Augustine on the Image of God: an Ethical Analysis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Augustine on the Image of God: an Ethical Analysis Augustine On the Image of God: An Ethical Analysis Matthew W. Puffer Charlottesville, Virginia Bachelor’s of Science, North Carolina State University, 1999 Master’s of Divinity, Princeton Theological Seminary, 2009 A Dissertation presented to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Virginia in Candidacy for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Religious Studies University of Virginia August 2014 © Matthew W. Puffer For Becca, Will, and Kate Table of Contents iii Abstract v Introduction 1 In the beginning of evil was the lie The history and method of the project How to read Augustine on the image of God Part I. Augustine on the Image of God I.1 Before Genesis: The image of God and the rational soul (386-388) 18 I.2 Turning Toward the Image of God in Genesis (388-390) 30 I.3 Augustine’s Priesthood: On Genesis, the beatitudes, and Romans (391-395) 42 Excursus: A late addendum to De Genesi ad litteram liber inperfectus Beatitudes as eights steps in moral progress Four stages of humanity in Romans I.4 The Bishop of Hippo Confesses a New Image of the Trinity (396-400) 65 The image of Caesar and the image of God I.5 The Image of the Trinity and the Image of God in Christ (401-412) 72 The image of God lost and found I.6 The Image of God in Five Trinities and Four Stages (413-426) 92 The trinities of the outer human The trinities of the inner human: scientia and sapientia Two trinities of faith Image of God as activity Image of God as capacity Interpreting the image of God in eight biblical texts I.7 Distinguishing Citizenships: Election and the image of the Son (420-430) 120 I.8 Seven Developments in Augustine’s imago dei (396-430) 125 Part II. Ethics after the Image of God II.1 Introduction: The Problem of Augustine’s Ethics 133 Lying and killing in Augustine’s ethics The Augustinian image of God and religious ethics today The image of God in Augustine’s ethics The image of God in Scriptural texts on lying Table of Contents iv II.2 Lying After the Image of God: De Trinitate 15 154 The analogy between the rational soul and the Trinity: Its basis and limits Immanent Trinitarian processions and the economic Christological mission The Trinitarian pre-linguistic “yes, yes; no, no” The Christological sign-assuming “yes, yes; no, no” Inseparable operations of the image of God ad extra Ignorance, errors, and lies: Finite knowledge, flawed intellect, and evil will Ignorance: Creaturely finitude of knowledge Errors: Unknowingly willing false words Lies: Knowing and willing false words Divine omniscience, simplicity, and omnipotence Exercising the image of God II.3 Retracing Augustine’s Ethics of Lying 191 Escaping deception and attaining perfection via steps and stages Mt 5.37 and the ethics of swearing Mt 5.37 and six theses on lying Mt 5.37 in Christology and Scripture Revisiting swearing: Moral dilemmas and outdoing murderers Reframing lying in ecclesial and political contexts Comparing lies: Priscillianist heresy and Catholic blasphemy Comparing lies: Egypt, Jericho, and the heavenly Jerusalem Laurentius: The necessity of error II.4 Three Stages in Augustine’s Moral Reasoning about Lying 252 The early ethics: Lying as imperfection in virtue The later ethics: Lying, error, and necessity De Trinitate 15: Lying as the origin of evil in the rational soul Conclusion 266 Defining the lie and the voluntate fallendi The limits of necessity An Augustinian account of the image of God for today Appendices 286 A: References to the image of God in Augustine’s writings B: Augustine’s image of God in five trinities and four stages C: Scriptural texts cited by Augustine in his primary expositions of lying D: Scriptural texts cited by Augustine more than once in expositions of lying E: Citations of Mt 5.37 by year Bibliography 297 v Abstract This dissertation addresses two questions: First, “What is the image of God for Augustine?” Second, “What are its ethical implications?” Part I addresses the first question by tracing the development of the image of God from Augustine’s first extant writings in 386 to his death in 430. Part II demonstrates how Augustine’s developing conception of the image of God informs the moral reasoning operative in his ethics. Part I argues three main points through an exposition of the historical development of image of God throughout Augustine’s writings. First, and most basically, Augustine’s conception of the image of God changes over the course of his writing career in ways significantly more nuanced and substantial than has been appreciated in previous scholarship. Second, the shifts in Augustine’s presentations of the image of God are evident in the alternative ways that he interprets a small number of biblical texts to which he repeatedly returns in advancing particular claims about the image of God. Third, each of seven developments in Augustine’s evolving accounts of the image of God can be traced to his interpretation of one or more of this small selection of biblical texts. In short, Augustine’s understanding of the image of God changes over time and the developments are justified in large part by his exegesis of specific biblical texts. Part II argues that the development of the image of God traced in Part I holds explanatory power for interpreting and arbitrating disputes about Augustine’s ethics. First, a close reading of De Trinitate 15 shows how Trinitarian and Christological reflection upon the image of God informs the late ethics of lying such that lying becomes the ethical issue par excellence in Augustine’s mature conception of the image of God. Second, a chronological examination of earlier expositions of lying manifests other developments in Augustine’s ethical thought. I tease out three distinct stages in the moral reasoning about lying that map onto developments observed regarding the image of God. At each stage several comparisons highlight the distinct features of Augustine’s ethics of lying at that point in its development—comparisons with his contemporaneous accounts of the image of God, with other ethical issues addressed in his writings, and with the ethic detailed in the other stages. Through this theological, historical, comparative analysis, Part II argues that recognizing developments in Augustine’s account of the image of God contributes toward identifying corresponding developments in his ethics. In short, understanding the historical development of the image of God in Augustine’s thought is necessary in order to explain features of his ethics that current scholarship elides as well as the ways in which the ethics of lying is (and is not) analogous to the ethics of swearing and coercion. Introduction 1 From the first days of his conversion to Christianity Augustine had instilled in him a deep and abiding interest in the image of God that would only increase over his forty-five year writing career.1 In total, more than five hundred explicit references to the image and likeness of God appear across more than one hundred fifty of Augustine’s treatises, sermons, and letters.2 Within the confines of this project it is not possible to address all of them, nor would it be desirable to do so. Many are mere allusions of little consequence and, as one would expect, there are many redundancies.3 Instead of an exhaustive treatment, I offer an interpretation of the development of Augustine’s thought that highlights the emergence of various conceptualizations and distinctions within his innovative and influential expositions of the image of God. This method of presentation 1 Augustine’s early interpretation of the image of God and its development are indebted to Ambrose, Origen, Plotinus, Simplicianus, Theodorus, and Marcellus Victorinus, among others. In what respects each has played a role remains of significant interest in Augustine scholarship today as evidenced by the major reassessment of the role of neo- Platonism in Augustine’s thought by self-proclaimed “New Canon” of Lewis Ayres, Michel Barnes, Luigi Gioia, Rowan Williams, and others. Assessments of Augustine’s indebtedness to the aforementioned figures include J. Heijke, “The Image of God According to Saint Augustine,” Studies in the Christian Perpetuation of the Classics (1956): 3-11; H. Somers, “Image de Dieu: Les sources de l’exégèse augustienne” Revue des études augustiniennes 7:2 (1961): 105-125; Gerald A. McCool, “The Ambrosian Origin of St. Augustine’s Theology of the Image of God in Man,” Theological Studies (1959): 62-81; R.A. Markus, “‘Imago’ and ‘similitudo’ in Augustine,” Revue des études augustiniennes (1963): 125-143; Gerald Bonner, “Augustine’s Doctrine of Man: Image of God and Sinner,” Augustinianum 24 (1984): 495-514; Roland J. Teske, “The Image and Likeness of God in St. Augustine’s De Genesi ad litteram liber imperfectus,” Augustinianum 30:2 (1990): 441-451; Teske, “Origen and St. Augustine's First Commentaries on Genesis,” Origeniana Quinta (1992): 179-185; György Heidl, Origen’s Influence on the Young Augustine: A Chapter of the History of Origenism (Piscataway, N.J.: Gorgias Press, 2003); Lewis Ayres, Augustine and the Trinity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010); Luigi Gioia, The Theological Epistemology of Augustine’s De Trinitate (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008); and Gerald Boersma, “The Context of Augustine’s Early Theology of the Imago Dei” PhD Thesis, Durham University, 2013. 2 See Appendix A. 3 Where I treat claims by Augustine about the image of God that are substantiated or corroborated in contemporaneous texts, I provide additional citations in the footnotes. Introduction 2 aims to elucidate Augustine’s mature understanding of the image of God—what it is and how it evolves—by attending not only to the increasing specificity Augustine gives to this concept but also to the particular reasons and interesting ways in which his mind changed.4 Not long ago scholars could write of Augustine that “it is reasonable to regard his opinions on most theological issues as having been established by the time he became sole bishop of Hippo in 396.”5 Careful attention to Augustine’s expositions of biblical 4 For the dating of Augustine’s works, consult the Zentrum für Augustinus-Forschung and the Augustinus-Lexikon, ed.
Recommended publications
  • Retracing Augustine's Ethics: Lying, Necessity, and the Image Of
    Valparaiso University ValpoScholar Christ College Faculty Publications Christ College (Honors College) 12-1-2016 Retracing Augustine’s Ethics: Lying, Necessity, and the Image of God Matthew Puffer Valparaiso University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.valpo.edu/cc_fac_pub Recommended Citation Puffer, M. (2016). "Retracing Augustine’s ethics: Lying, necessity, and the image of God." Journal of Religious Ethics, 44(4), 685–720. https://doi.org/10.1111/jore.12159 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Christ College (Honors College) at ValpoScholar. It has been accepted for inclusion in Christ College Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of ValpoScholar. For more information, please contact a ValpoScholar staff member at [email protected]. RETRACING AUGUSTINE’S ETHICS Lying, Necessity, and the Image of God Matthew Puffer ABSTRACT Augustine’s exposition of the image of God in Book 15 of On The Trinity (De Trinitate) sheds light on multiple issues that arise in scholarly interpretations of Augustine’s account of lying. This essay argues against interpretations that pos- it a uniform account of lying in Augustine—with the same constitutive features, and insisting both that it is never necessary to tell a lie and that lying is abso- lutely prohibited. Such interpretations regularly employ intertextual reading strategies that elide distinctions and developments in Augustine’sethicsoflying. Instead, I show how looking at texts written prior and subsequent to the texts usually consulted suggests a trajectory in Augustine’s thought, beginning with an understanding of lies as morally culpable but potentially necessary, and cul- minating in a vision of lying as the fundamental evil and the origin of every sin.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2011 The rP oblem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions Edward Matusek University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Matusek, Edward, "The rP oblem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions" (2011). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3733 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Problem of Evil in Augustine’s Confessions by Edward A. Matusek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Charles B. Guignon, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 14, 2011 Keywords: theodicy, privation, metaphysical evil, Manichaeism, Neo-Platonism Copyright © 2011, Edward A. Matusek i TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iii Chapter One: Introduction to Augustine’s Confessions and the Present Study 1 Purpose and Background of the Study 2 Literary and Historical Considerations of Confessions 4 Relevance of the Study for Various
    [Show full text]
  • New American Commentary Joshua 2
    New American Commentary1 Joshua 2 Side Remark: On Rahab's Lie A troublesome aspect of the Rahab story for many people is that she apparently uttered a bold- faced lie by telling the king of Jericho's messengers that the Israelite spies had fled when in fact they were hiding in her own house (Josh 2:4), and she was never censured for it. In fact, she and her family were spared by the Israelites (Josh 6:25) and the New Testament twice commends her in very glowing terms (Heb 11:31; Jas 2:25). How could she have been accorded such a positive treatment in the face of this lie that she told? Generations of Christian ethicists have considered Rahab's case carefully in constructing broader systems of ethics. In her case, two absolute principles of moral behavior seem to have come into conflict: (1) the principle that it is wrong to tell a lie and (2) the principle that one must protect human life. In Rahab's case, it appears that, in order to save the spies’ life, she had no alternative but to lie. Or, conversely, had she told the truth and revealed the spies’ position, their lives would most likely have been forfeited and Israel's inheritance of the land may have been jeopardized. Generally, orthodox Christian ethicists argue one of three positions concerning situations in which Biblical principles of behavior seem to conflict with each other. The first position involves what many call “conflicting absolutes” or “the lesser of two evils.” Christians holding this position argue that in a fallen world, sometimes two or more absolute principles of moral behavior will conflict absolutely, and that there is no recourse in the situation but to sin.
    [Show full text]
  • Duns Scotus on the Common Nature and the Individual Differentia
    c Peter King, Philosophical Topics 20 (1992), 50–76 DUNS SCOTUS ON THE COMMON NATURE* Introduction COTUS holds that in each individual there is a principle that accounts for its being the very thing it is and a formally S distinct principle that accounts for its being the kind of thing it is; the former is its individual differentia, the latter its common nature.1 These two principles are not on a par: the common nature is prior to the individual differentia, both independent of it and indifferent to it. When the individual differentia is combined with the common nature, the result is a concrete individual that really differs from all else and really agrees with others of the same kind. The individual differentia and the common nature thereby explain what Scotus takes to stand in need of explanation: the indi- viduality of Socrates on the one hand, the commonalities between Socrates * An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 26th International Congress on Medieval Studies, sponsored by the Medieval Institute, held at Western Michigan University 9–12 May 1991. All translations are my own. Scotus’s writings may be found in the following editions: (1) Vaticana: Iohannis Duns Scoti Doctoris Subtilis et Mariani opera omnia, ed. P. Carolus Bali¸cet alii, Typis Polyglottis Vaticanae 1950– Vols. I–VII, XVI–XVIII. (2) Wadding-Viv`es: Joannis Duns Scoti Doctoris Subtilis Ordinis Minorum opera omnia, ed. Luke Wadding, Lyon 1639; republished, with only slight alterations, by L. Viv`es,Paris 1891–1895. Vols. I–XXVI. References are to the Vatican edition wherever possible, to the Wadding-Viv`esedition otherwise.
    [Show full text]
  • The Image of God in Pauline Preaching
    Leaven Volume 16 Issue 2 Creation and New Creation Article 8 1-1-2008 The Image of God in Pauline Preaching Jeffrey Peterson Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.pepperdine.edu/leaven Part of the Biblical Studies Commons, Christianity Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Peterson, Jeffrey (2008) "The Image of God in Pauline Preaching," Leaven: Vol. 16 : Iss. 2 , Article 8. Available at: https://digitalcommons.pepperdine.edu/leaven/vol16/iss2/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Religion at Pepperdine Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Leaven by an authorized editor of Pepperdine Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected], [email protected]. Peterson: The Image of God in Pauline Preaching The Image of God in Pauline Preaching JEFFREY PETERSON he image (eikon) of God is a motif that appears only a few times in Paul's letters; if we judged by frequency of occurrence, we would suppose that it was a minor element in his theology.' To Tconclude thus, however, would be "the substitution of counting for thinking," a fault that Austin Farrer observed even in eminent students of the New Testament.! We can better appreciate the importance of the image of God in Paul's theology when we observe that the contexts in which it appears allude to the instruction preparing converts for baptism that Paul employed in forming messianic communities "from Jerusalem and around as far as Illyricum" (Rom 15.19).3 Seen in the context of his missionary catechesis and his converts' initiation, Paul's appropriation of "the image of God" and related motifs from Gen l.26-28 (and also 5.1-3) expresses fundamental convictions and hopes of believers in Christ.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • The Revelation of God, East and West: Contrasting Special Revelation in Western Modernity with the Ancient Christian East
    Open Theology 2017; 3: 565–589 Analytic Perspectives on Method and Authority in Theology Nathan A. Jacobs* The Revelation of God, East and West: Contrasting Special Revelation in Western Modernity with the Ancient Christian East https://doi.org/10.1515/opth-2017-0043 Received August 11, 2017; accepted September 11, 2017 Abstract: The questions of whether God reveals himself; if so, how we can know a purported revelation is authentic; and how such revelations relate to the insights of reason are discussed by John Locke, Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes, G. W. Leibniz, and Immanuel Kant, to name a few. Yet, what these philosophers say with such consistency about revelation stands in stark contrast with the claims of the Christian East, which are equally consistent from the second century through the fourteenth century. In this essay, I will compare the modern discussion of special revelation from Thomas Hobbes through Johann Fichte with the Eastern Christian discussion from Irenaeus through Gregory Palamas. As we will see, there are noteworthy differences between the two trajectories, differences I will suggest merit careful consideration from philosophers of religion. Keywords: Religious Epistemology; Revelation; Divine Vision; Theosis; Eastern Orthodox; Locke; Hobbes; Lessing; Kant; Fichte; Irenaeus; Cappadocians; Cyril of Alexandria; Gregory Palamas The idea that God speaks to humanity, revealing things hidden or making his will known, comes under careful scrutiny in modern philosophy. The questions of whether God does reveal himself; if so, how we can know a purported revelation is authentic; and how such revelations relate to the insights of reason are discussed by John Locke, Thomas Hobbes, René Descartes, G.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mystical Way of Images and Choice
    THE MYSTICAL WAY OF IMAGES AND CHOICE Annemiek van Campen tASTERN CULTUREAND LIFE-STYLES are in fashion today. The East-- E rand in particular the Buddhism practised in Tibet and Japan-- evokes the esoteric, the mysterious, the mystical. It inspires decorators, cooks and bank-managers. Many people attend Zen courses. One can almost speak of the birth of a Western Zen Buddhism, marked by a striking emphasis on simplicity, on emptiness, on not-thinking. Buddhist-Christian dialogue takes on something of the same quality. It seems to centre on the concepts of 'emptiness', 'quiet' and 'non- being'--concepts that seem to attract and intrigue people today. There are indeed Christian mystics who have experienced God as 'non- being'; classic examples are Meister Eckhart, Jan van Ruusbroec and John of the Cross. Their writings are a major resource for the Christian side in this dialogue. They speak of their experience of God's utter reality in terms of not knowing and of negativity. They are constantly saying that God is 'not this' and also 'not that'; for them God surpasses all that is definite or definable. Ignatius Loyola does not normally appear in this company. In Buddhist-Christian dialogue, he seems to have nothing to say. One reason for this is that Ignatius' mystical life has often been misunderstood, as many of the other essays in this collection illustrate. Another is that he makes such abundant use of the imagination in the Spiritual Exercises; his spirituality seems to stress a this-worldly choice ('election'). Such use of the imagination in the process of learning about God is therefore quite different from a non-thinking and imageless approach to the Unknowable.
    [Show full text]
  • Article Review Justice, Rights and Wrongs
    ECCLESIOLOGY Ecclesiology 8 (2012) 235–240 brill.nl/ecso Article Review Justice, Rights and Wrongs Nicholas Sagovsky Liverpool Hope University, Hope Park, Liverpool, L16 9JD, UK [email protected] Nicholas Wolterstorff, Justice, Rights and Wrongs (Princeton, NJ and Woodstock, UK: Princeton University Press, 2008) xiv + 400 pp. £35.00. ISBN 978-0-691-12967-9 (hbk). Nicholas Wolterstorff’s Justice, Rights and Wrongs is a major contribution to the contemporary debate about justice. It is, however, more narrowly focused than the broad brush title would suggest. Wolterstorff’s aim is to show the secure grounds on which a belief in natural rights can be the foun- dation for an understanding of justice: ‘I think of a social order as just’, he writes, ‘insofar as its members enjoy the goods to which they have rights.’ What he does not discuss is how to specify those rights, and how ‘natural rights’ can be deployed in a strategy for justice. The argument is in three parts. First, Wolterstorff examines ‘the archeol- ogy of rights’ to defend the claim that a belief in natural rights is not the product of the possessive individualism associated with the Enlightenment, nor is it the lineal descendent of the nominalism of William of Ockham. He follows Brian Tierney in tracing the line of descent of the notion of ius back to canon lawyers who pre-date Ockham. From there, he traces the pre- history of the notion of ‘right’ back to the Hebrew Scriptures, the New Testament and the early Christian writers. In his second section, Wolterstorff argues that the eudaimonism (belief in the ‘good life’ or ‘human flourishing’), which was central to the thinking of classical philosophers like Aristotle, could never have provided the basis for contemporary belief in universal natural rights.
    [Show full text]
  • A Critical Analysis of Thomas Aquinas's Doctrine of the Image Of
    Damascus University Journal, Vol. 19, No. (3+4), 2003 Sawsan M. Al- Bitar A Critical Analysis of Thomas Aquinas’s Doctrine of the Image of God Dr. Sawsan M. Al- Bitar * Abstract The basic issues of our time concern the spiritual substance of a free society, as it has historically derived from the central Christian concept of the image of God. However, the purpose of this paper is to analyze the meaning of the image of God, and examine this doctrine under two rubrics: natural theology and divine revelation. Such an analytical study would, mainly, rely on the Biblical texts and the Christian literature of the Church Fathers, besides the basic works of St. Thomas Aquinas and other theologians such as John of Damascus, Athanasius, Augustine and Pseudo- Didnysius. *Philosophy Department. Faculty of Arts and Humanities, Damascus University. 17 A Critical Analysis of Thomas Aquinas’s Doctrine of the Image of God Of all the doctrines of St. Thomas Aquinas, there is perhaps none whose present- day significance is greater than that of his teaching that man was made after the image of God. As the late John Courtney Murray put it, “ the basic issues of our time concern the spiritual substance of a free society, as it has historically derived from the central Christian concept, res sacra homo” (We hold These Truths, 1964) . And res sacra homo is another Latin term for imago Dei . Although the doctrine had occupied the attention of Christian thinkers since the days of the Church Fathers, there was by no means a consensus about its meaning.
    [Show full text]
  • The Univocity of Substance and the Formal Distinction of Attributes: the Role of Duns Scotus in Deleuze's Reading of Spinoza Nathan Widder
    parrhesia 33 · 2020 · 150-176 the univocity of substance and the formal distinction of attributes: the role of duns scotus in deleuze's reading of spinoza nathan widder This paper examines the role played by medieval theologian John Duns Scotus in Gilles Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza’s philosophy of expressive substance; more generally, it elaborates a crucial moment in the development of Deleuze’s philosophy of sense and difference. Deleuze contends that Spinoza adapts and extends Duns Scotus’s two most influential theses, the univocity of being and formal distinction, despite neither appearing explicitly in Spinoza’s writings. “It takes nothing away from Spinoza’s originality,” Deleuze declares, “to place him in a perspective that may already be found in Duns Scotus” (Deleuze, 1992, 49).1 Nevertheless, the historiographic evidence is clearly lacking, leaving Deleuze to admit that “it is hardly likely that” Spinoza had even read Duns Scotus (359n28). Indeed, the only support he musters for his speculation is Spinoza’s obvious in- terests in scholastic metaphysical and logical treatises, the “probable influence” of the Scotist-informed Franciscan priest Juan de Prado on his thought, and the fact that the problems Duns Scotus addresses need not be confined to Christian thought (359–360n28). The paucity of evidence supporting this “use and abuse” of history, however, does not necessarily defeat the thesis. Like other lineages Deleuze proposes, the one he traces from Duns Scotus to Spinoza, and subsequently to Nietzsche, turns not on establishing intentional references by one thinker to his predecessor, but instead on showing how the borrowings and adaptations asserted to create the connec- tion make sense of the way the second philosopher surmounts blockages he faces while responding to issues left unaddressed by the first.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue and Happiness: a Philosophical Inquiry
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Wits Institutional Repository on DSPACE VIRTUE AND HAPPINESS: A PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY Muhammad Assadallah Schuitema 320900 A Research Report submitted to the Faculty of Humanities, University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, Applied Ethics for Professionals University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg, 16th March 2015 1 Abstract The position that holds that virtue, as a good, is sufficient for happiness has had illustrious exponents in the past. We will refer to this position as the sufficiency thesis. In recent times however this position has fallen into disfavour. This is largely due to the strong intuition that certain goods other than virtue are necessary for happiness. We will refer to this as the problem of external goods. The point of this paper is to respond to the problem of external goods by articulating an understanding of virtue as involving the ability to occupy a “distanced perspective” within which the virtuous agent becomes detached from external goods insofar as he comes to view them as indifferent. My articulation of this understanding of virtue will be based upon what I take to be the core of the Stoic description of virtue. 2 Declaration I declare that this research report is my own unaided work. It is submitted for the degree of Master of Arts in the University of the Witwatersrand, Johannesburg. It has not been submitted before for any other degree or examination in any other university.
    [Show full text]