Mark Cowling: the Dialectic in Marx and Hegel – an Outline

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Mark Cowling: the Dialectic in Marx and Hegel – an Outline Mark Cowling: The Dialectic in Marx and Hegel – an Outline. Paper presented to the Marxism panels of the PSA annual conference, Brighton, March 21-23rd 2016. Abstract This paper offers an outline of the relationship between the dialectic in Hegel and Marx. It identifies four major forms of the dialectic in Hegel. These are, most importantly, the dialectic of method, meaning the dialectical development of categories; the dialectic of historical development through human intellectual labour, and the conception of the social totality which results from this; the dialectic of the concrete real, as found particularly in Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature, and finally the dialectic of human physical labour. I then look briefly at the major forms of the dialectic in Marx. In order to do this it is necessary to divide Marx’s work into periods. I discuss the extent to which the dialectic in Marx is derived from that of Hegel. I conclude that the only part of Hegel’s dialectic which is significant in the older Marx is his dialectic of method, which suggested a scientific method to Marx. Introduction. Before going on to the main discussion, I shall give a brief account of how not to analyse the relationship between the dialectic in Hegel and that in Marx. The 1960s were characterised by an upsurge in interest in Marx’s writings in the West, notably by an interest in Marx’s Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (EPM), which, in turn, was linked to a desire to distance Western Marxism from the legacy of Stalinism. One of the figures who took this approach was the French philosopher Roger Garaudy. In his account of the dialectic, to be found in his book Karl Marx – The Evolution of His Thought (Garaudy, 1964). Garaudy simply assumes that everything that Marx and Engels said at any time is valuable. He has a simplistic approach to Marx’s own statements about the relationship between his dialectic and that of Hegel. All he can come up with by taking this approach is vague generalisations: ‘Dialectics is primarily a logic of relationship. Dialectics is a logic of conflict… Dialectics is a logic of motion… Dialectics is a logic of life.’ (pp. 91-3). He also entangles himself in logical contradictions. He seems to both assert and deny that there can be a dialectics of nature. He says that dialectical thinking could not enable us to ‘understand a being not like it to any degree’ (p. 97), but also that Marxism is a ‘materialist method enabling us to grasp again the meaning of things’ (p. 82, cf. p. 134). Again, he asserts that Marx regarded the idea of the immediate reflection of the real world as the most valuable achievement of Feuerbach’s materialism (p. 85), and also says that in Capital Marx “retained (from Hegel) the movement of thought passing from the abstract to the concrete’ (p. 130). In other words we should and should not begin from the concrete-real. (In what follows I shall use the term concrete- real to refer to the material world, the tangible, the kickable. I recognise, of course, that this formula is simplistic, given that many of the concepts we used to grasp the concrete-real are highly theoretical, such as, for example, the idea of dark matter.) As a member of the PCF, Garaudy was committed to the idea that Marx’s writings are important and can provide the basis for action. In doing this it seems to me that he was laying himself and the PCF open to ridicule. I shall now set about trying to give a more precise account of the relationship, focusing particularly but not exclusively on the dialectic in Capital. The overall intentions of Hegel’s philosophy. Most books about Hegel are also, and not surprisingly, books about Hegel’s intentions. Raymond Plant’s approach to this makes a great deal of sense (Plant, 2011). He sees Hegel as attempting a solution to the problem of uniting men in society and the different areas of collective and individual life. The problem of uniting the differing areas of human life was a widespread one amongst the German intellectuals of the early 19th century. The division of labour which accompanied the rise of capitalism was seen as making people less than fully human, and also as isolating individuals from one another, tied only by the depersonalised link of market forces. German thinkers were also troubled by the disunity of Germany itself – a land united in language and culture but divided into many small principalities. A variety of solutions to this problem were proposed. Herder, Hölderlin, Schiller and Humboldt idealised the integrated life of the ancient Greek city states. Fichte and Kant favoured harmony in nature, whilst Novalis favoured mediaeval Christianity (Lobkowicz, 1967, pp. 164-5). Capitalism was particularly well developed in lowland Scotland, and the thinkers of the Scottish Enlightenment concerned themselves with the problem of the development of capitalism. German thinkers frequently saw history as comprising three stages: primitive harmony, alienation and division and final reconciliation. The second stage corresponded to the unhappy present. The third stage was at hand. Symptoms were the realisation of the ideals of the Enlightenment in the French revolution and the rise of German philosophy. Seen in this way, the central themes of the work of both Hegel and Marx can be seen as part of the German ideology of the late 18th and early 19th centuries. This search for a solution to disintegration and alienation makes sense of Hegel’s Early Theological Writings (Hegel, 1948). In these he goes through a startling series of religious changes, but these changes have in common a search for a practical solution to the bifurcations and discord of contemporary German life. Around 1800 Hegel started to see philosophy as the solution to bifurcation and discord, and started to lay the foundations of his mature philosophy. Hegel’s mature philosophical system is first seen in his Phenomenology (Phänomenologie des Geistes) of 1807 (Hegel 1931). He sees the process of world history as the gradual reconciliation of opposites, and the unification of Spirit (Geist) with itself in a mediated fashion, and its return from self-alienation. Along with this development goes that of self-consciousness. Spirit is at first a very simple form of consciousness, but becomes increasingly elaborate and all- embracing. The Cunning of Reason enters in that, in pursuing their goals, the individuals and traces of history also play their part – without particularly meaning to – in the development of unified, self-conscious Spirit. Individuals who have a particularly clear sense of a ‘her universal’, though not of the goal of World History itself (which is the Idea), and make it their own purpose, are called World Historical Individuals – examples would be Julius Caesar and Napoleon. At all stages of history and philosophy provides reconciliation through understanding (in the everyday sense rather than the Hegelian one), and religion, art and the state also do so, although each less explicitly than the one before. As Hegel’s philosophy comes at the end of world history up to the present it is actually the culmination of world history. Hegel as a philosophical encyclopaedist. There is a good case to be made for considering Hegel as a philosophical encyclopaedist. He called the version of his system that he used for teaching the Encyclopaedia (see Hegel, 1892, 1970, 1971) and there is much about it that parallels other writers of encyclopaedias in his day. There was a very wide desire for structured knowledge. The scientific books of his day were frequently structured as a progression from simple to complex. The levels which Hegel used in his Philosophy of Nature reflected those of the science of his day. The account here follows that of Petry in his introduction to his translation of Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature (Hegel 1970). Hegel aimed to divide knowledge into levels, hierarchies spheres. Within a sphere there are levels and hierarchies, and spheres of parts of more comprehensive spheres, where they are levels arranged in hierarchies. The biggest sphere is Encyclopaedia itself, which has as levels Logic, Nature and Spirit (Petry/Hegel, 1970, p. 31). According to Petry, the Logic concludes with the Idea, which is the most complex category that Hegel could formulate in this sphere. Hegel then moves on to the next sphere, which is Nature, and starts with its least complex level, space (Petry/Hegel, 1970, p. 45). To some extent, Petry’s version of Hegel regards the relationship between philosophy and the world as a heuristic one. Knowledge would be seen as independent of the world, which the Encyclopaedia helps us to understand. Although I shall be arguing subsequently that the relationship between theory and the real world in Marx’s Capital is of this nature, this is not a plausible account of Hegel’s philosophy. The more plausible view is parallelism – the idea that both Logic and Nature are internally consistent and are part of a united system – they are both fully realised in the Idea. Several commentators take an approach of this sort (see, for example, Mure, 1940, chapter 8; Hyppolite, 1953, pp. 74, 91-2, 129-31, 1969, p. 169; Stirling, 1865,Vol.1, pp. 26-7). In support of this approach, Hegel sees nature as fossilised intelligence, which was a relatively respectable scientific view in the early 19th century. He is clear that his categories are universally present – an example might be Being and Nothing at the beginning of his Logic, but even at the highest stages of the Logic Hegel includes what seems like empirical material (Hegel, 1969, pp.
Recommended publications
  • Anti-Duhring
    Friedrich Engels Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science Written: September 1876 - June 1878; Published: in Vorwärts, Jan 3 1877-July 7 1878; Published: as a book, Leipzig 1878; Translated: by Emile Burns from 1894 edition; Source: Frederick Engels, Anti-Dühring. Herr Eugen Dühring’s Revolution in Science, Progress Publishers, 1947; Transcribed: [email protected], August 1996; Proofed and corrected: Mark Harris 2010. Formerly known as Herr Eugen Dühring's Revolution in Science, Engels’ Anti-Dühring is a popular and enduring work which, as Engels wrote to Marx, was an attempt “to produce an encyclopaedic survey of our conception of the philosophical, natural-science and historical problems.” Marx and Engels first became aware of Professor Dühring with his December 1867 review of Capital, published in Ergänzungsblätter. They exchanged a series of letters about him from January-March 1868. He was largely forgotten until the mid-1870s, at which time Dühring entered Germany's political foreground. German Social-Democrats were influenced by both his Kritische Geschichte der Nationalökonomie und des Sozialismus and Cursus der Philosophie als streng wissenschaftlicher Weltanschauung und Lebensgestaltung. Among his readers were included Johann Most, Friedrich Wilhelm Fritzsche, Eduard Bernstein – and even August Bebel for a brief period. In March 1874, the Social-Democratic Workers’ Party paper Volksstaat ran an anonymous article (actually penned by Bebel) favorably reviewing one of Dühring's books. On both February 1 and April 21, 1875, Liebknecht encouraged Engels to take Dühring head-on in the pages of the Volksstaat. In February 1876, Engels fired an opening salvo with his Volksstaat article “Prussian Vodka in the German Reichstag”.
    [Show full text]
  • Marx and the Foundations of the Critical Theory of Morality and Ethics
    Marx and the Foundations of the Critical Theory of Morality and Ethics Ricardo Brown Epicurus Understanding the Question of Ethics in Marx 1. How are we to understand the ethical content of Marx's work? Is there a socialist ethic or an ethic of socialism? Of course, these are not new questions within the marxist tradition. One hundred years ago, debates over "ethical socialism" coincided with those over accumulation, imperialism, organization and party. Although the question of ethics has been raised most recently by neo-liberal and neo-authoritarian critics, the turn to the question of ethics has not occurred for intellectual reasons. It is occasioned by the passing of state capitalism in the USSR and by the simultaneous critique of the adaptation by the Left of the discursive categories of bourgeois science in the forms of scientific socialism and the science of historical materialism. However, to raise the question of ethics is one thing, but to uncover its location within critical theory is quite another. Broadly speaking, responses to the question of ethics have displayed two theoretical tendencies. In the first tendency, there is a moralization of Marx through the construction of the "young Marx." This tendency identifies the entirety of Marx's critique of morality Copyright © 1999 by Ricardo Brown and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087 Brown 2 with his readings of Hegel and Feuerbach, the assumption being that Marx's critique of morality is restricted to these early works, leaving the impression that his materialism is at best discontinuous from his critique of morality, and, at worst, simply derived from a previous, enlightenment moral theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Review Articles / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 167–210 Karl Marx, Das Kapital. Kritik Der Politischen Ökonomie, Dritter B
    Review Articles / Historical Materialism 15 (2007) 167–210 195 Karl Marx, Das Kapital. Kritik der politischen Ökonomie, Dritter Band, Hamburg 1894, in: Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, Gesamtausgabe (MEGA). Zweite Abteilung, Band 15, hg. von der Internationalen Marx Engels Stiftung Amsterdam. Bearbeitet von Regina Roth, Eike Kopf und Carl-Erich Vollgraf unter Mitwirkung von Gerald Hubmann, mit einer Einführung von Bertram Schefold, Akademie Verlag, Berlin 2004 (XI, 1420 pp. [860 pp. text, 560 pp. apparatus]) Twelve years after Marx’s death and a few months before Fredrick Engels died, the third volume of Marx’s Capital, edited by Engels, appeared in December 1894. Two years later, Eugen von Böhm-Bawerk, a well known representative of the Austrian school of marginalism, published the first comprehensive critique based on all three volumes of Capital. In December 2004, exactly 110 years after Engels’s edition of Capital’s third volume appeared, the same text was published as Volume 15 of the second section of the complete works of Marx and Engels (MEGA). Th is second section contains Capital and the works preparatory to Capital in chronological order. Numerically and chronologically, Volume 15 is the last one of this section.1 Because some earlier volumes are still unpublished, readers have still to wait some time until the second section will be actually complete. For a further critique of Marx, readers of this MEGA volume will not have to wait so long: radically breaking with the new 1993 editorial guidelines of the MEGA, this volume contains a strongly slanted ‘introduction’, written by Bertram Schefold, a neo-Ricardian economist, presenting a devastating critique of Marx as if it were an undisputed judgement of contemporary economic science.
    [Show full text]
  • 6 Marx's Grundrisse and the Ecological Contradictions of Capitalism
    6 Marx’s Grundrisse and the ecological contradictions of capitalism John Bellamy Foster Introduction In The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte Marx famously wrote: ‘Men make their own history, but they do not make it just as they please; they do not make it under circumstances chosen by themselves, but under circum- stances directly encountered, given and transmitted from the past’ (Marx 1979: 103). The material circumstances or conditions that he was referring to here were the product of both natural and social history. For Marx production was a realm of expanding needs and powers. But it was subject at all times to material limits imposed by nature. It was the tragedy of capital that its narrow logic propelled it in an unrelenting assault on both these natural limits and the new social needs that it brought into being. By constantly revolutionizing production capital transformed society, but only by continually alienating natural necessity (conditions of sustainability and reproduction) and human needs. Recent research has revealed that an ecological–materialist critique was embedded in all of Marx’s work from The Economic and Philosophical Manu- scripts of 1844 to his Ethnological Notebooks of the late 1870s to early 1880s (see Burkett 1999; Foster 2000; Dickens 2004). This can be seen in his material- ist conception of nature and history, his theory of alienation (which encom- passed the alienation of nature), his understanding of the labour and production process as the metabolic relation between humanity and nature, and his co- evolutionary approach to society–nature relations. Nevertheless, because Marx’s overall critique of political economy remained unfinished, these and other aspects of his larger materialist conception of nature and history were incompletely developed – even in those works, such as Capital, volume 1, published in his lifetime.
    [Show full text]
  • In Marx's Laboratory
    In Marx’s Laboratory Critical Interpretations of the Grundrisse Edited by Riccardo Bellofijiore, Guido Starosta, and Peter D. Thomas LEIDEN • BOSTON 2013 © 2013 Koninklijke Brill NV ISBN 978-90-04-23676-9 Contents Introduction: In Marx’s Laboratory ........................................................................ 1 Riccardo Bellofijiore, Guido Starosta and Peter D. Thomas Part One: Achievements and Limits of the Grundrisse The Grundrisse after Capital, or How to Re-read Marx Backwards ............. 17 Riccardo Bellofijiore Method: From the Grundrisse to Capital .............................................................. 43 Juan Iñigo Carrera The Four Levels of Abstraction of Marx’s Concept of ‘Capital’. Or, Can We Consider the Grundrisse the Most Advanced Version of Marx’s Theory of Capital? ............................................................................... 71 Roberto Fineschi Part Two: Abstract Labour, Value and Money The Practical Truth of Abstract Labour ................................................................ 101 Christopher J. Arthur Unavoidable Crises: Reflections on Backhaus and the Development of Marx’s Value-Form Theory in the Grundrisse ................................................ 121 Patrick Murray Part Three: The Concept of Capital The Transformation of Money into Capital ......................................................... 149 Martha Campbell The Concept of Capital in the Grundrisse ............................................................ 177 Howard Engelskirchen © 2013 Koninklijke
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Marx's Changing Picture of the End of Capitalism
    Journal of the British Academy, 6, 187–206. DOI https://doi.org/10.5871/jba/006.187 Posted 30 July 2018. © The British Academy 2018 Karl Marx’s changing picture of the end of capitalism Master-Mind Lecture read 21 November 2017 GARETH STEDMAN JONES Fellow of the Academy Abstract: This essay examines three successive attempts Marx made to theorise his conception of the ‘value form’ or the capitalist mode of production. The first in the 1840s ascribed the destruction of an original human sociability to the institution of private property and looked forward to its destruction and transcendence in the coming revolution. This vision was shattered by the disenchanting failure of the 1848 revolutions. The second attempt, belonging to the 1850s and outlined in the Grundrisse, attempted to chart the rise, global triumph, and the ultimate destruction of what Marx called the ‘value form’. Its model of global triumph and final disintegration was inspired by Hegel’s Logic. But the global economic crisis of 1857–8 did not lead to the return of revolution. Marx’s disturbed reaction to this failure was seen in his paranoia about the failure of his Critique of Political Economy (1859). Marx’s third attempt to formulate his critique in Das Kapital in 1867 was much more successful. It was accompanied by a new conception of revolution as a transi­ tional process rather than an event and was stimulated by his participation in the International Working Men’s Association and the accompanying growth of cooper­ atives, trade unions, and a political reform movement culminating in the Reform Bill of 1867.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Marx's Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique
    8 Rethinking Capital in light of the Grundrisse1 Moishe Postone Critical social theory and the contemporary world Critical social theory has not kept pace with the far-reaching global transforma- tions of the past three decades. The intense and fruitful revival of Marxian thought and scholarship in the 1960s and early 1970s was followed by a very strong turn away from Marxism on the part of many theorists. The intellectual field became dominated by postmodernist and poststructuralist approaches that appeared plausible to many as critiques of Marxism. It has become increasingly evident, however, that such approaches do not adequately grasp the current epoch; they fail to elucidate the basic historical changes that have reconfigured the world in recent decades. Even major thinkers such as Habermas, Foucault and Derrida now appear as theorists of a fading historical configuration – declin- ing Fordism; their critical approaches illuminate less and less of the contempor- ary social universe. One obvious weakness of these post-Marxist discourses has been the absence of serious political–economic considerations, an absence that has become glaring in the face of processes of globalization. At the same time, it is clear that, however important integrating political–economic considerations into crit- ical theories of the present might be, there can be no plausible return to tradi- tional Marxism. That traditional critical framework failed to provide the basis for an adequate historical analysis of Communist regimes of accumulation; its political–economic assumptions were challenged on the basis of the growing importance of scientific knowledge and advanced technology in the process of production; and its emancipatory ideals have become increasingly remote from the themes of much current social and cultural dissatisfaction.
    [Show full text]
  • Karl Marx's Outline of the Critique of Political Economy (Grundrisse)
    Karl Marx’s Outline of the Critique of Political Economy (Grundrisse) Karl Marx 1859 A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy Preface Source: K. Marx, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, Progress Publishers, Moscow, 1977, with some notes by R. Rojas. I examine the system of bourgeois economy in the following order: capital, landed property, wage-labour; the State, foreign trade, world market. The economic conditions of existence of the three great classes into which modern bourgeois society is divided are analysed under the first three headings; the interconnection of the other three headings is self-evident. The first part of the first book, dealing with Capital, comprises the following chapters: 1. The commodity, 2. Money or simple circulation; 3. Capital in general. The present part consists of the first two chapters. The entire material lies before me in the form of monographs, which were written not for publication but for self-clarification at widely separated periods; their remoulding into an integrated whole according to the plan I have indicated will depend upon circumstances. A general introduction, which I had drafted, is omitted, since on further consideration it seems to me confusing to anticipate results which still have to be substantiated, and the reader who really wishes to follow me will have to decide to advance from the particular to the general. A few brief remarks regarding the course of my study of political economy are appropriate here. Although I studied jurisprudence, I pursued it as a subject subordinated to philosophy and history. In the year 1842-43, as editor of the Rheinische Zeitung, I first found myself in the embarrassing position of having to discuss what is known as material interests.
    [Show full text]
  • Engels's Anti-Dühring As Marxist Philosophy. Critique, 45
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Northumbria Research Link Citation: Blackledge, Paul (2017) Practical Materialism: Engels’s Anti-Dühring as Marxist Philosophy. Critique, 45 (4). pp. 483-499. ISSN 0301-7605 Published by: Taylor & Francis URL: https://doi.org/10.1080/03017605.2017.1377927 <https://doi.org/10.1080/03017605.2017.1377927> This version was downloaded from Northumbria Research Link: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/40346/ Northumbria University has developed Northumbria Research Link (NRL) to enable users to access the University’s research output. Copyright © and moral rights for items on NRL are retained by the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. Single copies of full items can be reproduced, displayed or performed, and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided the authors, title and full bibliographic details are given, as well as a hyperlink and/or URL to the original metadata page. The content must not be changed in any way. Full items must not be sold commercially in any format or medium without formal permission of the copyright holder. The full policy is available online: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/policies.html This document may differ from the final, published version of the research and has been made available online in accordance with publisher policies. To read and/or cite from the published version of the research, please visit the publisher’s website (a subscription may be required.) Practical Materialism: Engels’s Anti-Dühring as Marxist Philosophy Paul Blackledge Abstract: Frederick Engels’s Anti-Dühring was the most important theoretical response to the emerging reformist tendencies within European socialism in the nineteenth century.
    [Show full text]
  • “Capital”After MEGA: Discontinuities, Interruptions, and New Beginnings Michael Heinrich
    C 1Abstract:The MEGA (the complete edition of all works of Marx C R R I and Engels), which completed its section on „Capital“-editions and I S „Capital“-manuscripts, makes it possible to follow the development S “Capital”after MEGA:I I of Marx’s Critique of Political Economy from 1857 up to 1881. This S S development was not at all a continuous and smooth one. Marx & conceptualized different projects (at first the 6-book plan later the 4-book & plan of „Capital“) and in the 1870s he questioned results about the falling Discontinuities, C C R rate of profit and the theory of crisis that he had come to in his earlier R I manuscript for vol. 3 of „Capital“, written in 1864/65. I T T I I Interruptions, and Q Keywords: Marx’s „Capital“, Value-theory, Crisis-Theory, Law of Q U the Tendency of the Profit-Rate to fall, MEGA U E E / / New Beginnings Fifty years ago, two works were published in France, which greatly Volume 3 / Volume 3 / Issue 3 influenced international discussions on Marx for many years. The first Issue 3 is Althusser’s collection of essays Pour Marx, and the second is the collaborative work of Althusser, Balibar, Establet, Macherey and Rancière Lire le Capital. In particular, it was Althusser’s theory of the noticeable ‘break’ between the young, philosophical and humanistic Marx in the Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts and the more mature scientist of Michael Heinrich Grundrisse and Capital that prompted fierce debate. Regardless of the position taken in this dispute concerning the relationship between his earlier and later work, the later work dedicated to economics, which came into being from 1857, is usually considered as a single unit, but sometimes even as a double unit.
    [Show full text]
  • The Development of Marx's Concept of Alienation: an Introduction
    THE DEVELOPMENT OF MARX'S CONCEPT OF ALIENATION: AN INTRODUCTION Lanny Ace Thompson* University of Kansas MidAmerican Review of Sociology, 1979, Vol. IV, No. 1:23-38 The paper presents an introduction to and summary of the concept of alienation as found in the works of Karl Marx, from a developmental perspective. Five separate works, ranging from his early to later writings, are discussed. Tlie paper argues that Marx's concept of alienation is a continuous clarification and expansion of ideas first put forth in 1844. His development in economics supports and qualifies his assertions of a more philosophical nature. The early and later works should neither be understood as having complete continuity nor complete incompatibility, for the later grew out of the earlier. Beginning with the belated publication of the Economic and Philosophie id Manuscripts oj 1844 (in German, 1939), students and proponents of Marx have disagreed on the correct interpretation of this work in the context of his later writings. Central to this discussion is the debate over the importance of alienation in the whole.of Marx's thought. Some argue that this concept is a philosophical apparition of the young idealist still being persuaded by Hegel, only to be abandoned by the mature, scientific Marx (Hook, 1962; Althusscr, 1970). This point is contested by those holding that this concept is found throughout Marx's writings (Avineri, 1968; McLellan, 1970). Oilman (1971) and, especially, Meszaros (1972) have dispelled the abandonment thesis although it still exists in various forms (LeoGrande, 1977). What is still lacking is a treatment of alienation that clearly outlines a development of Marx's thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Futures of the Lumpenproletariat
    Lumpen: Vagrancies of a Concept from Marx to Fanon (and on) by Bennett Dempsey Carpenter Program in Literature Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Roberto Dainotto, Supervisor ___________________________ Wahneema Lubiano ___________________________ Anne Garréta ___________________________ Nancy Armstrong Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate Program in Literature in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 i v ABSTRACT Lumpen: Vagrancies of a Concept from Marx to Fanon (and on) by Bennett Dempsey Carpenter Graduate Program in Literature Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Roberto Dainotto, Supervisor ___________________________ Wahneema Lubiano ___________________________ Anne Garréta ___________________________ Nancy Armstrong An abstract of a thesis/dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate Program in Literature in the Graduate School of Duke University 2019 Copyright by Bennett Dempsey Carpenter 2019 Abstract This dissertation, Lumpen: Vagrancies of a Concept from Marx to Fanon (and on), tracks the concept of the lumpenproletariat from its coinage by Karl Marx through its reworking by Franz Fanon, the Black Panthers and others in the context of the colonial liberation and Black Power movements, and onwards into contemporary debates about populism, identity, politics, and the end
    [Show full text]