In Order. for Us to Discuss on Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude in Some

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

In Order. for Us to Discuss on Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude in Some On Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude Keiichiro KAMINO Osaka City University 1. Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude 2. Criticism on Popper's Theory of Verisimilitude 3. Suggested Ways of Defining the Notion 4. Popper's Rejoinders 5. Concluding Remarks The purpose of this essay is in the first place to make a survey of the problem situation in which the notion of verisimilitude is now found, and then try to clarify what Popper intends to do with the notion. Therefore, I shall sketch Popper's general epistemological position in so far as it is relevant to the present discussion, and also mention Popper's original proposal for the definition of the notion. Secondly, in order to make the situation clear, I shall introduce some of the criticisms raised against Popper's original proposal and also show what I think is the general trend in the recent attempts to define the notion. Finally, I shall examine Popper's reaction against those criticisms and new proposals which were produced by Tichy , Miller, and others, to try to see Popper's real intention concerning the notion of verisimiltude, and to find out a way which hopefully will lead to a better problem situation agreeable from Popper's point of view, which is based on critical rationalism. 1. Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude 1.1 Popper's epistemological point of view In order.for us to discuss on Popper's notion of verisimilitudein some detail, it would be necessary to characterise his general philosophical position so that all arguments will not drift astray. On the one hand Popper is surely sceptical with regard to the possibility of our attaining scientific truths. For according to Popper, scientifictheories are not the digest of observations; they are inventions, or conjectures boldly put forward for trial to be eliminated if they clash with observations. And he contends even that we can never have sufficiently good arguments in the empirical sciensesfor claiming that we have actually reached the truth. All theories are hypothetical, and all may be overthrown. Indeed, any attempt logically to justify a scientific statement as ture, would lead to an infinite regress. We can never have sufficient reasons for holding any scientific -1- 2 K. KAMINO Vol. 6 statement to be true, even if the statement be in fact true. Popper's rejection of the quest for justification has some affinity to the sceptical claim, which is very pessimistic with respect to the possibility of knowledge. In fact, he calls his own position dynamic scepticism, although he identifies this with 'critical inquiry'. On the other hand, however, he admits the possibility of the growth of know- ledge. He is always optimistic with the possibility of knowledge. Indeed, he is still optimistic, even when his theory of verisimilitude is exposedto severe attacks. With his theory of knowledge,however, one thing should be kept in our mind. The traditional view on knowledge claims that scientia is knowledgeof universal truths which are true of neccesity, and that knowledge can only be obtained by demon stration (though not necessarily logical demonstration). In the long history of Western thought since Plato and Aristotle, knowledge has been contrasted with belief or opinion, whose attribute is not 'true' but 'probable'. Knowledgeought to be true and to have certainty; opinion is more or less probable and subjective. In view of this, I contend that Popper stands on a very unique position. Certainly he claims that all scientifictheories are hypothetical, and strips off their garments of certainty. This naturally sounds as if he takes a kind of probabilism. It is clear, however,that he stands firmly on the traditional view that scientiais demonstrative, when he tries to demarcate scientia against pseudo-sciences. Because in trying to do so, he relies upon the power of logic, i.e., modustollens. I shall call Popper's position 'optimisticscepticism. This nice expressionI borrowed from P. Tichy. 1.2 Why Popper needs the notion of verisimilitude Popper's optimistic scepticism, however, does not claim that the truth itself is just an illusion. Some such description would indeed be a misleading one to express the nature of Popper's theory of knowledge. Popper maintains that even if there is no general criterion of truth for scientific theories, the notion of truth is logically legitimate. This, as he himself says, is very opposite to the positivistic position as was propounded by Wittgenstein that a concept is vacuous if there is no criterion for its application. The positivistic conceptionis as is known refuted by the modern development of logic, and especially by Tarski's theory of truth, which contains the theorem: for sufficientlyrich languages there can be no criterion of truth. (Popper, O.K., p. 321.) What then are we doing, when we say that we are seeking for truth We say, for instance, that we have come nearer to the truth, or that some theory Tl is superseded by some new theory T2, because T2 is more like the truth than T1. These are somehow intuitive assertions, of course. Can we, however, give good reasons for these propositions at least in some cases. If the notion of truth is dubious, so will be the notion of a better approach to the truth, or of a nearness to the truth or of a greater verisimilitude. Fortunately, however, the legitimacy of the notion of -2- No. 1 On Popper's Notion of Verisimilitude 3 truth has been established by Tarski. Can we then hope that we may say the notion of verisimilitudeis also legitimate? I hope the answer is in the affirmative. In advocating the notion of verisimilitiude,what does Popper take to be its advant ages or utilities? First let us see how it explicates our notion of scientificinvestiga tion. The task of scienceis, in a sense, to cover by hits as much as possibleof the true statements, by the method of proposing theories or conjectures which seems to us promising, and as little as possible of the false conjectures. It is therefore very important that we conjecture true theories; but truth is not the only important properties of our conjectural theories. We are not particularly interested in pro- posing trivialities or tautologies; as "all tables are table" will not be a scientific truth. On the contrary, we know for instance that Newtonian physics is false. We know that few of scientifictheories we discover are true, or perhaps none is. Even so, we think that it is a much better 'approximation' to the truth, because it contains a number of interesting and informative true consequencses; the truth content of Newtonian physics is very great indeed. The fact is that we are not simply looking for truth, but are looking for interest- ing and enlightening truth. The introduction of the concept of versimilitude, there- fore, brings us a considerable advantage over the simple formulation that the aim of science is truth. The notion of verisimilitude will free scientific theories from the search of trivial truths, and at the same time, will explain why we are interested in some fales theories such as Newtonian physics or Einstein's relativity theories which have a great truth content. We admit false theories or statements if they are not ' too false' (if they have not too large falsity content) and contain a great truth content. Popper also adds that the search for verisimilitude is a clearer and a more realistic aim than the search for truth, and that we can have strong and reasonably good arguments for claiming that we may have made progress towards the truth. Moreover, he claims, we can explain the method of science, and much of the history of science, as the rational procedure for getting nearer to truth. (cf. ibid., pp. 57-8) 1.3 Popper's definition of verisimilitude Popper's theory of verisimilitude was first presented in Popper (1962) and (1963). It has since been expanded in Popper (1972). Popper's logical notion of verisimili- tude is a combination of two notions, both of which were originally introduced by Tarski; one is the notion of truth and the other is the notion of the logical con- tent of a statement, i.e., its consequence class. Now the content or the strength of a deductive theory can be determined by the size of its consequence class. The greater the consequence class of a theory is, the stronger it is. In other words, the comparability of theory will be reduced to set-theoretical inclusion relation. The size of the consequence class, however, -3- 4 K. KAMINO Vol 6 does not establish the superiority of theory, or so Popper thought in the sixties. In assessing scientific theories, we are interested in the increase of true con- sequences, of course. Thus Popper first tried to define both the truth content and the falsity content of theory. Thus Popper said: the set A of all true statements following from any given statement a is called the truth content of a. It is a deductive system., in symbols: A=Cn(A)=Cn(a), and vice versa, (to every statement say a there corresponds a finitely axiomatizable system say A) therefore, A=A•¿T=Cn(a•Ét). To define the falsity content of A, he drew upon the idea of the relative content A, given B, or A, B. A,B=Cn(A,B)=Cn(A•¾B)-Cn(B)=Cn(a&b)-Cn(b) The falsity content, then, AF=A,AT=Cn(A+AT)-Cn(AT)=Cn(A)-Cn(AT). Thus, for the notion of verisimilitude, he said: a theory T, has less versimilitude than a theory TQ if and only if (a) their truth contents and falsity conetents (or their measure) are comparable, and either (b) the truth content but not the falsity content of Tl is smaller than that of T2, or (c) the truth content of Tl is not greater than that of T2, but its falsity content is greater.
Recommended publications
  • Truth, Rationality, and the Growth of Scientific Knowledge
    ....... CONJECTURES sense similar to that in which processes or things may be said to be parts of the world; that the world consists of facts in a sense in which it may be said to consist of (four dimensional) processes or of (three dimensional) things. They believe that, just as certain nouns are names of things, sentences are names of facts. And they sometimes even believe that sentences are some- thing like pictures of facts, or that they are projections of facts.7 But all this is mistaken. The fact that there is no elephant in this room is not one of the processes or parts ofthe world; nor is the fact that a hailstorm in Newfound- 10 land occurred exactIy I I I years after a tree collapsed in the New Zealand bush. Facts are something like a common product oflanguage and reality; they are reality pinned down by descriptive statements. They are like abstracts from TRUTH, RATIONALITY, AND THE a book, made in a language which is different from that of the original, and determined not only by the original book but nearly as much by the principles GROWTH OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE of selection and by other methods of abstracting, and by the means of which the new language disposes. New linguistic means not only help us to describe 1. THE GROWTH OF KNOWLEDGE: THEORIES AND PROBLEMS new kinds of facts; in a way, they even create new kinds of facts. In a certain sense, these facts obviously existed before the new means were created which I were indispensable for their description; I say, 'obviously' because a calcula- tion, for example, ofthe movements of the planet Mercury of 100 years ago, MY aim in this lecture is to stress the significance of one particular aspect of carried out today with the help of the calculus of the theory of relativity, may science-its need to grow, or, if you like, its need to progress.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding the Progress of Science
    Understanding the Progress of Science C. D. McCoy 30 May 2018 The central problem of epistemology has always been and still is the problem of the growth of knowledge. And the growth of knowledge can be studied best by studying the growth of scientific knowledge. —(Popper, 2002b, xix) Merely fact-minded sciences make merely fact-minded people. —(Husserl, 1970, 6) The growth of human knowledge is realized most dramatically in the growth of scientific knowledge. What we have come to know through science about the workings of our human bodies and the workings of heavenly bodies, among much else, astounds, especially in comparison to our accumulating knowledge of the commonplace and everyday. Impressed by the evident epistemic progress made by science, many philosophers during the 20th century thought that studying how scientific knowledge increases is a crucial task of epistemological inquiry, and, indeed, the progress of science has been a topic of considerable interest. Yet, eventually, late in the century, attention waned and for the most part shifted to other tasks. Recently, however, a provocative article by Bird has re-ignited philosophical interest in the topic of scientific progress (Bird, 2007). Bird criticizes what he takes to have been the most prominent accounts advanced in the 20th century and presses for what he views as a venerable but lately overlooked one. He claims that realist philosophers of science have often presumed that truth is the goal of science and progress to be properly characterized by an accu- mulation of truth or truths, and notes that anti-realists have often rejected truth as a goal of science and characterized progress in terms of, among other things, “problem-solving effectiveness.”1 He criticizes the former for overlooking the relevance of justification to progress and the latter for giving up on truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge
    CRITICISM AND THE GROWTH OF KNOWLEDGE Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science, London, ig 6^, volume 4 Edited by IMRE LAKATOS Professor of Logic, University of London ALAN MUSGRAVE Professor of Philosophy, University of Otago CAMBRIDGE AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS 1970 CONTENTS Published by the Syndics of the Cambridge University Press Page Bentley House, 200 Euston Road, London N.W .i Preface vii American Branch: 32 East 57th Street, New York, N.Y. 10022 T. s. KUHN: Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research? i © Cambridge University Press 1970 Library of Congress Catalogue Card Number 78-105496 Discussion: j. w. N. WATKINS: Against ‘Normal Science’ 25 Standard Book Number: 521 07826 i toulmin: Does the Distinction between Normal and Revolutionary Science Hold Water? 39 L. PEARCE williams: Normal Science, Scientific Revolutions / ^ d the History of Science 49 popper: Normal Science and its Dangers 5^ uJVfiC^ARET masterman: The Nature of a Paradigm 59 i I: Lakatos: Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes 9^ K„ feyer aben d : Consolations for the Specialist 197 s. KUHN: Reflections on my Critics 231 Index 279 Printed in Great Britain at the University Press, Aberdeen PREFACE This book constitutes the fourth volume of the Proceedings of the 1965 International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science held at Bedford College, Regent’s Park, London, from i i to 17 July 1965. The Colloquium was organized jointly by the British Society for the Philosophy of Science and the London School of Economics and Political Science, under the auspices of the Division of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science of the International Union of History and Philosophy of Seience.
    [Show full text]
  • The P–T Probability Framework for Semantic Communication, Falsification, Confirmation, and Bayesian Reasoning
    philosophies Article The P–T Probability Framework for Semantic Communication, Falsification, Confirmation, and Bayesian Reasoning Chenguang Lu School of Computer Engineering and Applied Mathematics, Changsha University, Changsha 410003, China; [email protected] Received: 8 July 2020; Accepted: 16 September 2020; Published: 2 October 2020 Abstract: Many researchers want to unify probability and logic by defining logical probability or probabilistic logic reasonably. This paper tries to unify statistics and logic so that we can use both statistical probability and logical probability at the same time. For this purpose, this paper proposes the P–T probability framework, which is assembled with Shannon’s statistical probability framework for communication, Kolmogorov’s probability axioms for logical probability, and Zadeh’s membership functions used as truth functions. Two kinds of probabilities are connected by an extended Bayes’ theorem, with which we can convert a likelihood function and a truth function from one to another. Hence, we can train truth functions (in logic) by sampling distributions (in statistics). This probability framework was developed in the author’s long-term studies on semantic information, statistical learning, and color vision. This paper first proposes the P–T probability framework and explains different probabilities in it by its applications to semantic information theory. Then, this framework and the semantic information methods are applied to statistical learning, statistical mechanics, hypothesis evaluation (including falsification), confirmation, and Bayesian reasoning. Theoretical applications illustrate the reasonability and practicability of this framework. This framework is helpful for interpretable AI. To interpret neural networks, we need further study. Keywords: statistical probability; logical probability; semantic information; rate-distortion; Boltzmann distribution; falsification; verisimilitude; confirmation measure; Raven Paradox; Bayesian reasoning 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Degrees of Riskiness, Falsifiability, and Truthlikeness. a Neo-Popperian
    Degrees of riskiness, falsifiability, and truthlikeness. A neo-Popperian account applicable to probabilistic theories. Leander Vignero Sylvia Wenmackers [email protected] [email protected] KU Leuven, Institute of Philosophy, Centre for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Kardinaal Mercierplein 2 { bus 3200, 3000 Leuven, Belgium. July 7, 2021 (Forthcoming in Synthese.) Abstract In this paper, we take a fresh look at three Popperian concepts: riskiness, falsifiability, and truthlikeness (or verisimilitude) of scien- tific hypotheses or theories. First, we make explicit the dimensions that underlie the notion of riskiness. Secondly, we examine if and how degrees of falsifiability can be defined, and how they are related to var- ious dimensions of the concept of riskiness as well as the experimental context. Thirdly, we consider the relation of riskiness to (expected degrees of) truthlikeness. Throughout, we pay special attention to probabilistic theories and we offer a tentative, quantitative account of verisimilitude for probabilistic theories. \Modern logic, as I hope is now evident, has the effect of enlarging our abstract imagination, and providing an infinite number of possible hypotheses to be applied in the analysis of any complex fact." { Russell (1914, p. 58). A theory is falsifiable if it allows us to deduce predictions that can be compared to evidence, which according to our background knowledge could arXiv:2107.03772v1 [physics.hist-ph] 8 Jul 2021 show the prediction | and hence the theory | to be false. In his defense of falsifiability as a demarcation criterion, Popper has stressed the importance of bold, risky claims that can be tested, for they allow science to make progress.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Scientific Progress?
    What is Scientific Progress? 1 Introduction What is scientific progress? The answer is simple. Science (or some particular scientific field or theory) makes progress precisely when it shows the accumulation of scientific knowledge; an episode in science is progressive when at the end of the episode there is more knowledge than at the beginning. This simple, cumulative conception of scientific progress is not original; indeed it has a venerable history.1 Yet philosophers of science have almost entirely ignored this conception, at least since it was condemned by Kuhn and others in the 1960s. Even in the realist reaction against positivism and relativism the cumulative conception has not been rehabilitated. Realists have typically sought an account of progress in terms of increasing verisimilitude (truth-likeness, approximate truth) rather than increasing knowledge. In this paper I will be comparing three approaches to characterising scientific progress: (i) the epistemic approach, (ii) the semantic approach, and (iii) the functional-internalist approach. The epistemic approach takes knowledge to be the concept we need in order to understand what progress is. (The only version of the epistemic approach I shall consider is the cumulative knowledge account I have already advertised.) The semantic approach takes truth (or verisimilitude) to be the central concept is defining progress. And the functional-internalist holds that progress is made when a scientific development succeeds in fulfilling a certain function (such as solving a scientific problem), where that function is understood in such a way that the scientific practitioners are themselves in a position to judge whether the function has been fulfilled.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Advocate Pancritical Rationalism?
    Why Advocate Pancritical Rationalism? Darrell P. Rowbottom and Otávio Bueno Abstract This paper provides a rationale for advocating pancritical rationalism. First, it argues that the advocate of critical rationalism may accept (but not be internally justified in accepting) that there is ‘justification’ in an externalist sense, specifically that certain procedures can track truth, and suggest that this recognition should inform practice; that one should try to determine which sources and methods are appropriate for various aspects of inquiry, and to what extent they are. Second, it argues that if there is external justification, then a critical rationalist is better off than a dogmatist from an evolutionary perspective. Introduction Consider two individuals. One believes h dogmatically, and will never give it up. The other believes h just as strongly (i.e., has the same synchronic degree of belief), but is prepared to reconsider that belief in the light of criticism. Is the latter in a better position than the former? From an ordinary language point of view, it seems as if the advocate of (comprehensively) critical rationalism thinks so; and therefore also believes that the latter is ‘justified’ in believing h in a manner that the former is not. Why else recommend the critical attitude? A possible answer is that the former individual is incapable of learning (insofar as h is concerned), whereas the latter clearly is so capable. But if we accept that one can learn something that is false, as (comprehensively) critical rationalists tend to, then this seems insufficient. Learning could lead one to false beliefs, rather than just true ones.
    [Show full text]
  • 128 What Social Scientists Don't Understand
    In D. W. Fiske and R. A. Shweder (Eds.) Metatheory in social science: Pluralisms and subjectivities. Chicago: University of 128 Chicago Press, 1986. (Chapter 14, pp.315-338) What Social Scientists Don’t Understand P. E. Meehl In the papers prepared for the conference on which this book is based and in the discussion, there were some matters almost universally agreed upon but repeated unnecessarily. Then there were some things that should have been agreed upon but were not. Finally, there were matters that were not agreed upon that needed more intensive examination—matters playing a central role in the philosophy of the social sciences and in the present intellectual gloominess that seems to prevail in all of the disciplines represented. THINGS GENERALLY AGREED ON FROM THE BEGINNING It was agreed that logical positivism and strict operationism won’t wash. Logical positivism, in anything like the sense of Vienna in the late twenties turned out not to be logically defensible, or even rigorously formulatable, by its adherents. It is epistemologically unsound from a variety of viewpoints (including ordinary-language analysis), it is not an accurate picture of the structure of advanced sciences such as physics, and it is grossly inadequate as a reconstruction of empirical history of science. So it is dead. All old surviving logical positivists agree, including my friend and teacher Feigl, who invented the phrase “logical positivism” and was the first to introduce the approach in the United States in 1931. The last remaining defender of anything like logical positivism was Gustav Bergmann, who ceased to do so by the late 1940s.
    [Show full text]
  • The Critical Rationalist
    The Critical Rationalist ISSN 1393-3809 Volume 02 Number 02 05-Jun-1997 Editor-in-Chief: Dr. Ray Scott Percival E-mail: [email protected] Web: http://www.eeng.dcu.ie/~tkpw/tcr/tcr-home The Critical Rationalist Vol. 02 No. 02 ISSN: 1393-3809 05-Jun-1997 Popp erian Ideas on Progress and Rationalityin Science John Watkins c 1997 1 The Critical Rationalist Vol. 02 No. 02 ISSN: 1393-3809 05-Jun-1997 Popp erian Ideas on Progress and Rationalityin Science (First presented at the American Philosophical Association East- ern Division Meeting 1996, at the Symposium on Scientific Ra- tionality and Progress in Memory of Paul Feyerabend and Karl Popper.) 1 I got to know Paul Feyerabend well in 1961, when I was in Berkeley. (I also met Tom Kuhn then.) I loved his racy, carefree, and often surpris- ingly erudite talk and letters. But after Against Method we got rather stuck into confrontational postures (see for instance our argy-bargy in Progress and Rationality in Science, Radnitzky & Andersson 1978). Karl Popper I first encountered back in 1947. He had a decisive formative influence on my intellectual life. I remain a tremendous admirer of the ideas about science, especially about the growth and progress of science, which he published dur- ing his heyday, from 1934 down to about 1960. But I am critical of certain tendencies in his later philosophy, one of which I turn to now. 2 For Popper, science is like music or poetry in that it requires inventive- ness, there being no recipe or method for creating it, and also unlike music and poetry in that there are criteria of progress for it but not for them.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Progress on the Semantic View
    Scientific Progress On The Semantic View An Account of Scientific Progress as Objective Logical and Empirical Strength Increments Anders Solli Sal Master Thesis IFIKK, Faculty of Humanities University of Oslo Autumn 2013 1 Theories are our own inventions, our own ideas; they are not forced upon us, but are our self-made instruments of thought: this has been clearly seen by the idealist. But some of these theories of ours can clash with reality; and when they do, we know that there is a reality; that there is something to remind us of the fact that our ideas may be mistaken. And this is why the realist is right. - Karl Popper 2 Abstract The aim of this master thesis is to make a convincing argument that scientific progress can be spoken of in objective terms. In order to make this argument I will propose a philosophical theory of scientific progress. Two concepts will be constructed with this aim in mind, both which are types of strength measures on scientific theories. The first concept, that of logical strength, pertains to the way a theory may exclude, or permit less, model classes compared to another theory. The second concept, that of empirical strength, pertains to an objective measure of the informational content of data models, defined in terms of Kolmogorov complexity. This latter idea stems from communication and computational theory. Scientific progress is then defined as the interaction, or the stepwise increases, of these two strength measures. Central for the conception of a scientific theory is the philosophical framework known as The Semantic View of Scientific Theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Critical Rationalism and 'Normal Science' - a Proposed Resolution of the Popper/Kuhn Controversy and Its Implications for the Sociology of Science
    CRITICAL RATIONALISM AND 'NORMAL SCIENCE' - A PROPOSED RESOLUTION OF THE POPPER/KUHN CONTROVERSY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR THE SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE Marie-Andr6e Rivet B.A., Simon Fraser University, 1983 THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of Sociology and Anthropology @ Marie-Andrke Rivet 1988 SIMON FRASER UNIVERSITY March, 1988 All rights reserved. This work may not be reproduced in whole or in part, by photocopy or other means, without permission of the author. APPROVAL Name: Marie-Andrke ~ivet .. 0 Degree: Master o'f Arts Title of thesis: CRITICAL RATIONALISM AND 'NORMAL SCIENCE' - A PROPOSED RESOLUTION OF THE POPPER/KUHN CONTROVERSY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR THE SOCIOLOGY OF SCI ENCE Examining Committee: Chairman : Dr. Hari Sharma --.- "L Dr. Keith Dixon . Senior Supervisor Dr. Heribert Adam Department of Philosophy Date Approved: March Ist, 1988 PARTIAL COPYRIGHT LICENSE .. m I hereby grant to Simon Fraser University the right to lend my thesis, project or extended essay (the title of which is shown below) to users of the Simon Fraser University Library, and to make partial or single copies only for such users or in response to a request from the library of any other university, or other educational institution, on its own behalf or for one of its users. I further agree that permission for multiple copying of this work for scholarly purposes may be granted by me or the Dean of Graduate Studies. It is understood that copying ' or publication of this work for financial gain shall not be allowed without my written permission.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Greek Probability Arguments and Common Ground in Dissensus Manfred Kraus Universität Tübingen
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Scholarship at UWindsor University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 7 Jun 6th, 9:00 AM - Jun 9th, 5:00 PM Early Greek Probability Arguments and Common Ground in Dissensus Manfred Kraus Universität Tübingen Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive Part of the Philosophy Commons Kraus, Manfred, "Early Greek Probability Arguments and Common Ground in Dissensus" (2007). OSSA Conference Archive. 92. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA7/papersandcommentaries/92 This Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty of Arts, Humanities and Social Sciences at Scholarship at UWindsor. It has been accepted for inclusion in OSSA Conference Archive by an authorized conference organizer of Scholarship at UWindsor. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Early Greek Probability Arguments and Common Ground in Dissensus MANFRED KRAUS Philologisches Seminar Universität Tübingen Wilhelmstraße 36 72074 Tübingen Germany [email protected] ABSTRACT: The paper argues that the arguments from probability (eikós) so popular in early Greek rhetoric and oratory essentially operate by appealing to common positions shared by both speaker and audience. Particularly in controversial debate provoked by fundamental dissensus they make their claim acceptable to the audience by pointing out a basic coherence or congruence of the speaker’s narrative with the audience’s own pre-established (legal, moral, emotional) standards or standards of knowledge. KEYWORDS: audience, eikós-argument, enthymeme, example, experience, plausibility, probability, similarity, truth, verisimilitude. 1. INTRODUCTION At some time during the fifth century B.C.E., judicial orators in Greek Sicily appear to have contrived a perfectly suitable method of successfully pleading their cases in such instances in which no eye-witnesses or written documents or other unassailable pieces of direct evidence could be produced.
    [Show full text]