Comparing Infinite Sets

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Comparing Infinite Sets Comparing Infinite Sets By Christina Grossman A Thesis Submitted to the Faculty of the DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of MASTER OF MIDDLE SCHOOL MATHEMATICS LEADERSHIP In the Graduate College THE UNIVERSITY OF ARIZONA 2010 1 In thinking about infinite sets, one might not associate the process of comparing infinite sets because….do they really have a size? Finite sets have a size associated with them; however, how can one size something that is considered infinite? By defining what exactly is an infinite set and looking at the possibility of different sizes of infinite sets when determined by one-to-one and onto functions, the result will reveal the relationship between the infinite sets of N , Z , Q , and R . 2 Before exploring infinite sets, think about how numbers are used in everyday life. As children, we are taught how to use numbers very early in our learning. We began our relationship with numbers by counting our toes, fingers, apples, and oranges. These are finite; they can be counted. Counting these items usually began with using numbers 1, 2, 3, … etc. Everything that we know of the natural world can be counted this way. In turn, this set of numbers that we use is called the set of natural numbers ( N ). Because we use the natural numbers to count objects or other things, they are usually known as the counting numbers. Finite Sets We are able to count things as children using the natural numbers and we also learn about how to find the size of groups or in this case sets of things. When looking at a group of people, you count the number of people in that group, thus calculating the size of the group. If wanting to know the size of a set of numbers, you need to be able to count how many numbers, or elements are in the set. From what we know at such a young age, we use the natural numbers as tools to count the elements of something that is finite. The word finite is used to describe a set or a group of elements or objects that can be counted and where the counting stops eventually. In general, sets do not always include numbers. For the sake of familiarity, number sets will be used. For example, if there are eight elements in a set of numbers it might be {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8}. Looking further at this set, we can say that 1 is the first element of this set of numbers and 6 is the sixth element of this set of numbers. If there are ten elements in a set of numbers it might be {2, 4, 6, 8, 10, 12, 14, 16, 18, 20} where 14 is the seventh element in this set. Because these particular two sets of numbers have a definite number of elements that we can count, we call these finite sets. With finite sets, the elements can be counted by use of the natural numbers. 3 Since there are elements that can be counted, finite sets can now be sized. In mathematics, instead of size, the word cardinality is used. Thus, if a finite set has k elements, the finite set is of cardinality k. Being able to know the set is finite and its cardinality can be used to compare it to other finite sets. In looking at the two given sets below, there are a few things that can describe the two of them: A = {5, 6, 7, 8} and B = {1, 2, 3, 4}. Set A and B are finite sets. Set A is of cardinality 4. Set B is also of cardinality 4. Look at how each element of the two sets are arranged below. 5 1 6 2 7 3 8 4 Because every element in set B has an element in set A assigned to it, this is called a relation that is onto. Each element in set A does not go to more than one element in set B. This is relation is one-to-one because no two elements of set A go to the same element in B. Just like people are different from one another, so are relations between different sets. Take the set C = {1, 2, 3} and set D = {3, 6, 9, 12, 15}. Both sets are finite, but their cardinality is different. Set C has a cardinality of 3 as opposed to set D has a cardinality of 5. In this case again, cardinality is used to describe finite sets of numbers. Look at how this relation compares between these two sets. 1 3 6 4 2 9 3 12 15 Each element in set C corresponds to an element in set D and no two elements in set C go to the same element in set D. This relation is called one-to-one. The difference in this case is that not all the elements in set D correspond to an element in set C. This relation is not onto. Another relation between finite sets is depicted in figure 1. NOT "One-to-One", but onto Figure 1 http://www.regentsprep.org/Regents/math/algtrig/ATP5/OntoFunctions.htm In analyzing finite sets, they can be compared to each other by way of cardinality. For example, if two sets have the same cardinality, it is that there is a relation between them that is both one-to-one and onto. The relationship between the status of cardinality and a one to one and onto relation is that for two sets to have the same cardinality there must exist a one-to-one and onto relationship between them. Focusing on cardinality is fairly easy when dealing with finite sets. The interesting aspect comes to play when dealing with varying infinite sets. In 5 review, there are key features when comparing finite sets and now infinite sets: (a) the counting elements must be in numeric/alphabetic order; (b) the particular set has to be in one-to-one correspondence with the set being counted; and (c) the cardinality must be the same. Infinite Sets A finite set has a first element, second element, until it reaches its kth element. It did not keep going forever on the number of elements in the finite set. In an infinite set, you still have the first element, second element, and so on. However there is no last element because the infinite set will contain a kth element and there will always be a (k+1)th element because there is no limit to the number of elements in an infinite set. When first looking at infinite sets, that was all that I understood about them. In contrast, infinite sets are more than a set of numbers that continue infinitely, they can also either be countable or uncountable. It is possible to figure how a given infinite set is countable or not regardless of whether the number of elements is infinite. This traces back to the interesting characteristics of the set of natural numbers ( N ). The set of natural numbers ( N ) is a set that can be written as {1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9…n…}. Because this set has an infinite number of elements, it is called an infinite set. By definition, if an infinite set behaves this way, the infinite set is a denumerable set. “Both finite sets and denumerable sets are countable sets because we can count, or enumerate the elements in the set (Plummer, 2009).” By way of counting an infinite set, it does not mean that you can sit there and be able to give the total number of elements in one sitting. It just refers to the fact that in an infinite set, you can choose a first element, then a second element, and so on, and that you can eventually get to every element of the infinite set by counting. What is special about a denumerable set is that is has “…a one-to-one correspondence between the elements in the 6 infinite set and the infinite set of natural numbers ( N ) (Plummer, 2009). “ The infinite set of natural numbers ( N ) is considered a denumerable set, countable. The set of natural numbers ( N ) is used as a reference set for any denumerable set, just as the set {1,2,3} is a reference set for any set of cardinality 3. That is what is so fascinating about set N . In relation to using the infinite set N to describe the cardinality of finite sets, it is also used to describe the cardinality of infinite sets. With finite sets, if two finite sets were of the same cardinality there was a possibility of the relation to be one-to-one and also onto. In the same respect, if the infinite set has a one-to-one and onto correspondence with the set N , then it is considered countable and has the same cardinality as N . To be countable, the infinite set must have a defined cardinality as discussed with finite sets. One of the questions of researching this area was whether or not there are infinite sets that have different sizes when size is determined by one to one and onto relations. The infinite sets in question are the set of integers ( Z ), the set of rational numbers ( Q ), and the set of real numbers ( R ). To visualize how these infinite sets relate to each other, refer to figure 2. Irrationals Rationals Integers Natural Numbers 7 Figure 2: A diagram depicting the set of real numbers.
Recommended publications
  • Math/CS 467 (Lesieutre) Homework 2 September 9, 2020 Submission
    Math/CS 467 (Lesieutre) Homework 2 September 9, 2020 Submission instructions: Upload your solutions, minus the code, to Gradescope, like you did last week. Email your code to me as an attachment at [email protected], including the string HW2 in the subject line so I can filter them. Problem 1. Both prime numbers and perfect squares get more and more uncommon among larger and larger numbers. But just how uncommon are they? a) Roughly how many perfect squares are there less than or equal to N? p 2 For a positivep integer k, notice that k is less than N if and only if k ≤ N. So there are about N possibilities for k. b) Are there likely to be more prime numbers or perfect squares less than 10100? Give an estimate of the number of each. p There are about 1010 = 1050 perfect squares. According to the prime number theorem, there are about 10100 10100 π(10100) ≈ = = 1098 · log 10 = 2:3 · 1098: log(10100) 100 log 10 That’s a lot more primes than squares. (Note that the “log” in the prime number theorem is the natural log. If you use log10, you won’t get the right answer.) Problem 2. Compute g = gcd(1661; 231). Find integers a and b so that 1661a + 231b = g. (You can do this by hand or on the computer; either submit the code or show your work.) We do this using the Euclidean algorithm. At each step, we keep track of how to write ri as a combination of a and b.
    [Show full text]
  • COMPSCI 501: Formal Language Theory Insights on Computability Turing Machines Are a Model of Computation Two (No Longer) Surpris
    Insights on Computability Turing machines are a model of computation COMPSCI 501: Formal Language Theory Lecture 11: Turing Machines Two (no longer) surprising facts: Marius Minea Although simple, can describe everything [email protected] a (real) computer can do. University of Massachusetts Amherst Although computers are powerful, not everything is computable! Plus: “play” / program with Turing machines! 13 February 2019 Why should we formally define computation? Must indeed an algorithm exist? Back to 1900: David Hilbert’s 23 open problems Increasingly a realization that sometimes this may not be the case. Tenth problem: “Occasionally it happens that we seek the solution under insufficient Given a Diophantine equation with any number of un- hypotheses or in an incorrect sense, and for this reason do not succeed. known quantities and with rational integral numerical The problem then arises: to show the impossibility of the solution under coefficients: To devise a process according to which the given hypotheses or in the sense contemplated.” it can be determined in a finite number of operations Hilbert, 1900 whether the equation is solvable in rational integers. This asks, in effect, for an algorithm. Hilbert’s Entscheidungsproblem (1928): Is there an algorithm that And “to devise” suggests there should be one. decides whether a statement in first-order logic is valid? Church and Turing A Turing machine, informally Church and Turing both showed in 1936 that a solution to the Entscheidungsproblem is impossible for the theory of arithmetic. control To make and prove such a statement, one needs to define computability. In a recent paper Alonzo Church has introduced an idea of “effective calculability”, read/write head which is equivalent to my “computability”, but is very differently defined.
    [Show full text]
  • Section 4.2 Counting
    Section 4.2 Counting CS 130 – Discrete Structures Counting: Multiplication Principle • The idea is to find out how many members are present in a finite set • Multiplication Principle: If there are n possible outcomes for a first event and m possible outcomes for a second event, then there are n*m possible outcomes for the sequence of two events. • From the multiplication principle, it follows that for 2 sets A and B, |A x B| = |A|x|B| – A x B consists of all ordered pairs with first component from A and second component from B CS 130 – Discrete Structures 27 Examples • How many four digit number can there be if repetitions of numbers is allowed? • And if repetition of numbers is not allowed? • If a man has 4 suits, 8 shirts and 5 ties, how many outfits can he put together? CS 130 – Discrete Structures 28 Counting: Addition Principle • Addition Principle: If A and B are disjoint events with n and m outcomes, respectively, then the total number of possible outcomes for event “A or B” is n+m • If A and B are disjoint sets, then |A B| = |A| + |B| using the addition principle • Example: A customer wants to purchase a vehicle from a dealer. The dealer has 23 autos and 14 trucks in stock. How many selections does the customer have? CS 130 – Discrete Structures 29 More On Addition Principle • If A and B are disjoint sets, then |A B| = |A| + |B| • Prove that if A and B are finite sets then |A-B| = |A| - |A B| and |A-B| = |A| - |B| if B A (A-B) (A B) = (A B) (A B) = A (B B) = A U = A Also, A-B and A B are disjoint sets, therefore using the addition principle, |A| = | (A-B) (A B) | = |A-B| + |A B| Hence, |A-B| = |A| - |A B| If B A, then A B = B Hence, |A-B| = |A| - |B| CS 130 – Discrete Structures 30 Using Principles Together • How many four-digit numbers begin with a 4 or a 5 • How many three-digit integers (numbers between 100 and 999 inclusive) are even? • Suppose the last four digit of a telephone number must include at least one repeated digit.
    [Show full text]
  • 6Th Online Learning #2 MATH Subject: Mathematics State: Ohio
    6th Online Learning #2 MATH Subject: Mathematics State: Ohio Student Name: Teacher Name: School Name: 1 Yari was doing the long division problem shown below. When she finishes, her teacher tells her she made a mistake. Find Yari's mistake. Explain it to her using at least 2 complete sentences. Then, re-do the long division problem correctly. 2 Use the computation shown below to find the products. Explain how you found your answers. (a) 189 × 16 (b) 80 × 16 (c) 9 × 16 3 Solve. 34,992 ÷ 81 = ? 4 The total amount of money collected by a store for sweatshirt sales was $10,000. Each sweatshirt sold for $40. What was the total number of sweatshirts sold by the store? (A) 100 (B) 220 (C) 250 (D) 400 5 Justin divided 403 by a number and got a quotient of 26 with a remainder of 13. What was the number Justin divided by? (A) 13 (B) 14 (C) 15 (D) 16 6 What is the quotient of 13,632 ÷ 48? (A) 262 R36 (B) 272 (C) 284 (D) 325 R32 7 What is the result when 75,069 is divided by 45? 8 What is the value of 63,106 ÷ 72? Write your answer below. 9 Divide. 21,900 ÷ 25 Write the exact quotient below. 10 The manager of a bookstore ordered 480 copies of a book. The manager paid a total of $7,440 for the books. The books arrived at the store in 5 cartons. Each carton contained the same number of books. A worker unpacked books at a rate of 48 books every 2 minutes.
    [Show full text]
  • 180: Counting Techniques
    180: Counting Techniques In the following exercise we demonstrate the use of a few fundamental counting principles, namely the addition, multiplication, complementary, and inclusion-exclusion principles. While none of the principles are particular complicated in their own right, it does take some practice to become familiar with them, and recognise when they are applicable. I have attempted to indicate where alternate approaches are possible (and reasonable). Problem: Assume n ≥ 2 and m ≥ 1. Count the number of functions f :[n] ! [m] (i) in total. (ii) such that f(1) = 1 or f(2) = 1. (iii) with minx2[n] f(x) ≤ 5. (iv) such that f(1) ≥ f(2). (v) that are strictly increasing; that is, whenever x < y, f(x) < f(y). (vi) that are one-to-one (injective). (vii) that are onto (surjective). (viii) that are bijections. (ix) such that f(x) + f(y) is even for every x; y 2 [n]. (x) with maxx2[n] f(x) = minx2[n] f(x) + 1. Solution: (i) A function f :[n] ! [m] assigns for every integer 1 ≤ x ≤ n an integer 1 ≤ f(x) ≤ m. For each integer x, we have m options. As we make n such choices (independently), the total number of functions is m × m × : : : m = mn. (ii) (We assume n ≥ 2.) Let A1 be the set of functions with f(1) = 1, and A2 the set of functions with f(2) = 1. Then A1 [ A2 represents those functions with f(1) = 1 or f(2) = 1, which is precisely what we need to count. We have jA1 [ A2j = jA1j + jA2j − jA1 \ A2j.
    [Show full text]
  • Infinite Sets
    “mcs-ftl” — 2010/9/8 — 0:40 — page 379 — #385 13 Infinite Sets So you might be wondering how much is there to say about an infinite set other than, well, it has an infinite number of elements. Of course, an infinite set does have an infinite number of elements, but it turns out that not all infinite sets have the same size—some are bigger than others! And, understanding infinity is not as easy as you might think. Some of the toughest questions in mathematics involve infinite sets. Why should you care? Indeed, isn’t computer science only about finite sets? Not exactly. For example, we deal with the set of natural numbers N all the time and it is an infinite set. In fact, that is why we have induction: to reason about predicates over N. Infinite sets are also important in Part IV of the text when we talk about random variables over potentially infinite sample spaces. So sit back and open your mind for a few moments while we take a very brief look at infinity. 13.1 Injections, Surjections, and Bijections We know from Theorem 7.2.1 that if there is an injection or surjection between two finite sets, then we can say something about the relative sizes of the two sets. The same is true for infinite sets. In fact, relations are the primary tool for determining the relative size of infinite sets. Definition 13.1.1. Given any two sets A and B, we say that A surj B iff there is a surjection from A to B, A inj B iff there is an injection from A to B, A bij B iff there is a bijection between A and B, and A strict B iff there is a surjection from A to B but there is no bijection from B to A.
    [Show full text]
  • UNIT 1: Counting and Cardinality
    Grade: K Unit Number: 1 Unit Name: Counting and Cardinality Instructional Days: 40 days EVERGREEN SCHOOL K DISTRICT GRADE Unit 1 Unit 2 Unit 3 Unit 4 Unit 5 Unit 6 Counting Operations Geometry Measurement Numbers & Algebraic Thinking and and Data Operations in Cardinality Base 10 8 weeks 4 weeks 8 weeks 3 weeks 4 weeks 5 weeks UNIT 1: Counting and Cardinality Dear Colleagues, Enclosed is a unit that addresses all of the Common Core Counting and Cardinality standards for Kindergarten. We took the time to analyze, group and organize them into a logical learning sequence. Thank you for entrusting us with the task of designing a rich learning experience for all students, and we hope to improve the unit as you pilot it and make it your own. Sincerely, Grade K Math Unit Design Team CRITICAL THINKING COLLABORATION COMMUNICATION CREATIVITY Evergreen School District 1 MATH Curriculum Map aligned to the California Common Core State Standards 7/29/14 Grade: K Unit Number: 1 Unit Name: Counting and Cardinality Instructional Days: 40 days UNIT 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS Overview of the grade K Mathematics Program . 3 Essential Standards . 4 Emphasized Mathematical Practices . 4 Enduring Understandings & Essential Questions . 5 Chapter Overviews . 6 Chapter 1 . 8 Chapter 2 . 9 Chapter 3 . 10 Chapter 4 . 11 End-of-Unit Performance Task . 12 Appendices . 13 Evergreen School District 2 MATH Curriculum Map aligned to the California Common Core State Standards 7/29/14 Grade: K Unit Number: 1 Unit Name: Counting and Cardinality Instructional Days: 40 days Overview of the Grade K Mathematics Program UNIT NAME APPROX.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch
    Axiomatic Set Teory P.D.Welch. August 16, 2020 Contents Page 1 Axioms and Formal Systems 1 1.1 Introduction 1 1.2 Preliminaries: axioms and formal systems. 3 1.2.1 The formal language of ZF set theory; terms 4 1.2.2 The Zermelo-Fraenkel Axioms 7 1.3 Transfinite Recursion 9 1.4 Relativisation of terms and formulae 11 2 Initial segments of the Universe 17 2.1 Singular ordinals: cofinality 17 2.1.1 Cofinality 17 2.1.2 Normal Functions and closed and unbounded classes 19 2.1.3 Stationary Sets 22 2.2 Some further cardinal arithmetic 24 2.3 Transitive Models 25 2.4 The H sets 27 2.4.1 H - the hereditarily finite sets 28 2.4.2 H - the hereditarily countable sets 29 2.5 The Montague-Levy Reflection theorem 30 2.5.1 Absoluteness 30 2.5.2 Reflection Theorems 32 2.6 Inaccessible Cardinals 34 2.6.1 Inaccessible cardinals 35 2.6.2 A menagerie of other large cardinals 36 3 Formalising semantics within ZF 39 3.1 Definite terms and formulae 39 3.1.1 The non-finite axiomatisability of ZF 44 3.2 Formalising syntax 45 3.3 Formalising the satisfaction relation 46 3.4 Formalising definability: the function Def. 47 3.5 More on correctness and consistency 48 ii iii 3.5.1 Incompleteness and Consistency Arguments 50 4 The Constructible Hierarchy 53 4.1 The L -hierarchy 53 4.2 The Axiom of Choice in L 56 4.3 The Axiom of Constructibility 57 4.4 The Generalised Continuum Hypothesis in L.
    [Show full text]
  • Algorithms, Turing Machines and Algorithmic Undecidability
    U.U.D.M. Project Report 2021:7 Algorithms, Turing machines and algorithmic undecidability Agnes Davidsdottir Examensarbete i matematik, 15 hp Handledare: Vera Koponen Examinator: Martin Herschend April 2021 Department of Mathematics Uppsala University Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Algorithms . .1 1.2 Formalisation of the concept of algorithms . .1 2 Turing machines 3 2.1 Coding of machines . .4 2.2 Unbounded and bounded machines . .6 2.3 Binary sequences representing real numbers . .6 2.4 Examples of Turing machines . .7 3 Undecidability 9 i 1 Introduction This paper is about Alan Turing's paper On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem, which was published in 1936. In his paper, he introduced what later has been called Turing machines as well as a few examples of undecidable problems. A few of these will be brought up here along with Turing's arguments in the proofs but using a more modern terminology. To begin with, there will be some background on the history of why this breakthrough happened at that given time. 1.1 Algorithms The concept of an algorithm has always existed within the world of mathematics. It refers to a process meant to solve a problem in a certain number of steps. It is often repetitive, with only a few rules to follow. In more recent years, the term also has been used to refer to the rules a computer follows to operate in a certain way. Thereby, an algorithm can be used in a plethora of circumstances. The word might describe anything from the process of solving a Rubik's cube to how search engines like Google work [4].
    [Show full text]
  • 13A. Lists of Numbers
    13A. Lists of Numbers Topics: Lists of numbers List Methods: Void vs Fruitful Methods Setting up Lists A Function that returns a list We Have Seen Lists Before Recall that the rgb encoding of a color involves a triplet of numbers: MyColor = [.3,.4,.5] DrawDisk(0,0,1,FillColor = MyColor) MyColor is a list. A list of numbers is a way of assembling a sequence of numbers. Terminology x = [3.0, 5.0, -1.0, 0.0, 3.14] How we talk about what is in a list: 5.0 is an item in the list x. 5.0 is an entry in the list x. 5.0 is an element in the list x. 5.0 is a value in the list x. Get used to the synonyms. A List Has a Length The following would assign the value of 5 to the variable n: x = [3.0, 5.0, -1.0, 0.0, 3.14] n = len(x) The Entries in a List are Accessed Using Subscripts The following would assign the value of -1.0 to the variable a: x = [3.0, 5.0, -1.0, 0.0, 3.14] a = x[2] A List Can Be Sliced This: x = [10,40,50,30,20] y = x[1:3] z = x[:3] w = x[3:] Is same as: x = [10,40,50,30,20] y = [40,50] z = [10,40,50] w = [30,20] Lists are Similar to Strings s: ‘x’ ‘L’ ‘1’ ‘?’ ‘a’ ‘C’ x: 3 5 2 7 0 4 A string is a sequence of characters.
    [Show full text]
  • Ground and Explanation in Mathematics
    volume 19, no. 33 ncreased attention has recently been paid to the fact that in math- august 2019 ematical practice, certain mathematical proofs but not others are I recognized as explaining why the theorems they prove obtain (Mancosu 2008; Lange 2010, 2015a, 2016; Pincock 2015). Such “math- ematical explanation” is presumably not a variety of causal explana- tion. In addition, the role of metaphysical grounding as underwriting a variety of explanations has also recently received increased attention Ground and Explanation (Correia and Schnieder 2012; Fine 2001, 2012; Rosen 2010; Schaffer 2016). Accordingly, it is natural to wonder whether mathematical ex- planation is a variety of grounding explanation. This paper will offer several arguments that it is not. in Mathematics One obstacle facing these arguments is that there is currently no widely accepted account of either mathematical explanation or grounding. In the case of mathematical explanation, I will try to avoid this obstacle by appealing to examples of proofs that mathematicians themselves have characterized as explanatory (or as non-explanatory). I will offer many examples to avoid making my argument too dependent on any single one of them. I will also try to motivate these characterizations of various proofs as (non-) explanatory by proposing an account of what makes a proof explanatory. In the case of grounding, I will try to stick with features of grounding that are relatively uncontroversial among grounding theorists. But I will also Marc Lange look briefly at how some of my arguments would fare under alternative views of grounding. I hope at least to reveal something about what University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill grounding would have to look like in order for a theorem’s grounds to mathematically explain why that theorem obtains.
    [Show full text]
  • Whole Numbers
    03_WNCP_Gr4_U02.qxd.qxd 3/19/07 12:04 PM Page 32 U N I T Whole Numbers Learning Goals • recognize and read numbers from 1 to 10 000 • read and write numbers in standard form, expanded form, and written form • compare and order numbers • use diagrams to show relationships • estimate sums and differences • add and subtract 3-digit and 4-digit numbers mentally • use personal strategies to add and subtract • pose and solve problems 32 03_WNCP_Gr4_U02.qxd.qxd 3/19/07 12:04 PM Page 33 Key Words expanded form The elephant is the world’s largest animal. There are two kinds of elephants. standard form The African elephant can be found in most parts of Africa. Venn diagram The Asian elephant can be found in Southeast Asia. Carroll diagram African elephants are larger and heavier than their Asian cousins. The mass of a typical adult African female elephant is about 3600 kg. The mass of a typical male is about 5500 kg. The mass of a typical adult Asian female elephant is about 2720 kg. The mass of a typical male is about 4990 kg. •How could you find how much greater the mass of the African female elephant is than the Asian female elephant? •Kandula,a male Asian elephant,had a mass of about 145 kg at birth. Estimate how much mass he will gain from birth to adulthood. •The largest elephant on record was an African male with an estimated mass of about 10 000 kg. About how much greater was the mass of this elephant than the typical African male elephant? 33 03_WNCP_Gr4_U02.qxd.qxd 3/19/07 12:04 PM Page 34 LESSON Whole Numbers to 10 000 The largest marching band ever assembled had 4526 members.
    [Show full text]