the same place as the within its grasp. The work is an extension of safe, and knows the combination of the safe, then he Reiter’s solution to the frame problem for ordi- can open the safe by performing the action of dialing nary actions and Moore’s work on knowledge and that combination. If an agent is at the same place action. The properties of our specification are as both the safe and a piece of paper and he knows that knowledge-producing actions do not affect that the combination of the safe is written on the pa, fluents other than the knowledge fluent, and ac- per, he can open the safe by first reading the piece of tions that are not knowledge-producing only affect paper, and then dialing that combination.
    [Show full text]
  • The Frame Problem, Then and Now
    The Frame Problem, Then and Now Vladimir Lifschitz University of Texas at Austin My collaboration with John McCarthy started in 1984. He was interested then in what he called the commonsense law of inertia. That idea is related to actions, such as moving an object to a different location, or, for instance, toggling a light switch. According to this law, whatever we know about the state of affairs before executing an action can be presumed, by default, to hold after the action as well. Formalizing this default would resolve the difficulty known in AI as the frame problem. Reasoning with defaults is nonmonotonic. John proposed a solution to the frame problem based on the method of nonmonotonic reasoning that he called circumscription [1]. And then something unpleasant happened. Two researchers from Yale University discovered that John's proposed solution was incorrect [2]. Their counterexample involved the actions of loading a gun and shooting, and it became known as the \Yale Shooting Scenario." Twenty years later their paper received the AAAI Classic Paper Award [3]. But that was not all. Automated reasoning is notoriously difficult, and the presence of defaults adds yet another level of complexity. Even assuming that the problem with Yale Shooting is resolved, was there any hope, one could ask, that the commonsense law of inertia would ever become part of usable software? So John's proposal seemed unsound and non-implementable. It also seemed unnecessary, because other researchers have proposed approaches to the frame problem that did not require nonmonotonic reasoning [4, 5, 6]. There were all indications that his project just wouldn't fly.
    [Show full text]