Tolerant Imperialism: John Stuart Mill's Defense of British Rule in India

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Tolerant Imperialism: John Stuart Mill's Defense of British Rule in India The Review of Politics 68 (2006), 1–26. Copyright # University of Notre Dame DOI: 10.1017/S0034670506000246 Printed in the USA 1 2 Tolerant Imperialism: John Stuart Mill’s Defense 3 of British Rule in India 4 5 6 Mark Tunick 7 8 9 Abstract: Some critics of John Stuart Mill understand him to advocate the forced 10 assimilation of people he regards as uncivilized and to defend toleration and the 11 principle of liberty only for civilized people of the West. Examination of Mill’s social 12 and political writings and practice while serving the British East India Company 13 shows, instead, that Mill is a tolerant imperialist: Mill defends interference in India 14 to promote the protection of legal rights, respect and toleration for conflicting 15 viewpoints, and a commercial society that can cope with natural threats. He does 16 not think the principle of liberty is waived for the uncivilized or that the West 17 should forcibly reshape them in its own monistic image. Mill’s tolerant imperialism 18 reflects a tension between liberty and moral development that also surfaces when 19 Mill thinks about the scope of government in civilized societies. 20 21 22 23 24 I. Critics of Mill’s Imperialism1 25 26 John Stuart Mill, an undisputed spokesperson for British imperialism, was a 27 loyal employee of the East India Company for roughly half his life. He saw 28 England and the Company as forces of progress that spread liberal values 29 and improved mankind’s capacity for individuality and the enjoyment 30 of higher pleasures (Rel 10:422, 426; AU 1:145–46). He praised the impro- 31 vements to India’s infrastructure, health care system, and educational 32 institutions that were made possible by the Company’s introduction 33 of modernizing technologies (CW 30:141–48). 34 35 36 1 37 References to Mill’s works will be cited as “CW volume: page.” Abbreviations: AU 38 (Autobiography, 1873: in CW 1); Civ (“Civilization,”1836: in CW 18); CW (John Stuart 39 Mill, Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. John M. Robson et al. [Toronto: 40 University of Toronto Press, 1963-]); NI (“A Few Words on Non-Intervention,” 1859: in CW 21); NW (John Stuart Mill, Newspaper Writings, eds. Ann P. Robson and John 41 M. Robson (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1986); OL (On Liberty, 1859: in CW 42 18); PPE (Principles of Political Economy, 1848: in CW 2, 3); Rel (Three Essays on 43 Religion, 1874: in CW 10); RG (Considerations on Representative Government, 1861: in 44 CW 19); SpA (“The Spirit of the Age,” 1831: in CW 22); U (Utilitarianism, 1861: in 45 CW 10). Q1 1 2 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS 46 Mill’s support of British imperialism may seem puzzling given that Mill 2 47 defends toleration, liberty, and experiments in living. How could the theorist 48 who defends a principle holding that no one could “rightfully be compelled to 49 do or forbear because it will be better for him to do so” (OL 18:223–24) also 50 defend a system of imperialism seeking to compel the improvement of 51 others? Uday Mehta finds the defense of empire by liberals like Mill 52 “ironic,” given that liberals should be committed to toleration, 3 53 self-determination, and human dignity. The two positions—support of 54 imperialism and defense of liberal values—have been reconciled in the past 55 by understanding Mill’s principle of liberty to apply only to civilized 56 people and Mill to support despotism for the uncivilized. On this view, 57 Mill did not think we should be tolerant of the practices and laws of 58 peoples, like those living in India, whom he thought uncivilized. 59 Mill has been sharply criticized for championing despotism for 60 non-Western peoples. Some critics charge him with ethnocentrically seeking 61 to impose the individualist liberal values of his England on the rest of the 62 world and advocating cultural assimilation.4 Bikhu Parekh sees Mill as 63 willing to use violent and intolerant forms of coercion to impose a “monistic 64 vision of the good life.”5 On Parekh’s view, Mill, assuming some cultures are 65 superior to others, wants to prevent the ascendancy of an inferior group by 66 ruling out any form of diversity that emphasizes “ethnically grounded” or 67 “traditional and customary ways of life, as well as those centered on the com- 68 munity.” For Parekh, Mill is a “missionary” for liberal diversity and intolerant 69 of nonliberal ways of life.6 70 Some of Mill’s critics trace what they perceive as Mill’s intolerant imperial- 71 ism to racist attitudes.7 Some link it to a lack of appreciation for radically 72 different ways of understanding the world. Mehta argues that Mill, in 73 74 2OL 18:260–61, 275; cf. Elizabeth S. Anderson, “John Stuart Mill and Experiments in 75 Living,” Ethics 102 (1991): 4–26. 76 3Uday Singh Mehta, Liberalism and Empire (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 77 1999), 3–4. 78 4Bhikhu Parekh, “Decolonizing Liberalism,” in The End of ‘isms’? Reflections on the 79 Fate of Ideological Politics after Communism’s Collapse, ed. Alexander Shtromas 80 (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), 85–103; “Liberalism and Colonialism: a Critique of Locke 81 and Mill,” in The Decolonization of Imagination: Culture, Knowledge and Power, ed. Jan 82 Pieterse and Bhikhu Parekh (London: Zed Books, 1995), 81–98; and Eddy Souffrant, 83 Formal Transgression: J.S. Mill’s Philosophy of International Affairs (Lanham: Rowman 84 and Littlefield, 2000). 5 85 Parekh, “Liberalism and Colonialism,” 96; cf., “Decolonizing Liberalism.” 6Ibid., “Superior People: The Narrowness of Liberalism from Mill to Rawls,” Times 86 Literary Supplement (February 25, 1994). 87 7Shiraz Dossa, “Liberal Imperialism? Natives, Muslims, and Others,” Political 88 Theory 30 (2002):738–45; Vinay Lal, “Organic Conservatism, Administrative 89 Realism, and the Imperialist Ethos in the ‘Indian Career’ of John Stuart Mill,” New 90 Quest 54 (1998): 54–64; Richard Drayton, Nature’s Government: Science, Imperial TOLERANT IMPERIALISM 3 91 wanting to civilize Indians, completely ignores how Indians already have an 92 integral way of life and a system of reference giving meanings to particular 8 93 things. Mill, according to Mehta’s view, in confronting Indian forms of life 94 so different from his own, lacks the humility needed to appreciate how 95 Indian religions and traditions provided “dwellings in which peoples lived 9 96 and had deeply invested identities.” Mill, overly confident in his own 97 claims of knowledge, infantilizes Indians without understanding them. He 98 assumes that Indian experiences were provisional and in need of correction 10 99 and completion by enlightened guides. This criticism of Mill’s defense of 100 British imperialism draws on a broader criticism of liberalism itself as the 101 imposition of what is seen as peculiarly Western ideas of rationality, 102 science, and progress. In seeing India as not yet civilized, Mill imposes a 103 certain historical approach that dismisses folk beliefs that are not rationally 104 demonstrable, including all “unreal, impossible and supernatural events.”11 105 In Mehta’s words, Mill imposes a “cosmopolitanism of reason” that rejects 106 the unfamiliar.12 Mill wants the British to civilize India, thereby imposing a 107 particular conception of how a people ought to live and what constitutes a 108 good life, without recognizing the validity of different conceptions. Who, 109 ask Mill’s critics, is Mill to say that one has mismanaged one’s life and is in 110 need of benevolent interference, and why should we assume that civilization 111 will always make all humans happy?13 112 While Mill certainly defends imperialism and a vision of historical progress 113 against which he finds India wanting, I shall argue that many of the above 114 criticisms misrepresent Mill’s position. Mill defends what I call “tolerant 115 imperialism” (section 2). He does want England to civilize India, but to civi- 116 lize, for Mill, does not entail forced assimilation (section 3), nor should the 117 despotism it involves deny the rights of or use power arbitrarily against 118 Indians (section 4). Mill’s critics fail to see how Mill tolerates even illiberal 119 practices of Indians and recognizes the importance they play in their lives 120 121 122 123 Britain, and the ‘Improvement’ of the World (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2000); 124 Mehta, Liberalism and Empire, 195–96. 125 8Mehta, Liberalism and Empire, 82. 126 9Ibid., 27–28, 21, 212. 10 127 Ibid., 44, 191. 11 128 Partha Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World (Minneapolis: 129 University of Minnesota Press, 1986), 58–59; and Dipesh Chakrabarty, 130 Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000), 10, 238. 131 12Mehta, Liberalism and Empire, 20. 132 13Souffrant, Formal Transgression, 98–99, 121; cf. Mehta, Liberalism and Empire, 20, 133 44–45; Bruce Baum, Rereading Power and Freedom in J. S. Mill (Toronto: University of 134 Toronto Press, 2000); Jennifer Pitts, “Legislator of the World? A Rereading of 135 Bentham on Colonies,” Political Theory 31 (2003): 224. 4 THE REVIEW OF POLITICS 136 (section 5). There are limits to the toleration Mill would allow, but this reflects, 137 I shall argue, not a lack of respect stemming from racist attitudes (section 6), 138 but rather a tension between liberty and moral development, both of which 139 Mill values—a tension evident not only in Mill’s concept of tolerant imperial- 140 ism for the East but in the liberalism he advocates for the civilized and not so 141 civilized peoples of the West (section 7).
Recommended publications
  • CRITICAL THEORY and AUTHORITARIAN POPULISM Critical Theory and Authoritarian Populism
    CDSMS EDITED BY JEREMIAH MORELOCK CRITICAL THEORY AND AUTHORITARIAN POPULISM Critical Theory and Authoritarian Populism edited by Jeremiah Morelock Critical, Digital and Social Media Studies Series Editor: Christian Fuchs The peer-reviewed book series edited by Christian Fuchs publishes books that critically study the role of the internet and digital and social media in society. Titles analyse how power structures, digital capitalism, ideology and social struggles shape and are shaped by digital and social media. They use and develop critical theory discussing the political relevance and implications of studied topics. The series is a theoretical forum for in- ternet and social media research for books using methods and theories that challenge digital positivism; it also seeks to explore digital media ethics grounded in critical social theories and philosophy. Editorial Board Thomas Allmer, Mark Andrejevic, Miriyam Aouragh, Charles Brown, Eran Fisher, Peter Goodwin, Jonathan Hardy, Kylie Jarrett, Anastasia Kavada, Maria Michalis, Stefania Milan, Vincent Mosco, Jack Qiu, Jernej Amon Prodnik, Marisol Sandoval, Se- bastian Sevignani, Pieter Verdegem Published Critical Theory of Communication: New Readings of Lukács, Adorno, Marcuse, Honneth and Habermas in the Age of the Internet Christian Fuchs https://doi.org/10.16997/book1 Knowledge in the Age of Digital Capitalism: An Introduction to Cognitive Materialism Mariano Zukerfeld https://doi.org/10.16997/book3 Politicizing Digital Space: Theory, the Internet, and Renewing Democracy Trevor Garrison Smith https://doi.org/10.16997/book5 Capital, State, Empire: The New American Way of Digital Warfare Scott Timcke https://doi.org/10.16997/book6 The Spectacle 2.0: Reading Debord in the Context of Digital Capitalism Edited by Marco Briziarelli and Emiliana Armano https://doi.org/10.16997/book11 The Big Data Agenda: Data Ethics and Critical Data Studies Annika Richterich https://doi.org/10.16997/book14 Social Capital Online: Alienation and Accumulation Kane X.
    [Show full text]
  • Sage. Cosmopolitan Liberalism and Its Limits Craig Calhoun Cosmopolit
    Forthcoming in R. Robertson, ed.: Cosmopolitanism. London: Sage. Cosmopolitan Liberalism and its Limits Craig Calhoun Cosmopolitanism is in fashion. It is valued in clothing style and eating habits, leisure travel and business connections, musical taste and ethical commitments. I have previously criticized the too easy conflation of these different dimensions. This tends to give a tone of moral self- righteousness to matters of personal style, and it tends to deflect attention from the extent to which these sorts of cosmopolitanism rest on positions of personal privilege. I have termed this the “class consciousness of frequent travelers”. Here, I want to take up a different but related theme, the renewal of political liberalism as cosmopolitanism. Most versions of cosmopolitanism are contained within liberalism. They are grounded in thinking about individuals – their rights, tastes, and potential travels through the world, and indeed also their ethical obligations. They have much less to say about social transformations that would raise the opportunities and standards of living of the poor or collective struggles that might bring these about. In this they share something with 19th century bourgeois liberalism. Compared to previous aristocratic closure of opportunities it helped underwrite a new openness. But it offered much less to struggles to transform capitalist inequalities. And it was often actively hostile to attempts by craft workers and others to defend their traditional communities.i So it is today with those enthusiastic about a range of new technologies and willing to accept the economic relations that shape their distribution and use. There is a tension running through modern history between struggles to open new individual opportunities – for those with the resources to take them up – and struggles to transform social structures to benefit those much less well off.
    [Show full text]
  • 'The Supreme Principle of Morality'? in the Preface to His Best
    The Supreme Principle of Morality Allen W. Wood 1. What is ‘The Supreme Principle of Morality’? In the Preface to his best known work on moral philosophy, Kant states his purpose very clearly and succinctly: “The present groundwork is, however, nothing more than the search for and establishment of the supreme principle of morality, which already constitutes an enterprise whole in its aim and to be separated from every other moral investigation” (Groundwork 4:392). This paper will deal with the outcome of the first part of this task, namely, Kant’s attempt to formulate the supreme principle of morality, which is the intended outcome of the search. It will consider this formulation in light of Kant’s conception of the historical antecedents of his attempt. Our first task, however, must be to say a little about the meaning of the term ‘supreme principle of morality’. For it is not nearly as evident to many as it was to Kant that there is such a thing at all. And it is extremely common for people, whatever position they may take on this issue, to misunderstand what a ‘supreme principle of morality’ is, what it is for, and what role it is supposed to play in moral theorizing and moral reasoning. Kant never directly presents any argument that there must be such a principle, but he does articulate several considerations that would seem to justify supposing that there is. Kant holds that moral questions are to be decided by reason. Reason, according to Kant, always seeks unity under principles, and ultimately, systematic unity under the fewest possible number of principles (Pure Reason A298-302/B355-359, A645- 650/B673-678).
    [Show full text]
  • The Restless Liberalism of Alexis De Tocqueville
    FILOZOFIA ___________________________________________________________________________Roč. 72, 2017, č. 9 THE RESTLESS LIBERALISM OF ALEXIS DE TOCQUEVILLE JAKUB TLOLKA, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK TLOLKA, J.: The Restless Liberalism of Alexis de Tocqueville FILOZOFIA, 72, No. 9, 2017, pp. 736-747 This essay attempts to contextualise the purported novelty of Alexis de Tocqueville’s particular brand of liberalism. It regards the author not as an heir or precursor to any given political tradition, but rather as a compelled syncretist whose primary philosophical concern was the moral significance of the democratic age. It suggests that Tocqueville devised his ‘new political science’ with a keen view to the existential implications of modernity. In order to support that suggestion, the essay explores the genealogy of Tocqueville’s moral and political thought and draws a relation between his analysis of democracy and his personal experience of modernity. Keywords: A. de Tocqueville – Modernity – Liberalism – Inquiétude – Religion Introduction. Relatively few authors in the history of political thought have produced an intellectual legacy of such overarching resonance as Alexis de Tocqueville. Even fewer, perhaps, have so persistently eluded ordinary analytical and exegetical frameworks, presenting to each astute observer a face so nuanced as to preclude serious interpretive consensus. As writes Lakoff (Lakoff 1998), ‘disagreement over textual interpretation in the study of political thought is not uncommon’. However, ‘it usually arises around those who left writings of a patently divergent character’ (p. 437). When we thus consider the ‘extraordinarily coherent and consistent nature’ of Alexis de Tocqueville’s political philosophy, it appears somewhat odd that the academic consensus surrounding that author relates almost exclusively to the grandeur of his intellectual achievement (Lukacs 1959, 6).
    [Show full text]
  • Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 4-12-2006 Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea Berit Van Neste University of South Florida Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Religion Commons Scholar Commons Citation Neste, Berit Van, "Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea" (2006). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3782 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cicero and St. Augustine's Just War Theory: Classical Influences on a Christian Idea by Berit Van Neste A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Religious Studies College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: James F. Strange, Ph.D. Paul G. Schneider, Ph.D. Michael J. Decker, Ph.D. Date of Approval: April 12, 2006 Keywords: theology, philosophy, politics, patristic, medieval © Copyright 2006 , Berit Van Neste For Elizabeth and Calista Table of Contents Abstract ii Chapter 1 1 Introduction 1 Cicero’s Influence on Augustine 7 Chapter 2 13 Justice 13 Natural and Temporal Law 19 Commonwealth 34 Chapter 3 49 Just War 49 Chapter 4 60 Conclusion 60 References 64 i Cicero and St.
    [Show full text]
  • On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant
    On Unitarian Universalist Moral Duties: Looking Forward with Cicero and Kant Myriam Renaud I. Why Moral Duties? Aren‟t We Done With That Conversation? For the purposes of this paper, I will rely on the following definition of moral duty (or obligation): an action which is required (imperative) and which is guided by certain moral rules and principles. In every day language, we capture the concept of duty or obligation when we say things like, “I should [or „ought‟] to do this because it‟s the right thing to do,” or “I want to do right by so and so.” These ordinary expressions reflect the view that awareness of the rightness of an action may be enough to provide the impetus to carry through that action—namely, that “in acting from a motive attached to a moral principle,”—in acting on what we take to be the right thing to do—“the moral rightness of the action gives the agent reason for action” [Herman, 30]. Admittedly, the word alone—duty—is likely to cause unpleasant shivers to course down the spines of most Unitarian Universalists. It brings to mind something we have to do, something we‟d rather not do, something we‟re made to do, probably at the expense of some activity we would actually enjoy. But, if we push past the unpleasant shiver, we recognize that duty, or obligation, is tied to the moral structure which governs our lives and which we try to impart to our children both at home and in the religious education classes offered in our congregations.
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Oakeshott 'On Being Conservative'
    Podoksik, Ephraim. "Michael Oakeshott ‘On Being Conservative’." Conservative Moments: Reading Conservative Texts. Ed. Mark Garnett. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2018. 67–74. Textual Moments in the History of Political Thought. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 2 Oct. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781350001565.ch-009>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 2 October 2021, 23:12 UTC. Copyright © Mark Garnett 2018. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 67 CHAPTER NINE Michael Oakeshott ‘On Being Conservative’ Ephraim Podoksik The self- government of men of passionate belief and enterprise is apt to break down when it is most needed. It often suffi ces to resolve minor collisions of interest, but beyond these it is not to be relied upon. A more precise and a less easily corrupted ritual is required to resolve the massive collisions which our manner of living is apt to generate and to release us from the massive frustrations in which we are apt to become locked. The custodian of this ritual is ‘the government’, and the rules it imposes are ‘the law’. One may imagine a government engaged in the activity of an arbiter in cases of collisions of interest but doing its business without the aid of laws, just as one may imagine a game without rules and an umpire who was appealed to in cases of dispute and who on each occasion merely used his judgment to devise ad hoc a way of releasing the disputants from their mutual frustration.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmopolitanism’ As an Analytic for the Comparative Study of Globalization and Education
    Rethinking ‘Cosmopolitanism’ as an Analytic for the Comparative Study of Globalization and Education Noah W. Sobe Loyola University Chicago This article proposes that for scholars in comparative and international education the study of “cosmpolitanisms” offers a productive avenue for thinking outside of the traditional paradigms of area studies and for understanding the new world-generating optics and multi-layered geographies that appear to be emerging with globalization. The piece explores the concept of “vernacular cosmopolitanisms” and discusses recent scholarship – on 21st century American education and on early-20th-century Yugoslav education – that have used cosmopolitanism as an analytic category. The article argues that studying actually, existing cosmopolitanisms is a useful strategy for examining the ways that solidarities are formed, identities are developed, and principles of inclusion and exclusion are elaborated amidst local and global assemblages. ne of the key analytic challenges that globalization presents is the need to develop social science research strategies appropriate to understanding emergent social, political and culturalO forms. In this article I argue that the study of cosmopolitanisms offers a productive avenue for thinking outside of the traditional paradigms of area studies and for understanding the new world-generating optics and multi-layered geographies that appear to be emerging with globalization. These new, often non-territorial configurations bring people, knowledge, institutions, and objects together
    [Show full text]
  • Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected]
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 11-1-2006 Ciceronian Business Ethics Owen Goldin Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studies in the History of Ethics (November 2006). Publisher link. © 2006 HistoryofEthics.org. Used with permission. Studies in the History of Ethics Ciceronian Bu siness Ethics Owen Goldin (Mar quette University) The teaching and practice of business must resist ethical compartmentalization. One engaged in business ought not check moral principles at the door and say “business is business,” for this is to pretend that when one is engaged in business, one is no longer a human being, with the rational nature, emotional constitution, and social bonds that are at the root of our ethical nature. Ethical standards apply to business as they do all aspects of human life. Nonetheless, making money is the goal of business, and more often than not, one is trying to take money from another, at the least possible cost. Such action is necessarily self-centered, if not selfish, and requires acting in a way that we would not want to see people act in all of their dealings with others, especially in regard to family, friends, and others with whom they have special social bonds. Granting that business practices are not compartmentalized against all ethical considerations, the fact that business demands maximization of profit entails that special rules apply. Determining what these are, in what circumstances they are less demanding than the ethical principles of everyday life, and in what circumstances they are more demanding, is the domain of business ethics, as a special domain of ethical philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • Cosmopolitanism: Rethinking the Agenda of Education Abroad Brian Whalen1 & Michael Woolf 2
    Critical Essay Frontiers: The Interdisciplinary Journal of Study Abroad © 2020 Brian Whalen & Michael Woolf The work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial- NoDerivatives 4.0 International License. Volume 32, Issue 3, pp. 72-98 DOI 10.36366/frontiers.v32i3.580 Cosmopolitanism: Rethinking the Agenda of Education Abroad Brian Whalen1 & Michael Woolf 2 Abstract Cosmopolitanism is an ambiguous and inherently paradoxical notion. Because of the complexities it raises, it generates analyses and discourses that challenge simplistic assumptions embedded in theory and practice of education abroad. Global citizenship, comprehensive internationalization, cultural relativity, immersion, cross-cultural learning, and community engagement are some of the concepts deconstructed through the lens of cosmopolitan ideas and histories. Cosmopolitan philosophies are also of particular and special relevance to student experience in international education. In short, cosmopolitanism is not one idea but a field of meaning, a cluster of profound propositions that might collectively enrich the curriculum of education abroad. Keywords: cosmopolitanism; history and philosophy; deconstructing the agenda; nationalism, cultural history Introduction: What is Cosmopolitanism? What is it not? Cosmopolitanism... is a philosophy and ethical orientation that takes account of the dense enmeshment of human beings - the connections 1 CAPA: THE GLOBAL EDUCATION NETWORK, LONDON, UK 2 AMERICAN INTERNATIONAL RECRUITMENT COUNCIL (AIRC), BETHESDA, MD, USA Corresponding author: Michael Woolf, CAPA: The Global Education Network, [email protected] Frontiers: The Interdisciplinary Journal of Study Abroad 32(3) Whalen & Woolf between them, the bonds that link them, the interests that divide them, and the clashes of ethical and political outlook. Cosmopolitanism is a philosophy for the age of human interconnectedness, and generates a politics for a ‘small world’ (Brown & Held, 2010, p.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Smashing Cosmopolitanism: the Neo-Liberal Destruction of Cosmopolitan Education in East-Central Europe
    Smashing Cosmopolitanism: The Neo-liberal Destruction of Cosmopolitan Education in East-Central Europe Robert J. Imre University of Newcastle Zsuzsa Millei University of Newcastle Critiques that seek to examine cosmopolitanism as a concept suffer from a severe popularity problem. Rather than engage in this pro/con debate, we are interested in demonstrating that cosmopolitanism can wax and wane, ebb and flow, and has appeared as a grounding ideology for educational programs before, only to be torn asunder by those seeking to consolidate regime change. We do not suggest that cosmopolitanism is good and righteous politics, normatively opposed to or supporting patriotism, nor is it ideologically left, right or centre. We see a burgeoning cosmopolitan outlook in a particular time and place, that was smashed by political and social forces both unforeseen and powerful, changing foundational concepts of education in East-Central Europe in general and Hungary in particular. s a popular concept in the English-speaking world, cosmopolitanism conjures up notions of a well-read, well-fed, bourgeoisie with economic and social capacities to move around the worldA using their networks and sophisticated understandings of cultural diversity. A cosmopolitan understanding of the world encompasses a commitment to universal human rights, universal human potential, and a deeply embedded acceptance of difference and diversity. These ideas are core parts of a universalist frame of reference, and a philosophical underpinning of a particular view of the modern world held during the Industrial Revolution until today (Held, 2003). This paper challenges the idea that cosmopolitanism exists exclusively in the post-Cold War period in East-Central Europe, and also challenges the idea that the Hungarian education system was a monolithic neo-Stalinist version of ‘ideology expression’.
    [Show full text]