The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism Aporia vol. 25 no. 1 — 2015 The Tangled Beard of Modal Realism KELVIN JENSEN avid Lewis is well known for his theory of modal realism. According to this theory, our world — us, the universe we inhabit, Dand anything that has ever existed therein — is just one among many. In fact, modal realism holds that there are countless worlds more or less similar to our own. There is a world, for instance, identical to ours saving one difference: in lieu of wearing a polo shirt today, I wore a button - down shirt. Other worlds are not so similar; one world, for example, consists of planets populated by unicorns. Another is governed by physical laws that permit humans to walk on water. Indeed, for any logically possible state of affairs, there is a world embodying that state of affairs. Since there are infinite possible states of affairs, there are infinite worlds. To be sure, these worlds are spatio - temporally inaccessible and causally isolated from our world, but they exist as fully as our world does. Why would Lewis preach such a bizarre metaphysical doctrine? One sole reason: usefulness (Plurality 3). Lewis believes that his theory resolves important problems in philosophy, specifically in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science. Of particular renown is the solution to a perennial issue in modality, an issue that can be summarized by the following question: what makes modal properties possible? What, for instance, grounds the property I have of possibly wearing a button - down shirt? Modal realism has a ready answer: I possess the property of possibly wearing a button - down shirt because there is a world like ours in every Kelvin Jensen is a senior majoring in philosophy at Brigham Young University. His primary interests include ethics, philosophy of religion, and political philosophy. After graduating next April, Kelvin plans on attending law school. This essay tied for third place in the 2015 David H. Yarn Philosophcal Essay Contest. 46 KELVIN JENSEN respect except that my counterpart is wearing a button - down shirt. That is, modal properties are grounded in their non - modal realization on Lewisian possible worlds. Whether Lewis’s theory can truly explain modal properties — and provide the other benefits that Lewis touts — has been disputed. However, I shall not argue with Lewis here; for the purposes of this paper, I grant the benefits, all of the benefits, that he ascribes to his theory. I do, however, want to explore an objection that he treats. In his book Counterfactuals, Lewis considers several complaints about modal realism. One qualm relates to Ockham’s Razor and can be explained thus: modal realism flies in the face of ontological parsimony, which demands — at the very least — that one not recklessly postulate the existence of new entities. This prescription is two - pronged: according to quantitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional individual entities; according to qualitative ontological parsimony, one ought not to frivolously postulate additional kinds of entities. Modal realism is thought to run afoul of both senses of parsimony — it not only postulates multiple worlds similar to ours, but also postulates multiple worlds different in kind than ours. Inasmuch as ontological parsimony is an important theoretical virtue, modal realism falls short. Lewis’s response to this objection is threefold: first, he admits that modal realism disrespects quantitative ontological parsimony but claims that this concession is innocuous (87). Quantitative parsimony is irrelevant to a theory’s truth; qualitative parsimony is what matters. Lewis doesn’t argue for this position — he simply takes it for granted. Second, he insists that modal realism in no way violates qualitative parsimony; after all, possible worlds are not different in kind than the actual world. As Lewis observes, “You believe in our actual world already. I ask you to believe in more things of that kind, not in things of some new kind” (87). And finally, he presumes that no Ockham’s Razor objection can be decisive (87). What he means is that violations of ontological parsimony — no matter how flagrant — do not, by themselves, warrant rejecting modal realism. I take issue with Lewis’s response. Quantitative parsimony is a theoretical virtue, and modal realism does disregard qualitative parsimony. That is, Lewis’s theory disrespects both quantitative and qualitative parsimony, both of which are important theoretical considerations. Perhaps a violation of ontological parsimony cannot be decisive, but the violation here is so egregious, even frightful, that we ought to turn our attention to rival theories and remold them to provide the theoretical benefits of modal realism, without the ontological costs. Let’s examine the support for my claims. Lewis is not unique in dismissing quantitative parsimony without a hearing. Many philosophers have presumed that quantitative parsimony THE TANGLED BEARD OF MODAL REALISM 47 is simply irrelevant to the truth of a theory. Why is this assumption so prevalent? According to Alan Baker, many reject quantitative parsimony because it doesn’t appear to connect to “independently recognizable theoretical virtues” (248). For instance, qualitative parsimony can be justified by appeals to epistemic conservatism, which holds, at its core, that we ought not to believe in something unless we have good reason to believe in it (248). Syntactical elegance — the other strand of Ockham’s Razor, a strand which demands simplicity in a theory’s basic principles or axioms — can be justified on pragmatic grounds. A theory that is syntactically elegant is easier to use or manipulate, and is generally more comprehensible (248). From which theoretical virtue can quantitative parsimony be derived? It can’t be derived from epistemic conservatism, for quantitative parsimony doesn’t have to do with the postulation of new kinds of entities or mechanisms. Rather, it postulates additional entities of the kinds in which we already believe. Nor does it seem likely that quantitative parsimony can be derived from pragmatic concerns. Thus, inasmuch as quantitative parsimony can’t be tied to any obvious theoretical virtue, Lewis is right — quantitative parsimony ought to be jettisoned. It may be true that quantitative parsimony isn’t justified by appeals to some recognizable theoretical virtue. But I think it can be justified by appeals to the workings of nature. Nature generally uses the simplest means to achieve her ends, and this fact justifies the prescription to keep down the number of individual entities, even if these entities are not different in kind from those in which we believe. If nature uses the simplest means to accomplish her purposes, quantitatively parsimonious theories are more likely to be true ceteris paribus. An example may prove illustrative: in the early twentieth century, physicists observed a puzzling aspect of beta decay, a type of radioactive decay in which an electron is emitted from a nucleus. Upon emission of the electron, the energy of the nucleus decreased by more energy than could be ascribed to the emitted electron. This result bemused scientists, who had anticipated that the diminution of energy in the nucleus would be equivalent to the energy of the emitted electron. Wolfgang Pauli attempted to resolve the discrepancy by conjecturing the existence of a neutrally charged particle — a “neutrino” — emitted concomi- tantly with the electron. This neutrino, Pauli reasoned, would possess an energy mass equal to the difference between the energy loss of the nucleus and the energy of the emitted electron. Pauli’s theory was accepted, and the existence of his neutrino was empirically confirmed many years later. Two features of this example stand out: the quantity of neutrinos actually emitted from the atom, and the quantity of neutrinos Pauli postulated. Only one neutrino was emitted from the anomalous atom. Had the atom emitted two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy of the original, 48 KELVIN JENSEN nature could have achieved the same results (Nolan 333). Indeed, nature could have achieved the same results with three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy of the original; or four; or four hundred. But nature didn’t employ four hundred neutrinos, each with one four - hundredth of the necessary charge; she selected one neutrino. In this instance, at least, nature really did use the simplest means to accomplish her ends. Interestingly, Pauli decided to postulate only one neutrino. He could have postulated two neutrinos, each possessing half of the energy needed to account for the discrepancy. This postulation would have yielded the same explanatory power as his first theory (Nolan 333). Or he could have postulated three neutrinos, each possessing a third of the energy needed; or four; or four hundred. Yet Pauli proposed just one neutrino. Pauli was apparently guided by considerations of quantitative parsimony, and even if he wasn’t, adherence to quantitative parsimony would have encouraged him to postulate merely one neutrino had he considered the postulation of additional neutrinos. Therefore, it appears that a commitment to quantitative parsimony helps us to select theories more likely to reflect the workings of nature. At this juncture I anticipate two objections: first, although quan- titative parsimony got it right in this scenario, it may not always pick out the correct theory. There may be some instances in which nature doesn’t use the simplest means to achieve her ends. Moreover, even if there are no such instances, it’s not clear that nature will always continue to employ the simplest means. This is a fair objection, and I fear that my response may be somewhat weak. I’m not sure that the workings of nature vindicate the utility of quantitative parsimony in every instance, and I certainly don’t know whether nature will continue to use the simplest instruments to achieve her ends.
Recommended publications
  • Modalism and Theoretical Virtues: Toward an Epistemology of Modality
    This is a repository copy of Modalism and theoretical virtues: Toward an epistemology of modality. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/83720/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Bueno, O and Shalkowski, SA (2015) Modalism and theoretical virtues: Toward an epistemology of modality. Philosophical Studies, 172 (3). pp. 671-689. ISSN 0031-8116 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-014-0327-7 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Modalism and Theoretical Virtues: Toward an Epistemology of Modality1 Otávio Bueno Department of Philosophy University of Miami Coral Gables, FL 33124-4670, USA e-mail: [email protected] Scott A. Shalkowski Department of Philosophy University of Leeds Leeds LS2 9JT, UK e-mail: [email protected] ABSTRACT According to modalism, modality is primitive. In this paper, we examine the implications of this view for modal epistemology, and articulate a modalist account of modal knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Reflections on Modern Quantum Gravity Research
    Stringed along or caught in a loop? Stringed along or caught in a loop? Philosophical reflections on modern quantum gravity research Keizo Matsubara Dissertation presented at Uppsala University to be publicly examined in Geijersalen, Building 6, (Eng 6-1023), English Park Campus, Thunbergsvägen 3P, Uppsala, Friday, January 18, 2013 at 10:15 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. The examination will be conducted in English. Abstract Matsubara, K. 2013. Stringed along or caught in a loop?: Philosophical reflections on modern quantum gravity research. Filosofiska Institutionen. 139 pp. Uppsala. ISBN 978-91-506-2324-6. A number of philosophical questions, all connected to modern research in quantum gravity, are discussed in this dissertation. The goal of research in quantum gravity is to find a quantum theory for gravitation; the ot- her fundamental forces are already understood in terms of quantum physics. Quantum gravity is studied within a number of different research programmes. The most popular are string theory and loop quantum gravity; besides these a number of other approaches are pursued. Due to the lack of empirical support, it is relevant to assess the scientific status of this rese- arch. This is done from four different points of view, namely the ones held by: logical positi- vists, Popper, Kuhn and Lakatos. It is then argued that research in quantum gravity may be considered scientific, conditional on scientists being open with the tentative and speculative nature of their pursuits. Given the lack of empirical progress, in all approaches to quantum gravity, a pluralistic strategy is advised. In string theory there are different theoretical formulations, or dualities, which are physi- cally equivalent.
    [Show full text]
  • Peircean Modal Realism?”
    Nordic NSP Studies in Pragmatism Helsinki | 2010 Sami Pihlstr¨om “Peircean Modal Realism?” In: Bergman, M., Paavola, S., Pietarinen, A.-V., & Rydenfelt, H. (Eds.) (2010). Ideas in Action: Proceedings of the Applying Peirce Conference (pp. 48–61). Nordic Studies in Pragmatism 1. Helsinki: Nordic Pragmatism Network. ISSN-L - ISSN - ISBN ---- Copyright c 2010 The Authors and the Nordic Pragmatism Network. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License. CC BY NC For more information, see http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/./ Nordic Pragmatism Network, NPN Helsinki 2010 www.nordprag.org Peircean Modal Realism? Sami Pihlstr¨om University of Helsinki 1. Introduction: the metaphysically realist assumptions of contem- porary modal realism1 The purpose of this paper is to critically compare Charles Peirce’s meta- physics of the modalities – or a “Peircean” approach to this metaphysical is- sue derived from his defense of scholastic realism – to the modal realist views defended by important twentieth century and contemporary philosophers. In this introductory section, I note that the contemporary discourse on modality is firmly rooted in metaphysical realism. In section 2, I suggest that the Peircean approach is closer to Kantian transcendental metaphysics. The contrast between metaphysical realism – or what Kant called “tran- scendental realism” – and the properly transcendental metaphysics in my view inherited by pragmatism turns out to be important, both generally and in the case of modality. Section 3 examines the possibility of inter- preting Peirce’s scholastic realism (a key doctrine in his modal theory) as 1 In addition to the Applying Peirce conference (Helsinki, June 2007), parts of this material were presented at the conference on Peirce’s normative thought in Opole, Poland (also June 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Historical Parallels Between, and Modal Realism Underlying Einstein and Everett Relativities
    Historical Parallels between, and Modal Realism underlying Einstein and Everett Relativities Sascha Vongehr National Laboratory of Solid-State Microstructures, Nanjing University, Nanjing 210093, P. R. China A century ago, “ past ” and “ future ”, previously strictly apart, mixed up and merged. Temporal terminology improved. Today, not actualized quantum states, that is merely “ possible ” alternatives, objectively “exist ” (are real) when they interfere. Again, two previously strictly immiscible realms mix. Now, modal terminology is insufficient. Both times, extreme reactions reach from rejection of the empirical science to mystic holism. This paper shows how progress started with the relativization of previously absolute terms, first through Einstein’s relativity and now through Everett’s relative state description, which is a modal realism. The historical parallels suggest mere relativization is insufficient. A deformation of domains occurs: The determined past and the dependent future were restricted to smaller regions of space-time. This ‘light cone description’ is superior to hyperspace foliations and already entails the modal realism of quantum mechanics. Moreover, an entirely new region, namely the ‘absolute elsewhere’ was identified. The historical precedent suggests that modal terminology may need a similar extension. Discussing the modal realistic connection underlying both relativities, Popper’s proof of future indeterminism is turned to shatter the past already into many worlds/minds, thus Everett relativity is merely the
    [Show full text]
  • Possible Worlds I: Modal Realism
    Possible Worlds I: Modal Realism May 31, 2009 It is difficult to wander far in contemporary metaphysics without bumping into talk of possible worlds. And reference to possible worlds is not confined to metaphysics. It can be found in contemporary epistemology and ethics, and has even found its way into linguistics and decision theory. But what are those possible worlds, the entities to which theorists in these disciplines all appeal? Call any attempt to answer this question a theory of possible worlds. This paper sets out and evaluates a leading contemporary theory of possible worlds. The view’s principal proponent is David Lewis, and his label for it is ‘Modal Realism,’ which I will abbreviate ‘MR.’1 The view accepts the following sys- tematic correspondence between certain modal facts and facts regarding the existence of possible worlds: (SC) it is possible that φ iff there is a w such that w is a possible world and ‘φ’ is true at w. Lewis proposes MR, in part, as an attempt to specify the nature of the possible worlds whose existence is required by (SC)’s instances. This paper outlines Lewis’s view and discusses some main lines of objection. I will start by noting two competing ambitions for a theory of possible worlds (§1): that a theory of possible worlds be reductive and user-friendly. I will then outline Lewis’s version of MR (§2), and consider objections on the grounds that MR is not reductive (§3) and not user-friendly (§4). 1 Two Ambitions for a Theory of Possible Worlds There are at least two ambitions one might have for a theory of possible worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • 22 Worlds Within Worlds: a Dilemma for Modal Realism
    Worlds within Worlds: 22 a Dilemma for Modal Realism Subrena E. Smith | University of New Hampshire. In this paper I will present an argument that David Lewis’ modal realism is self-refuting, and that the contradiction that makes it self-refuting can only be blocked by modifying certain other of Lewis’ philosophical commitments. My argument will proceed as follows. First, I will briefly describe the motivation for and the main components of Lewisian modal realism. Second, I will explain Lewis’ view of what it is for an individual or a set to exist in a world. Third, I go on to argue that Lewis’ position creates a dilemma for modal realism: either each world contains all the other worlds as parts, which violates the principle that worlds are spatiotemporally isolated, or worlds are reducible to sets, which violates the principle that worlds are individuals. Finally, I briefly discuss a suggestion by Divers that strongly bears on this problem. Modal Realism I begin with a summary description of modal realism. Modal realism is motivated by the broadly Quinean view that quantifying over possibilia provides us with the best way of making sense of modal claims, a position that Lewis (1986a) defends in considerable detail as “a philosopher’s paradise.” Lewis identifies possibilia with worlds. Worlds are concrete (“a big physical object” [Lewis, 1986b: 1]) and non-overlapping. They are non-overlapping because they are spatiotemporally, and therefore causally, segregated from one another. Items are spatiotemporally or causally related to one another just in case they are parts of the same world, and no two worlds share any parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Primitive Modality and Possible Worlds
    CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by RERO DOC Digital Library Primitive Modality and Possible Worlds JAVIER KALHAT Abstract This paper sets out a number of reasons for thinking that the framework of possible worlds, even when construed non-reductively, does not provide an adequate basis for an explanation of modality. I first consider a non-reductive version of Lewis’ modal realism, and then move on to consider the ersatzist approach of Plantinga et al.My main complaint is that the framework of possible worlds gets the semantics and meta- physics of ordinary modal discourse wrong. That is, possible worlds do not give us an adequate answer to the semantic question of what ordinary modal claims mean, nor do they give us an adequate answer to the metaphysical question of what makes such claims true. There is a growing consensus among philosophers that modality cannot be reductively explained. Modal notions are to be accounted for, not by trying to reduce them to non-modal ones, but rather by tracing their complex interconnections with one another. The most prominent non-reductive approach to modality is what David Lewis calls ersatzism.1 Like Lewis, ersatzists attempt to explain modality in terms of possible worlds and their inhabitants. Unlike Lewis, they construe possible worlds as abstract representations of concrete worlds, rather than as concrete worlds themselves. And unlike Lewis, of course, they construe possible worlds as primitively modal in nature. Proponents of ersatzism include Adams, Kripke, Plantinga, and Stalnaker among others.2 1 David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986), Ch.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Really David Lewis a Realist?
    Ontology Studies 8, 2008 119 Is really David Lewis a realist? Sorin Costreie University of Western Ontario Department of Philosophy Talbot College University of Bucharest Department of Philosophy Resumen. ¿Es David Lewis realmente un realista? Paradoxically, concerning the structure of the world, David Lewis endorses a very nominalistic point of view, whereas he approaches possible worlds from an extreme realistic position. The aim of the present paper is exactly to analyze the relation between the ontology of actual world and the possible worlds ontology in the case of David Lewis, and to see whether or not this tension between the two irreconcilable positions is based on an inner contradiction in his philosophy. Key Words: nominalism, realism, possible worlds, actual world Abstract Paradoxically, concerning the structure of the world, David Lewis endorses a very nominalistic point of view, whereas he approaches possible worlds from an extreme realistic position. The aim of the present paper is exactly to analyze the relation between the ontology of actual world and the possible worlds ontology in the case of David Lewis, and to see whether or not this tension between the two irreconcilable positions is based on an inner contradiction in his philosophy. Key Words: nominalism, realism, possible worlds, actual world In assessing David Lewis’ ontology, one seems to be trapped in the following dilemma: on one hand, he holds a nominalistic position regarding the structure of the world, and, on the other hand, he is well-known for endorsing a realistic position concerning possible worlds. Lewis says explicitly: “That ontology, though Nominalistic, is in other respects generous.
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Realism: the Radical 1 for the American Philosophy Forum
    1 2 Modal Realism: The Radical 1 For The American Philosophy Forum. 2 3 The latest version of this handout will Shimpei Endo be available on my website: endoshim- peiendo.github.io June 23, 2019 (Sat) 10:00-10:40 3 Master of Logic, ILLC, Unviersity of Amsterdam. My main interests David Lewis is not extreme enough. Spatialize his modal realism. are metaphysics and logic(s), partic- ularly, modal realism and semantics for non-classical modal logics. Lewis’ “Mad Dog”Modal Realism claims that there are pos- [email protected] sible worlds and possible things exist as concrete entities as our actual world and things around us. A world is a maximal sum of spatio-temporally connected. No world is metaphysically privileged: actuality is just indexical. 4 4 David Lewis. On the Plurality of Worlds. Blackwell, Oxford, 1986 Many “incredulous stares” have criticized him. 5 5 Shimpei Endo. Contemporary Debates on Possible Worlds. Japanese Student Research Notes of Philosophy of Science, Too extreme?Not extreme enough! How to rescue Lewisian 1(1):135–144, 2018 modal realism? Instead of milding down 6 , I would make Lewisian 6 Richard B Miller. Moderate Modal modal realism more extreme. Realism. Philosophia, 28(3):3—-38, 2001 Lewis is not that crazy for following naturalistic (?) traditions. In total, Lewisian modal metaphysics offers a good deal: a “paradise for philosophers” for a reasonable price. 1. Utility. Possible worlds explain modal phenomena and others. 7 8 7 David K Lewis. Counterfactuals. Basil Blackwell, 1973 2. Quinean ontological commitment. We should admit the existence 8 of possible worlds because our best theory requires thier existence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Methodology of Modal Logic As Metaphysics
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXVIII No. 3, May 2014 doi: 10.1111/phpr.12100 © 2014 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC The Methodology of Modal Logic as Metaphysics PHILLIP BRICKER University of Massachusetts Amherst Timothy Williamson’s Modal Logic as Metaphysics is, among much else, a detailed and complex defense of the metaphysical view he calls necessitism, the view that necessarily everything necessarily exists (is something), that although it may be a contingent matter how things are, what things there are is entirely a matter of necessity. The majority of contemporary modal metaphysicians reject this view; they are contingentists. Williamson exam- ines the case for necessitism with great thoroughness, and with a distinctive methodology captured in slogan form by the book’s title. The book is an impressive achievement, and will have an impact on the shape of future debate. Necessitism appears to fly in the face of common opinion. Surely—or so I think—if my parents had never met, then I would not have existed. Surely—or so I think—I could have had a brother (although I actually do not), without it being the case that there (actually) exists something that could have been my brother. Indeed, on the familiar assumption that one’s genetic makeup is part of one’s essence, necessitism leads to an ontological explosion of my possible brothers, all of whom (actually) exist. A common response to necessitism is that the conflict with common opinion is so great that it can be rejected out of hand.1 Williamson would disagree.
    [Show full text]
  • Modal Panentheism Nagasawa, Yujin
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Birmingham Research Portal Modal Panentheism Nagasawa, Yujin License: Other (please specify with Rights Statement) Document Version Peer reviewed version Citation for published version (Harvard): Nagasawa, Y 2016, Modal Panentheism. in A Buckareff & Y Nagasawa (eds), Alternative concepts of God: essays on the metaphysics of the divine. Oxford University Press. Link to publication on Research at Birmingham portal Publisher Rights Statement: Chapter 5, Modal Panentheism by Yujin Nagasawa, 2016, reproduced by permission of Oxford University Press: https://global.oup.com/academic/product/alternative-concepts-of-god-9780198722250?cc=gb&lang=en&# Posting on the your own personal website or in an institutional or subject based repository after a 12 month period for Science and Medical titles and a 24 month period for Academic, Trade and Reference titles. General rights Unless a licence is specified above, all rights (including copyright and moral rights) in this document are retained by the authors and/or the copyright holders. The express permission of the copyright holder must be obtained for any use of this material other than for purposes permitted by law. •Users may freely distribute the URL that is used to identify this publication. •Users may download and/or print one copy of the publication from the University of Birmingham research portal for the purpose of private study or non-commercial research. •User may use extracts from the document in line with the concept of ‘fair dealing’ under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 (?) •Users may not further distribute the material nor use it for the purposes of commercial gain.
    [Show full text]
  • WHAT in the WORLD ARE POSSIBLE WORLDS? a Thesis by MARK JOHN DONDERO Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&
    WHAT IN THE WORLD ARE POSSIBLE WORLDS? A Thesis by MARK JOHN DONDERO Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS May 2009 Major Subject: Philosophy WHAT IN THE WORLD ARE POSSIBLE WORLDS? A Thesis by MARK JOHN DONDERO Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved by: Chair of Committee, Christopher Menzel Committee Members, Michael Hand Thomas Ioerger Head of Department Daniel Conway May 2009 Major Subject: Philosophy iii ABSTRACT What in the World Are Possible Worlds? (May 2009) Mark John Dondero, B.A., Rutgers University Chair of Advisory Committee: Dr. Christopher Menzel Ted Sider writes that “many are impressed with the utility of possible worlds in lin- guistics and philosophy”, and this is true, in particular, of those with an interest in modal logic. However, in the midst of the marvelous milieu brought on by the development of possible world semantics, some have stopped to ask just what it is that possible worlds are. They certainly seem useful, and we seem to understand how to use them and talk about them, but what precisely is it that we’re talking about when we talk of possible worlds? In this thesis, I will attempt to outline the most significant and well-recognized view in this debate: that of David Lewis. Through my discussion of him, I will find occa- sion to discuss some alternative views that have arisen.
    [Show full text]