Interview with Graham Harman Man-World Relation Is No Different in Kind from Any Other Relation.” and This to Me Is

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Interview with Graham Harman Man-World Relation Is No Different in Kind from Any Other Relation.” and This to Me Is INTERVIEWS 151 Interview with Graham Harman man-world relation is no different in kind from any other relation.” And this to me is the key. A good example of an R7 philoso- 1) The words ‘realism’ and ‘anti- pher would be Alfred North Whitehead, realism’ are ancient words, almost who does not treat the human-world relation as old as the history of Western phi- as different in ontological kind from that of losophy itself. Yet these are empty raindrops and a wooden roof. There is at concepts if they are not contextual- best a difference in degree between these ized: one has to specify the classes kinds of relations. With Kant, however, it is of objects to which these words re- quite different. Even if we might read Kant fer. So, can you explain on what as an R1 realist who believes very strongly basis you use different approaches in the independence of the thing-in-itself depending on the class of objects from the mind (which is how I read him) he under consideration? still definitely counts as an A7 philosopher for whom the human-world relation is spe- “Realism” obviously has different senses cial, since it mediates all our talk of all other in philosophy, politics, mathematics, the art relations. Whitehead lets us talk straight- of the novel, and in other areas. But we all away about raindrops striking wood, more or less know what it means in philoso- whereas Kant would say even this talk is phy— the commitment to a world existing mediated by the twelve categories of the independently from the mind. understanding as well as space and time, That’s only a rough approximation, of none of them necessarily applicable beyond course. One of the chief merits of Lee Bra- the realm of appearance. ver’s candidly anti-realist masterpiece A The fact that the human-world relation is Thing of This World: A History of Continental not special also has consequences for the Realism is that Braver carefully distinguishes scope of our knowledge. I see all relation as between six possible meanings of realism a matter of translation. There is no possible and their six possible anti-realist counter- direct access to reality that gives us that re- parts (R1-R6 and A1-A6, respectively). This ality in the flesh, without relation or medi- gives Braver a neat technical shorthand that ation. This holds for human knowledge, allows him to say things like “Philosopher X animal awareness, plant life, and even in- combines R1 realism of the external world animate collision. The human mind has no with A3 and A5 antirealist positions on re- especial entanglement in error and no special lated issues,” and so forth. capacity for direct contact with the real. This However, Braver neglects a key seventh is the point where I seem to disagree with realist thesis that in my review of the book I my colleagues Maurizio Ferraris and Markus called R7, with a counterpart antirealist A7. Gabriel, not to mention Quentin Meillas- Thesis R7 would run as follows: “the hu- soux, all of whom seem to hold that realism ISSUE VI – NUMBER 1 – SUMMER 2014 PHILOSOPHICAL READINGS 152 INTERVIEWS also marks an end to the relativity of per- between perspectives than the internal con- spectives. For me, by contrast, realism en- flict within a perspective to measure up to a tails the very opposite: the impossibility of real that eludes it. ever gaining direct knowledge of the world. In analytic philosophy, I believe Nancy Car- twright has said something similar: that she’s 3) Relativism is particularly hard to an ontological realist but a theory anti- refute in ethics. What can be the realist, or something along those lines. consequences of adopting a realist That’s more or less my position as well. perspective, from this point of view? 2) Relativism has often been treated One frequent assumption about realist as an extreme and necessary out- ethics is that it would require the same ob- come of antirealism. Is that so? jective rules to be followed by everyone, And, if not, what is the difference rules somehow grounded in the nature of re- between relativism and antirealism? ality itself— an “ought” grounded in an “is.” This follows the same assumption Allow me to approach this question from found elsewhere in philosophy: namely, that the opposite end instead: anti-relativism has realism does not just mean the existence of a often been treated as a necessary conse- world outside the mind, but also the ability quence of realism! Many people are moved of the mind to know it. to pursue a realist ontology precisely be- But this is a counter-philosophical atti- cause what they worry about most is relativ- tude from the start. Philosophy is phi- ism. Personally, I’m a lot more worried by losophia, or love of wisdom rather than wis- idealism than by relativism. A certain plu- dom itself. Note that Socrates is never able rality of perspectives is inevitable. Indeed, to give us a definition of friendship, justice, realism requires this if we allow that the real virtue, or love, however much he searches can never be equalled or exhausted by any for one. Socrates is not a knower, and we do particular perspective. not escape sophistry through knowledge One of my most observant readers, Jo- claims. seph Goodson of Michigan, has noted the So in a sense, I conclude the opposite of following difference between my position what your question might have suspected. and postmodern relativism. The relativists For me, a realist ethics entails the failure of are all hung up on the incommensurability of objective rules of behavior. Any ethical rule perspectives with each other, while for me can be no more than a rough approximation this is uninteresting, and the real problem is of the reality it attempts to address. Such ap- the incommensurability of any perspective proximation is necessary for social exist- with the real. It’s less a matter of the conflict ence— we can’t necessarily affirm a wildcat PHILOSOPHICAL READINGS ISSUE VI – NUMBER 2 – SUMMER 2014 INTERVIEWS 153 planet of ethical freelancers who invent their 4) Why is it that new realism is es- own standards at every moment. Nonethe- sentially continental? Is it true that, less, each of us has broken basic ethical rules as Quentin Meillassoux put it, “in at various times (not too brazenly, one analytic philosophy there is so much hopes) precisely because ethics often re- realism that they can’t be amazed by quires this. It is easy to imagine moments the capacity of realism”? And, if it when stating a cold, hard truth would is true, what distinguishes analytic amount to needless cruelty, for instance. For realism from continental realism? any ethical rule, we can probably dream up an exceptional situation that would strongly In the first place, Meillassoux’s statement encourage its violation. is basically correct. Realism has always been In fact, this to me is the key fact of ethics: a live option for analytic philosophy, where- everyone seems to be allowed certain ethical as in the continental tradition one has always exceptions on a fairly constant basis. There risked becoming a laughingstock even by is my colleague who regularly speaks of posing the question of realism vs. antirealism. dirty jokes in class streams, and this in cul- Thanks to the phenomenological tradition turally conservative Egypt. If you or I were (which I love for other reasons, unlike Meil- to do it, we would quickly be terminated, lassoux) we have been trained to treat the since there would no doubt be a certain ugly problem of realism as a pseudo-problem. edge to it. But my colleague is able to pull After all, thought is “always already outside off the “crazy uncle” persona that allows itself in intending an object.” However, we him to get away with this pretty regularly can also intend hallucinatory or otherwise despite a number of close calls. Women gen- delusional objects, which does not make erally get away with certain sorts of things them “real” in any defensible sense of the that men generally do not, and certainly vice term. versa. It is by no means the case that we treat Husserl is a full-blown idealist, though al- everyone the same. And while this may so an object-oriented realist— the first to sometimes be the result of “hypocrisy” or a merit that description in the history of phi- “double standard,” the most interesting losophy. There were other philosophers cases are those in which it may be a double such as Kasimir Twardowski (Husserl’s true standard but not mere hypocrisy. Though predecessor in the Brentano School) who the surface value of two actions may be insisted on a doubling, with an object equivalent, their underlying character may outside the mind and a content inside the be completely different in the two cases, mind. We are quick to see that Husserl got based on who carries them out. rid of the “outside the mind” part but rarely notice that he preserved Twarodwski’s dualism, while ingeniously imploding both terms into the phenomenal realm. The British Empiricist tradition disdained objects ISSUE VI – NUMBER 1 – SUMMER 2014 PHILOSOPHICAL READINGS 154 INTERVIEWS cist tradition disdained objects and analyzed justified) but also as one/many (which is them away as “bundles of qualities,” but for not). Husserl the object remains somewhat con- As for realism in analytic philosophy, it stant, robust enough to withstand numerous tends to involve too much science-worship changes in qualities.
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy in the Epoch of Alternative Facts: an Invitation from East Asia
    Volume 9 Number 1 Spring 2020 pISSN 1848-4298 oISSN 2623-8381 THESIS - Vol. 9, No. 1, Spring 2020 International Research Journal ISSN: 1848-4298 (Print) ISSN: 2623-8381(Online) Philosophy in the Epoch of Alternative Facts: An Invitation from East Asia Naruhiko Mikado How to cite this article: Mikado, N. (2020). Philosophy in the Epoch of Alternative Facts: An Invitation from East Asia. Thesis. Vol. 9, No. 1. (35-57). Published online: June 30, 2020 Article received on the 8th of March, 2020. Article accepted on the 4th of May, 2020. Conict of Interest: The author declares no conict of interests. Review Article Philosophy in the Epoch of Alternative Facts: An Invitation from East Asia Naruhiko Mikado Osaka University, Osaka, Japan Email: [email protected] Abstract The primary aim of this essay was to elucidate the unique philosophical concept of “the non-interpretive”, which Masaya Chiba, one of the most prominent philosophers in East Asia, formulated mainly by bridging the theories of Quentin Meillassoux and Graham Harman, who have generally been reckoned as two of the most pivotal proponents in the contemporary philosophical movement dubbed Speculative Realism. In order to achieve the aim, the first part clarified the chief arguments and doctrines of Meillassoux’s Speculative Materialism and Harman’s Object-Oriented Philosophy. Thereupon, the second and main part investigated how Chiba invented the concept, what it precisely meant, and what insights it could offer for us. The concluding section summarized the chief arguments of this paper and sketched a worldview which we could adopt in order to survive the turbulent epoch of alternative facts and post-truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Materialism Is Not the Solution Graham Harman
    Materialism is Not the Solution On Matter, Form, and Mimesis Graham Harman abstract This article defends a new sense of “formalism” in philosophy and the arts, against recent materialist fashion. Form has three key opposite terms: matter, function, and content. First, I respond to Jane Bennett’s cri- tique of object-oriented philosophy in favor of a unified matter-energy, show- ing that Bennett cannot reach the balanced standpoint she claims to obtain. Second, I show that the form/function dualism in architecture gives us two purely relational terms and thus cannot do justice to the topic of form. Third, I argue against Greenberg, Heidegger, and McLuhan that content cannot be trivialized in favor of deeper form. I close with a new conception of mimesis as performance rather than as the fabrication of copies. The form underlying any work’s content is provided by the spectator herself as the only real object that does not withdraw from the aesthetic scene. keywords Formalism, materialism, mimesis, Jane Bennett, Patrik Schu- macher, Clement Greenberg, Martin Heidegger, Marshall McLuhan Object-oriented philosophy is often included on lists of recent materialist philosophies. Let me begin by decisively rejecting the term “materialism,” which I view as one of the most damaging philosophical temptations of our time. Nonetheless, the people who call object-oriented philosophy ma- terialism are not fools. There is a reason why they see a close proximity between my approach and that of other nearby authors who sympathize with materialism, whereas no one has ever called object-oriented philoso- phy “Hegelianism” or “Marxism,” for instance.
    [Show full text]
  • PROPOSITIONS, OBJECTS, QUESTIONS Graham Harman, in Conversation with Jon Roffe
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 21 • 2014 • 23-52 PROPOSITIONS, OBJECTS, QUESTIONS Graham Harman, in conversation with Jon Roffe The following is a near-verbatim transcription of a long conversation between Graham Harman and Jon Roffe on 30 November 2014 in Melbourne, Australia. Bryan Cooke, who transcribed this event, and I made only very minor edits in order to clarify the few moments in the recording that were par- ticularly unclear; otherwise, this is a full record of a wide-ranging discussion, including a number of questions from the floor. Parrhesia would like to thank the Cluster for the study of Organisation, Society and Markets, who hosted Graham Harman’s visit, and the Melbourne School of Continental Philosophy for their support in running the event and publishing this transcript—Jon Roffe Jon Roffe Well, first of all, thanks for being a part of this. Graham Harman Happy to be here in Australia for the first time. We’ve had a wonderful visit. We’ve been in Melbourne for two weeks. We’re going to Sydney next; I’ve heard great things about Sydney too. JR Well these people are from Melbourne so they won’t believe anything nice you say about Sydney. [laughter] So, as I’ve said, we’re keen to sort of make this a conversation more than an … interrogation. If you feel the questions are too hard, you can respond, well, as if you were being interrogated! That’s fine as well. So I sup- pose I’d like, first of all, to just begin with some very preliminary kinds of questions and sort of introduce those people who are here to your thought in a kind of very introductory way that we can delve into as time goes on.
    [Show full text]
  • Object-Oriented Philosophy Graham Harman
    Object-Oriented Philosophy Graham Harman M. Unies Ananda Raja 1 INTISARI Artikel ini bertujuan untuk menjelaskan asumsi dasar dari filsafat Graham Harman (1968– ) yang disebut dengan Object-Oriented Philosophy. Latar belakang pemikiran Harman adalah kritiknya terhadap tendensi filsafat barat yang cenderung menjelaskan realitas secara problematis dengan dua cara, yakni mereduksi objek ke unit terkecil (undermining) atau menolak unifikasi objek dalam satu hal (overmining). Masalahuntuk dari kecenderungan kepentingan pertama adalah peninjauan ketidakmampuan menjelaskan kemunculan dan ketahanan objek, sedangkan masalah kecenderungan kedua adalah ketidamampuan menjelaskan perubahan objek. Untuk mengatasi dua kecenderungan tersebut, Harman mengembangkan pemikiran tentang objek yang didapat dengan pembacaan kritis atas gagasan intensionalitas Husserl, peranti Heidegger, dan monadologi Leibniz. Dua kesimpulan penting Harman untuk mengatasi problem tersebut adalah: pertama, membagi objek dan kualitas menjadi masing-masing dua bagian, sehingga terdapat empat hal dalam objek, yakni objek real, kualitas real, objek sensual, dan kualitas sensual. Kedua, memperluas relasi yang tidak hanya terjadi antar objek dan kualitas, tetapi juga antar objek dengan objek, dan kualitas dengan kualitas, sehingga terdapat sepuluh model hubungan dalam objek. Kedua jawaban Harman tersebut membuatnya dapat menjawab problem perubahan dengan penempatan kausalitas pada ranah sensual, dan problem kemunculan dan ketahanan objek dengan gagasan Fisi–Fusi. Konsekuensi dari filsafat
    [Show full text]
  • Objects, Technology, Existence: Engaging with Graham Harman's
    Annual ETHU Seminar Objects, Technology, Existence: Engaging with Graham Harman’s OOO -online- Wednesday February 24th, 2021, 6–10 PM CET Abstracts & Bios Ecological Humanism and Our Entanglement with Things Hans Alma My presentation will focus on the question of what Graham Harman’s rejection of anthropocentrism means for contemporary humanism. In his book Facing the Planetary: Entangled Humanism and the Politics of Swarming (2017) the political philosopher William Connolly argues that we need new ways of thinking about how humans relate to other forms of being. He criticizes the modernistic and dualistic worldview of many forms of humanism, but doesn’t reject humanism as such. Connolly advocates an ‘entangled humanism’ that takes the inextricable interdependency of all forms of being into account, but that leaves room for human qualities and responsibilities. For the sake of clarity, I speak of an ‘ecological humanism’ and try to develop it in ways that are fruitful for the Belgian context. In this paper, I will study whether the archaeologist Ian Hodder’s view on the entanglement of humans and things is helpful for my endeavor to rethink humanism in non-anthropocentric ways. I will confront his view with the criticism of Harman that Hodder’s approach retains a nature/culture dualism and consider what object-oriented ontology contributes to ecological humanism. Hans Alma is Full Professor Religious Humanism and Compassion at the Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam (VU Amsterdam). Trained in cultural psychology and psychology of religion at the Radboud University Nijmegen, her research interest focuses on the human search for meaning in life. From this perspective, she explores what humanism can mean in the face of existential questions raised by the ecological crisis.
    [Show full text]
  • Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour and Metaphysics
    Open Access Statement – Please Read This book is Open Access. This work is not simply an electronic book; it is the open access version of a work that exists in a number of forms, the traditional printed form being one of them. Copyright Notice This work is ‘Open Access’, published under a creative commons license which means that you are free to copy, distribute, display, and perform the work as long as you clearly attribute the work to the authors, that you do not use this work for any commercial gain in any form and that you in no way alter, transform or build on the work outside of its use in normal aca- demic scholarship without express permission of the author and the publisher of this volume. Furthermore, for any reuse or distribution, you must make clear to others the license terms of this work. For more information see the details of the creative commons licence at this website: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/2.5/ This means that you can: • read and store this document free of charge • distribute it for personal use free of charge • print sections of the work for personal use • read or perform parts of the work in a context where no financial transactions take place However, you cannot: • gain financially from the work in anyway • sell the work or seek monies in relation to the distribution of the work • use the work in any commercial activity of any kind • profit a third party indirectly via use or distribution of the work • distribute in or through a commercial body (with the exception of academic usage within educational institutions such as schools and universities) • reproduce, distribute or store the cover image outside of its function as a cover of this work • alter or build on the work outside of normal academic scholarship Cover Art The artwork on the cover of this book is not open access and falls under traditional copyright provisions and thus cannot be reproduced in any way without written permission of the artists and their agents.
    [Show full text]
  • Graham Harman, Immaterialism
    Review Article Theory, Culture & Society 0(0) 1–17 ! The Author(s) 2019 Graham Harman, Article reuse guidelines: sagepub.com/journals-permissions Immaterialism: Objects DOI: 10.1177/0263276418824638 and Social Theory journals.sagepub.com/home/tcs Norah Campbell Trinity College Dublin Stephen Dunne University of Edinburgh Paul Ennis University College Dublin Abstract The philosopher Graham Harman argues that contemporary debates about the nature of reality as such, and about the nature of objects in particular, can be mean- ingfully applied to social theory and practice. With Immaterialism, he has recently provided a case-based demonstration of how this could happen. But social theorists have compelling reasons to oppose object-oriented social theory’s 15 principles. Fidelity to Harman’s aesthetic foundationalism, and his particular use of serial endo- symbiosis theory as a mechanism of social change, constrain the very practices which it is supposed to enable. However, social theory stands to benefit from object- oriented philosophy through what we call posthuman relationism – characterised as a commitment to the reality of the nonhuman, but not divorced from the human. The emphasis in object-oriented social theory on how objects withdraw from cognitive or affective capture and representation needs to be tempered by an equal focus on how objects appeal. Keywords Graham Harman, object-oriented social theory, posthuman relationism, symbiosis Immaterialism: Objects and Social Theory Graham Harman London: Polity Press, 2016. Corresponding author: Norah Campbell. Email: [email protected] Extra material: http://theoryculturesociety.org/ 2 Theory, Culture & Society 0(0) Introducing Object-Oriented Ontology Graham Harman is the creator and most prolific advocate of object- oriented ontology’s (OOO’s) dissemination.
    [Show full text]
  • BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN and the DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv
    PARRHESIA NUMBER 19 • 2014 • 65-78 BEATNIK BROTHERS? BETWEEN GRAHAM HARMAN AND THE DELEUZO-WHITEHEADIAN AXIS Adrian Ivakhiv INTRODUCTION Recent years have seen a surge of interest among Deleuzian and post-Deleuzian theorists in the metaphysical writings of Alfred North Whitehead. To many, there is a natural affinity between Deleuze and Whitehead, one that is continuous with a line of other thinkers—from Spinoza and Bruno to Bergson, Peirce, James, Simondon, Tarde, Serres, Stengers, and Latour—who are unified by an interest in process, affectivity, and a dynamic and relational ontology.1 Responding to this interest, Graham Harman has argued that these thinkers are falsely allied in a “beatnik brotherhood” of “process philosophers” or “philosophers of immanence.”2 At heart, he counters, their philosophies are radically different. This article examines what is at stake in this debate between Harman and the Deleuzo-Whiteheadians. Ex- amining a series of recent writings by Harman, I will show that Harman overdraws the differences between Whitehead and Deleuze in order to privilege the radical distinction between objects and relations that is at the heart of his own object-oriented ontology (OOO). I will examine some affinities and differences between Har- man’s account of objects and Whitehead’s account of actual occasions, and suggest that the two are not as far apart as Harman makes them appear. The key difference between them, and therefore the central stake in the debate between object-oriented and process-relational ontologies, concerns their respective understandings of temporality. In comparing Harman’s object-oriented ontology with the process-relational metaphysics of Whitehead (and, by extension, Deleuze), this article intends to contribute to a debate that has transpired in what has been called the “speculative realist blogosphere” since at least 2009.
    [Show full text]
  • Object Oriented Ontology Versus New Materialism
    Neil Leach Digital Tool Thinking: EGS/Tongji/FIU Object Oriented Ontology versus New Materialism ABSTRACT Within contemporary philosophy, two apparently similar movements have gained attention recently, New Materialism and Object Oriented Ontology. Although these movements have quite distinct genealogies, they overlap on one key issue: they are both realist movements that focus on the object. In contrast to much twentieth-century thinking centered on the subject, these two move- ments address the seemingly overlooked question of the object. In shifting attention away from the anthropocentrism of Humanism, both movements can be seen to subscribe to the broad principles of Posthumanism. Are these two movements, however, as similar as they first appear? And how might they be seen to differ in their approach to digital design? This paper is an attempt to evaluate and critique the recent strain of Object Oriented Ontology and question its validity. It does so by tracing the differences between OOO and New Materialism, specifically through the work of the neo-Heideg- gerian philosopher Graham Harman and the post-Deleuzian philosopher Manuel DeLanda, and by focusing on the question of the ‘tool’ in particular. The paper opens up towards the question of the digital tool, questioning the connection between Object Oriented Ontology and Object Oriented Programming, and introducing the theory of affordances as an alternative to the stylistic logic of ‘parametricism’ as a way of understanding the impact of digital tools on architectural production.
    [Show full text]
  • Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-Writing
    After The Passions: Object Oriented Ontology, Art and Art-writing PRUE GIBSON DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF NEW SOUTH WALES 2014 Originality Statement I hereby declare that this submission is my own work and to the best of my knowledge it contains no materials previously published or written by another person, or substantial proportions of material which have been accepted for the award of any other degree or diploma at UNSW or any other educational institution, except where due acknowledgement is made in the thesis. Any contribution made to the research by others, with whom I have worked at UNSW or elsewhere, is explicitly acknowledged in the thesis. I also declare that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work, except to the extent that assistance from others in the project’s design and conception or in style, presentation and linguistic expression is acknowledged. Signed: Dated: i Acknowledgements My supervisor Professor Stephen Muecke welcomed me into academic life and has supported me ever since. He introduced me to Speculative Realism and Object Oriented Ontology and slowed my usual cracking pace to a more considered and cautious speed. Each time I felt I had discovered something new about writing, I realised Stephen had led me there. I have often tried to emulate his mentoring method for my own students: without judgement, enthusiastic and twinkle-eyed. Through the second half of the thesis process, my co-supervisor Professor Edward Scheer jumped in and demanded evidence, structured argument and accountability. This was the perfect timing for a rigorous edit.
    [Show full text]
  • Global Finitude a Conversation with Graham Harman
    Excerpted from The Kantian Catastrophe? Conversations on Finitude and the Limits of Philosophy, Anthony Morgan (ed.), Newcastle: Bigg Books, 2017. 253 14: Global Finitude A Conversation with Graham Harman In this conversation, Graham Harman begins by reflecting on the status of Speculative Realism a decade on from the conference that established it as a new and exciting move- ment in philosophy. Although Kant attracted a fair amount of critical attention from within this movement, Harman makes it clear that Kant’s legacy is far from a catastrophic one and goes on to explore the pivotal role Kant plays in his object-oriented ontology (OOO) in which it is argued that the Kantian thing-in-itself is an inevitable aspect of any re- lation (rather than simply of the human-world relation as in Kant). Arguably, Harman suggests, OOO is the only contem- porary philosophical movement that swears by the thing-in- itself. Graham Harman is distinguished professor of philosophy at the Southern California Institute of Architecture in Los Angeles, and is widely known as a key figure in the contem- porary Speculative Realism movement in philosophy and for his development of object-oriented ontology (OOO). He is the author of numerous books including Immaterialism, Dante’s Broken Hammer, and the forthcoming Object-Ori- ented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything. In 2015 he was ranked as one of Art Review’s 100 most influential fig- ures in the art world. --- We find ourselves ten years on from the famous confer- ence at Goldsmith’s at which the Speculative Realism movement was founded.
    [Show full text]
  • Graham Harman
    graham harman Graham Harman is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the Southern California Institute of Architecture (on leave from the American University in Cairo). He is the author of fourteen books, most recently Immaterialism: Objects and Social Theory (2016) and Dante’s Broken Hammer: The Ethics, Aesthetics, and Metaphysics of Love (2016). He is the editor of the Speculative Realism book series at Edinburgh University Press and (with Bruno Latour) co-editor of the New Metaphysics series at the Open Humanities Press. object-oriented seduction baudrillard reconsidered The late Jean Baudrillard is viewed in some quarters as the most frivolous author in recent French philosophy. Some of this can be ascribed to his style, which relies heavily on flash: on a speed of unmediated connection that often has the aroma of the arbitrary. Consider the following passage, chosen at random: Pompeii is thus a kind of trompe-l’oeil or primal scene: the same ver- tigo of a missing dimension, that of time, the same hallucination of an added dimension, that of the transparency of the slightest details, like that precise vision of submerged trees living at the bottom of an artificial lake over which you pass while swimming.1 Even when read in context, such passages often defy interpretation. His authorial voice tends to build a case less by developing successive pieces of evidence than by producing aphoristic paragraphs that count on the accuracy of their wit to pro- duce agreement. Another example reinforces the point: “The obese somehow es- cape sexuality and sexual division by the indivisibility of the full body.
    [Show full text]