What Is Sentience? and Why Do We Care?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

What Is Sentience? and Why Do We Care? What is Sentience? and Why do We Care? Ian J.H. Duncan University of Guelph Guelph, Ontario, Canada What is Sentience? Sentience n. The condition or quality of being sentient, consciousness, susceptibility to sensation. Sentient adj. A. That which feels or is capable of feeling; having the power or function of sensation or of perception by the senses. B. That which has sensation or feeling. The Oxford English Dictionary Why do we care? We should care, because being sentient means that what happens to animals MATTERS TO THEM A short history Dark Ages Evidence that there was some acceptance of sentience in animals. Renaissance Good evidence from the writings of Leonardo, Erasmus, Thomas More, Montaigne, Shakespeare et al., that animal sentience was accepted as part of secular knowledge. A short history But of course, philosophers did not follow the views of the masses, and there is a clear line of argument for non-sentience : Aristotle (384-322 BC) Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274) René Descartes (1596-1650) Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) Had little to say about animals, but he rejected the claims of Aristotle, Aquinas, Descartes and Kant outright. He said that rationality is not the relevant matter: “The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? But, Can they suffer?” William Youatt (1776-1847) Influential English veterinarian (who embarked on a veterinary career at the age of 35!). 1830. Canine Madness. 1831. The Horse. With a Treatise on Draught. 1834. Cattle. Their Breeds, Management and Diseases. 1837. Sheep. 1845. The Dog. 1847. The Pig. 1828–1847 Editor of The Veterinarian William Youatt (1776-1847) 1839. The Obligation and Extent of Humanity to Brutes, Principally Considered with Reference to the Domesticated Animals. Republished in 2004. Edited, introduced and annotated by Rod Preece. Edwin Mellen Press, Lewiston, N.Y. William Youatt (1776-1847) Youatt writes of animals’ senses, emotions, consciousness, attention, memory, sagacity, docility, association of ideas, imagination, reason, instinct, social affections, the moral qualities, friendship and loyalty. So he, most definitely knew that animals were sentient! William Youatt (1776-1847) More than 30 years before Darwin’s ‘The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals’, Youatt wrote:- “We are operating on animals that have, probably, as keen feelings of pleasure and of pain as ourselves” Darwin, C., 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. John Murray, London. Noted the universal nature of human facial emotional expression Described some commonalities in expression of emotions in animals Suggested a shared evolution Fig. 5. Dog approaching another dog with hostile intentions Darwin was mainly interested in EMOTIONAL EXPRESSION So he was interested in: Underlying anatomy and physiology Signal value of the expression The evolution of the emotions He seemed to accept the SUBJECTIVE EXPERIENCE associated with the emotions, but this was not explored in any depth. George John Romanes (1848-1894) Born in Kingston, Ontario. Educated at Cambridge. A close friend and disciple of Charles Darwin. He was explicit about subjective experiences of animals. George John Romanes (1883) “Pleasures and Pains must have been evolved as the subjective accompaniment of processes which are respectively beneficial or injurious to the organism, and so evolved for the purpose or to the end that the organism should seek the one and shun the other.” Mental Evolution in Animals The Disconnect So…130 years ago it was commonly accepted by scientists that animals had feelings. This was also the “commonsense” view held by the community. But through much of 20th century, scientists eschewed any study of animal feelings. COMMUNITY SCIENCE How did this disconnect arise? The answer is that a branch of psychology called “Behaviorism” had a huge effect on the way that behavioural scientists thought about the mind, consciousness and feelings through the first 70 years of the 20th century. William James (1842-1910) established principles on which Behaviorism was founded J.B. Watson (1878-1958) the founder of Behaviorism B.F. Skinner (1904-1990) the most famous proponent of Behaviorism. J.B. Watson (1928) “The behaviorist sweeps aside all medieval conceptions. He drops from his scientific vocabulary all subjective terms such as sensation, perception, image, desire and even thinking and emotion.” • These were powerful scientists. • Not surprising that the emergence of animal welfare science was delayed. • But the non-scientific community knew that animals had feelings - and it was feelings that mattered! A short history 1964 Ruth Harrison “Animal Machines” Great emphasis on “suffering”. 1965 “The Brambell Report” “Welfare is a wide term that embraces both the physical and mental well-being of the animal. Any attempt to evaluate welfare, therefore, must take into account the scientific evidence available concerning the feelings of animals that can be derived from their structure and function and also from their behaviour.” A short history 1964 Ruth Harrison “Animal Machines” 1965 “The Brambell Report” In spite of what Harrison and Brambell said, we early welfare scientists assumed that “welfare” would be best assessed with some measurement of stress. (The legacy of Behaviorism was strong) A short history Pattern broken by Donald Griffin at 1975 International Ethology Conference in Parma, Italy. Griffin, D., 1976. The Question of Animal Awareness. Rockefeller, New York. Following which there has been a burgeoning literature on sentience. All organisms have certain needs which have to be satisfied in order that the organism: survives grows reproduces As true for a potato as for a pig If needs not met, organism will show symptoms of atrophy, stress, ill health and will eventually die. Lower invertebrate satisfies its needs by simple, hard-wired, stimulus-response behaviour. (A fly avoids a large shape rushing towards it) Higher organisms (vertebrates) have evolved ‘feelings’ (subjective affective states) to protect their needs in a flexible way. (A bird avoids a cat moving towards it – but its avoidance is governed by fear) Feelings have evolved to protect “biological fitness” (the ability of genetic material to reproduce itself) So, I am drawing a fine distinction between: Primary need Secondary feeling having a nutrient feeling hungry deficiency having a fluid feeling thirsty deficiency avoiding predator feeling frightened being ill feeling ill being stressed feeling stressed being injured feeling pain The term: “TOUCHY-FEELY” Used (disparagingly) to describe anything non-scientific. “HARD SCIENCE” “TOUCHY- FEELY” Primary need Secondary feeling having a nutrient feeling hungry deficiency having a fluid feeling thirsty deficiency avoiding predator feeling frightened being ill feeling ill being stressed feeling stressed being injured feeling pain Within the discipline of Animal Welfare Science, two schools of thought emerged: Biological Feelings School Functioning School (determined to stick (maybe feelings can to hard science) be investigated scientifically) Biological Functioning School Animal welfare is all to do with good biological functioning :- • Absence of a stress response (or absence of a large stress response) • Animal able to ‘cope’ • Animal able to satisfy its biological needs Feelings School Animal welfare is all to do with what the animals feels :- • With the absence of negative emotional states (suffering) • With the presence of positive emotional states (pleasure) (probably) Of course, usually there will be close correspondence between NEED and FEELING (after all, feelings evolved to protect needs) - but not always, particularly in the case of domesticated animals. WHY NOT? NATURAL SELECTION keeps needs and feelings linked ARTIFICIAL SELECTION allows needs and feelings to separate Some examples of a mis-match: Basset Hound – lock up the garbage! Fighting Cocks – extremely aggressive Broiler breeders have huge appetites If allowed to satisfy these appetites, they become obese, ‘unfit’, and they suffer. If feed-restricted, they function well, their nutritional needs are met, and they appear to be ‘fitter’. BUT their welfare is severely compromised by the feed restriction. THEY FEEL HUNGRY ALL THE TIME! You may be misled by the good physical condition and performance of such animals. But welfare is to do with feelings. It resides inside the heads of the animals. And these animals are suffering. POTATO Can be diseased Can be water deficient Can be nutrient deficient Can be damaged POTATO PIG Can be diseased Can be diseased and can suffer from malaise Can be water deficient Can be water-deficient and can suffer from thirst Can be nutrient deficient Can be nutrient-deficient and can suffer from hunger Can be damaged Can be injured and can suffer from pain I would argue that it IS possible to be scientific about these feelings. They can be defined operationally and measured. feeling hungry feeling thirsty feeling frightened feeling ill feeling stressed feeling pain Much of my research career has involved “asking” animals what they feel about the conditions they are kept in and the procedures they are subjected to. The importance of sentience Gradual acceptance that it is feelings that govern welfare …. …. and therefore feelings that should be measured when assessing welfare. (With some resistance from stress physiologists!) The importance of sentience We can now recognize and ‘measure’ some states of suffering in some species: Frustration Fear Pain
Recommended publications
  • Resource Allocation Theory Applied to Farm Animal Production
    RESOURCE ALLOCATION T HEORY APPLIED TO FARM ANIMAL PRODUCTION It is the magician’s wand, by means of which [the agriculturist] may summon into life whatever form and mould he pleases William Youatt (1872) cited in Darwin (1872) One of the most remarkable features in our domesticated races is that we see in them adaptation, not indeed to the animal’s ( . ) own good, but to man’s use or fancy Charles Darwin (1872) RESOURCE ALLOCATION THEORY APPLIED TO FARM ANIMAL PRODUCTION Edited by Wendy Mercedes Rauw Department of Animal Biotechnology University of Nevada-Reno Reno, USA CABI is a trading name of CAB International CABI Head Offi ce CABI North American Offi ce Nosworthy Way 875 Massachusetts Avenue Wallingford 7th Floor Oxfordshire OX10 8DE Cambridge, MA 02139 UK USA Tel: +44 (0)1491 832111 Tel: +1 617 395 4056 Fax: +44 (0)1491 833508 Fax: +1 617 354 6875 E-mail: [email protected] E-mail: [email protected] Website: www.cabi.org ©CAB International 2009. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be re- produced in any form or by any means, electronically, mechanically, by photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owners. A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library, London, UK Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Resource allocation theory applied to farm animal production / edited by Wendy M. Rauw. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-84593-394-4 (alk. paper) 1. Livestock productivity--Mathematical models. 2. Resource allocation. I. Rauw, Wendy M.
    [Show full text]
  • "Higher" Cognition. Animal Sentience
    Animal Sentience 2017.030: Vallortigara on Marino on Thinking Chickens Sentience does not require “higher” cognition Commentary on Marino on Thinking Chickens Giorgio Vallortigara Centre for Mind/Brain Sciences University of Trento, Italy Abstract: I agree with Marino (2017a,b) that the cognitive capacities of chickens are likely to be the same as those of many others vertebrates. Also, data collected in the young of this precocial species provide rich information about how much cognition can be pre-wired and predisposed in the brain. However, evidence of advanced cognition — in chickens or any other organism — says little about sentience (i.e., feeling). We do not deny sentience in human beings who, because of cognitive deficits, would be incapable of exhibiting some of the cognitive feats of chickens. Moreover, complex problem solving, such as transitive inference, which has been reported in chickens, can be observed even in the absence of any accompanying conscious experience in humans. Giorgio Vallortigara, professor of Neuroscience at the Centre for Mind/Brain Sciences of the University of Trento, Italy, studies space, number and object cognition, and brain asymmetry in a comparative and evolutionary perspective. The author of more than 250 scientific papers on these topics, he was the recipient of several awards, including the Geoffroy Saint Hilaire Prize for Ethology (France) and a Doctor Rerum Naturalium Honoris Causa for outstanding achievements in the field of psychobiology (Ruhr University, Germany). r.unitn.it/en/cimec/abc In a revealing piece in New Scientist (Lawler, 2015a) and a beautiful book (Lawler, 2015b), science journalist Andrew Lawler discussed the possible consequences for humans of the sudden disappearance of some domesticated species.
    [Show full text]
  • Dharma Dogs: a Narrative Approach to Understanding the Connection of Sentience Between Humans and Canines Anna Caldwell SIT Study Abroad
    SIT Graduate Institute/SIT Study Abroad SIT Digital Collections Independent Study Project (ISP) Collection SIT Study Abroad Fall 2016 Dharma Dogs: A Narrative Approach to Understanding the Connection of Sentience Between Humans and Canines Anna Caldwell SIT Study Abroad Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcollections.sit.edu/isp_collection Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Asian Studies Commons, Community-Based Learning Commons, Community-Based Research Commons, Family, Life Course, and Society Commons, and the Sociology of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Caldwell, Anna, "Dharma Dogs: A Narrative Approach to Understanding the Connection of Sentience Between Humans and Canines" (2016). Independent Study Project (ISP) Collection. 2500. https://digitalcollections.sit.edu/isp_collection/2500 This Unpublished Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the SIT Study Abroad at SIT Digital Collections. It has been accepted for inclusion in Independent Study Project (ISP) Collection by an authorized administrator of SIT Digital Collections. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Dharma Dogs A Narrative Approach to Understanding the Connection of Sentience Between Humans and Canines Cadwell, Anna Academic Director: Decleer, Hubert and Yonetti, Eben Franklin and Marshall College Anthropology Central Asia, India, Himachal Pradesh, Dharamsala Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for Nepal: Tibetan and Himalayan Peoples, SIT Study Abroad, Fall 2016 Abstract India has the highest population of stray dogs in the world1. Dharamsala, a cross-cultural community in the north Indian Himalayan foothills, is home to a number of particularly overweight and happy canines. However, the street dogs of Dharamsala are not an accurate representation of the state of stay dogs across India.
    [Show full text]
  • Misadventures of Sentience: Animals and the Basis of Equality
    animals Article Misadventures of Sentience: Animals and the Basis of Equality Federico Zuolo Department of Classics, Philosophy and History, University of Genova, via Balbi 30, 16126 Genova, Italy; [email protected] Received: 31 October 2019; Accepted: 27 November 2019; Published: 29 November 2019 Simple Summary: Equal moral worth in animal ethics is an elusive moral notion not only because of the notorious human prejudice but also because grounding equal moral worth requires attending to the problem of the basis of equality. How can we ground equality given that all human and nonhuman individuals vary in all the morally considerable features? John Rawls claimed that we can use range properties, namely properties that are equally possessed by all people who pass a certain threshold of moral relevance (e.g., the age of majority gives equal right to vote). In this paper, I critically discuss two different attempts to defend an egalitarian theory in animal ethics: Alasdair Cochrane’s and Peter Singer’s. The former seeks to eschew the problem of range properties by appealing to a binary property naturally possessed by all sentient beings (the property of having interests). His attempt fails because this property has the same problems as range properties. The latter dispenses with equal moral worth altogether by defending the principle of equal consideration of interests. I argue that this principle has weak egalitarian credentials. I conclude by outlining the conditions that a sound theory in animal ethics should meet. Abstract: This paper aims to put in question the all-purposes function that sentience has come to play in animal ethics.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Welfare and the Paradox of Animal Consciousness
    ARTICLE IN PRESS Animal Welfare and the Paradox of Animal Consciousness Marian Dawkins1 Department of Zoology, University of Oxford, Oxford, UK 1Corresponding author: e-mail address: [email protected] Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Animal Consciousness: The Heart of the Paradox 2 2.1 Behaviorism Applies to Other People Too 5 3. Human Emotions and Animals Emotions 7 3.1 Physiological Indicators of Emotion 7 3.2 Behavioral Components of Emotion 8 3.2.1 Vacuum Behavior 10 3.2.2 Rebound 10 3.2.3 “Abnormal” Behavior 10 3.2.4 The Animal’s Point of View 11 3.2.5 Cognitive Bias 15 3.2.6 Expressions of the Emotions 15 3.3 The Third Component of Emotion: Consciousness 16 4. Definitions of Animal Welfare 24 5. Conclusions 26 References 27 1. INTRODUCTION Consciousness has always been both central to and a stumbling block for animal welfare. On the one hand, the belief that nonhuman animals suffer and feel pain is what draws many people to want to study animal welfare in the first place. Animal welfare is seen as fundamentally different from plant “welfare” or the welfare of works of art precisely because of the widely held belief that animals have feelings and experience emotions in ways that plants or inanimate objectsdhowever valuableddo not (Midgley, 1983; Regan, 1984; Rollin, 1989; Singer, 1975). On the other hand, consciousness is also the most elusive and difficult to study of any biological phenomenon (Blackmore, 2012; Koch, 2004). Even with our own human consciousness, we are still baffled as to how Advances in the Study of Behavior, Volume 47 ISSN 0065-3454 © 2014 Elsevier Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics Beyond Sentience Matthew Ip Analto Eastern Kentucky University
    Volume 1 Nature's Humans Article 6 2016 Ethics Beyond Sentience Matthew iP analto Eastern Kentucky University Follow this and additional works at: https://encompass.eku.edu/tcj Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Pianalto, Matthew (2016) "Ethics Beyond Sentience," The Chautauqua Journal: Vol. 1 , Article 6. Available at: https://encompass.eku.edu/tcj/vol1/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Encompass. It has been accepted for inclusion in The hC autauqua Journal by an authorized editor of Encompass. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Pianalto: Ethics Beyond Sentience MATTHEW PIANALTO ETHICS BEYOND SENTIENCE To whom—or what—do we owe basic acknowledgment, respect, and consideration? To whom—or what—do we have those basic obligations? These are the questions I wish to probe in this essay. They are questions that can seem to require the drawing of lines, the identification of criteria that make some beings “morally considerable” while other beings do not warrant this kind of special moral attention. Such questions have received a great deal of attention from moral philosophers, and have generated many very different responses, ranging from views that regard human beings as sole possessors of this special property of moral considerability to views that attribute this feature to every corner of existence. Views of the latter sort will strike some as silly—overly romantic perhaps, and because of this, largely impractical. I am nevertheless often attracted to such views for the potential power they have to stimulate moral imagination. Such views ask us to move beyond human-centered ways of thinking about ethics and obligations, to see our responsibilities extending beyond the effects of our actions on our fellow humans.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Behave in a Beehive Eusociality, What Is It? the Colony
    1/6-2017 How to behave in a beehive Krisztina Csiki Popular scientific review of Independent Project in Biology 2017 Biology Education Centre, Uppsala University Did you know that the European honeybee has other interesting properties besides producing honey? It is a widely studied insect today, but the fascination goes back to the19th century and Sir Charles Darwin. So what is this fascination about? They have a strange genetic makeup which is very different from ours. How can a female be more related to her sister than to her offspring, and why are some individuals sterile? Moreover, some bees seem to work every waking hour while others spend their time doing practically nothing! Eusociality, what is it? Honeybees are social animals. However, their social system is organized in a different fashion than ours. Eusociality is in fact the most advanced social system known in the animal kingdom! What makes it special is that it is made up of large colonies where the tasks of guarding, nursing, foraging and reproducing are divided amongst its members. Individuals are usually born into performing particular tasks and are unable to change this. Moreover, at least some members in these systems are sterile, and others help the reproducers to nurse offspring. Many theories have tried to explaining this behaviour. They all hope to answer the question why sterile individuals have evolved. The most famous theory is called kin selection, which is a modification of Darwin’s theory. It suggests that the gene - rather than the individual itself - is the fundamental unit of selection. It is thus the gene that “wants” to survive.
    [Show full text]
  • The Strange Survival and Apparent Resurgence of Sociobiology
    This is a repository copy of The strange survival and apparent resurgence of sociobiology. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/118157/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Dennis, A. orcid.org/0000-0003-4625-1123 (2018) The strange survival and apparent resurgence of sociobiology. History of the Human Sciences, 31 (1). pp. 19-35. ISSN 0952- 6951 https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695117735966 Dennis A. The strange survival and apparent resurgence of sociobiology. History of the Human Sciences. 2018;31(1):19-35. Copyright © 2017 The Author(s). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0952695117735966. Article available under the terms of the CC- BY-NC-ND licence (https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/). Reuse This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs (CC BY-NC-ND) licence. This licence only allows you to download this work and share it with others as long as you credit the authors, but you can’t change the article in any way or use it commercially. More information and the full terms of the licence here: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ The strange survival and apparent resurgence of sociobiology Abstract A recent dispute between Richard Dawkins and Edward O. Wilson concerning fundamental concepts in sociobiology is examined.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning Vs. Instinct *Dichotomy = Two-Part Classification
    8/28/2012 The Study of Behavior Humans vs. Animals Historical Background Descarte in 1600’s: animal’s behavior governed Shakespeare on solely by the laws of Instincts physics, “I’ll never be such a whereas human beings had a gosling to obey instinct, soul, which was thought to but stand as if a man reside in the pineal gland ... were author of himself and knew no other kin.” Humans, unlike animals, had -- Corolianus , ca. 1608 free will. The learning-instinct dichotomy Cartesians created a dichotomy* : Eventually known that animals could humans as reasoning beings learn, and behavior still pitched as: vs. animals as automata learning vs. instinct *dichotomy = two-part classification 1 8/28/2012 Evolution by Use and Disuse Lamarck on Instincts “…the continued use of any organ leads to its development, strengthens it, and even enlarges it, “ “By instinct is meant the fixed tendencies displayed by animals in while permanent disuse of any organ is their actions; injurious to its development, causes it to deteriorate and ultimately disappear if and many people have held that these the disuse continues for a long period tendencies are the produce of a reasoned choice, through successive generations.” J-B. de Lamarck and therefore the fruit of experience.” Philosophie Zoologique (1809) Will body-building cause one’s children Problem with Lamarck’s Theory to be more muscular from birth? ◊ Required effects of environment on non- reproductive tissue be transmitted to NO! DNA in gametes ◊ ‘Refuted’ by August Weismann in early 1900’s 2 8/28/2012 Charles Darwin, 1809-1882 ◊ Dropped out of medical school ◊ Studied theology at Cambridge ◊ Held lifelong interest in nature 1831-1836 Naturalist aboard the H.M.S.
    [Show full text]
  • Sociobiology
    SOCIOBIOLOGY C. George Boeree Ever since Darwin came out with his theory of evolution, people - including Darwin himself -- have been speculating on how our social behaviors (and feelings, attitudes, and so on) might also be affected by evolution. After all, if the way our bodies look and work as biological creatures can be better understood through evolution, why not the things we do with those bodies? The entemologist E. O Wilson was the first to formalize the idea that social behavior could be explained evolutionarily, and he called his theory sociobiology. At first, it gained attention only in biological circles -- even there it had strong critics. When sociologists and psychologists caught wind of it, the controversy really got started. At that time, sociology was predominantly structural-functionalist, with a smattering of Marxists and feminists. Psychology was still dominated by behaviorist learning theory, with humanism starting to make some headway. Not one of these theories has much room for the idea that we, as human beings, could be so strongly determined by evolutionary biology! Over time, Wilson's sociobiology found more and more supporters among biologists, psychologists, and even anthropologists. Only sociology has remained relatively unaffected. Instinct Let's begin with an example of instinctual behavior in animals: The three- spined stickleback is a one-inch long fish that one can find in the rivers and lakes of Europe. Springtime is, as you might expect, the mating season for the mighty stickleback and the perfect time to see instincts in action. Certain changes occur in their appearances: The male, normally dull, becomes red above the midline.
    [Show full text]
  • Fish Pain: a Painful Topic
    Safina, Carl (2016) Fish pain: A painful topic. Animal Sentience 3(41) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1076 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Animal Sentience 2016.066: Safina Commentary on Key on Fish Pain Fish pain: A painful topic Commentary on Key on Fish Pain Carl Safina Marine & Atmospheric Sciences Stony Brook University Abstract: If fish cannot feel pain, why do stingrays have purely defensive tail spines that deliver venom? Stingrays’ ancestral predators are fish. And why do many fishes possess defensive fin spines, some also with venom that produces pain in humans? These things did not evolve just in case sentient humans would evolve millions of years later and then invent scuba. If fish react purely unconsciously to “noxious” stimuli, why aren’t sharp jabbing spines enough? Why also stinging venom? Carl Safina [email protected] is the inaugural endowed professor for nature and humanity at Stony Brook University, where he co-chairs the Alan Alda Center for Communicating Science and is founding president of the not-for-profit Safina Center. Beyond Words: What Animals Think and Feel is Carl’s seventh book. http://safinacenter.org/about-carl-safina/ Key (2016) seems an excellent neurobiologist, but he is less convincing as a logician. He launches with the seemingly inarguable truism that to address whether fish can feel pain, “it is necessary to first understand the neural basis of pain in humans, since it is the only species able to directly report on its feelings.” But no logic supports this conflation of pain and human speech.
    [Show full text]
  • Fish Sentience Denial: Muddying the Waters
    Sneddon, Lynne U.; Lopez-Luna, Javier; Wolfenden, David C.C.; Leach, Matthew C.; Valentim, Ana M.; Steenbergen, Peter J.; Bardine, Nabila; Currie, Amanda D.; Broom, Donald M.; and Brown, Culum (2018) Fish sentience denial: Muddying the waters. Animal Sentience 21(1) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1317 This article has appeared in the journal Animal Sentience, a peer-reviewed journal on animal cognition and feeling. It has been made open access, free for all, by WellBeing International and deposited in the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Sneddon, Lynne U.; Lopez-Luna, Javier; Wolfenden, David C.C.; Leach, Matthew C.; Valentim, Ana M.; Steenbergen, Peter J.; Bardine, Nabila; Currie, Amanda D.; Broom, Donald M.; and Brown, Culum (2018) Fish sentience denial: Muddying the waters. Animal Sentience 21(1) DOI: 10.51291/2377-7478.1317 Authors Lynne U. Sneddon, Javier Lopez-Luna, David C.C. Wolfenden, Matthew C. Leach, Ana M. Valentim, Peter J. Steenbergen, Nabila Bardine, Amanda D. Currie, Donald M. Broom, and Culum Brown This article is available in Animal Sentience: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/ animsent/vol3/iss21/1 Animal Sentience 2018.115: Sneddon et al. on Sentience Denial Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been reviewed, revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. Instructions: animalstudiesrepository.org/animsent/guidelines.html Fish sentience denial: Muddying the waters Lynne U.
    [Show full text]