The Real Distinction Between Perdurance and Endurance

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Real Distinction Between Perdurance and Endurance Proceedings of the Kent State University May 4th Philosophy Graduate Student Conference The Real Distinction Between Perdurance and Endurance Jeremy Buxbaum University of Colorado at Boulder Abstract Theories of persistence fall into two general categories. Perdurance theories hold that an object persists in virtue of having temporal parts, and that no one temporal part of an object is present at more than one time. Endurance theories hold that an object persists in virtue of being wholly present at more than one time. The debate then, seems to center on whether or not persisting objects are wholly present at more than one time. But what is it for an object to be wholly present? Persistence theorists on both sides of the debate have claimed to not understand what exactly this feature of objects is. Ned Markosian says of ‘wholly present’, “This expression is crucial to [three- dimensionalism], but many find it somewhat mysterious.” Indeed there is something peculiar about the notion, but almost all of the literature on persistence makes use of the notion of an object being wholly present. In what follows, I want to look at three proposed definitions of ‘wholly present’, offered by Trenton Merricks, Ted Sider, and Ned Markosian, respectively. I will argue that all three are unsatisfactory because they fail in distinguishing perdurance from endurance, commit us to controversial doctrines, or fail in being informative. I will then propose a fourth definition of ‘wholly present’, one which I think adequately distinguishes between perdurance and endurance, and which is informative. This proposal will ultimately rely on a distinction between ‘existing’ and ‘existing at a time’. Theories of persistence fall into two general categories. whether or not persisting objects are wholly present at more Perdurance theories hold that an object persists in virtue of than one time. having temporal parts, and that no one temporal part of an But what is it for an object to be wholly present? object is present at more than one time. Endurance theories Persistence theorists on both sides of the debate have claimed to hold that an object persists in virtue of being wholly present at not understand what exactly this feature of objects is. E.J. Lowe more than one time.1 The debate then, seems to center on expresses concern about this notion: “I can find no useful application for the notion of such a thing being ‘wholly present’ 1 Notice that within these general groups the persistence theorist is left with at a time, any more than I can for that of its being ‘partially non- the task of explaining how it is that an object has temporal parts or how it is present’ (in the sense, of course, of having earlier or later that an object is wholly present at more than one time. This results in the standard internecine debates. But, one can stake out a position in the more general debate without necessarily entering into the in-house debates about which particular perdurance or endurance theory is correct. 1 Jeremy Buxbaum parts).”2 In discussing the notion of ‘wholly present’ Ted Sider the doctrine of presentism.” 6 Indeed a number of theorists on says, “ This is an unfortunate way to formulate three- both sides of the debate have offered definitions. But none of dimensionalism. What is it for an object x to be ‘wholly present’ these attempts seem satisfactory because they fail in at time t?”3 He goes on to say, “ A three-dimensionalist might distinguishing perdurance from endurance, commit us to give up on the attempt to give a mereological account of an controversial doctrines, or fail in being informative. object’s being wholly present and understand the notion in In what follows, I want to look at three proposed some other way. One wonders whether ‘wholly present’ would definitions of ‘wholly present’, offered by Trenton Merricks, then be an apt term.”4 Ned Markosian says of ‘wholly present’, Ted Sider, and Ned Markosian, respectively. I will argue that “ This expression is crucial to [three-dimensionalism], but many all three are unsatisfactory. I will then propose a fourth find it somewhat mysterious.”5 Indeed there is something definition of ‘wholly present’, one which I think adequately peculiar about the notion. None the less, almost all of the distinguishes between perdurance and endurance, and which is literature on persistence makes use of the notion of an object informative. This proposal will ultimately rely on a distinction being wholly present, either by denying that objects are ever between ‘existing’ and ‘existing at a time’. wholly present (perdurance) or affirming that they are (endurance). I. Three Failed Attempts At Defining ‘Wholly Present’ This leaves us in an uncomfortable situation. Either we must give a perspicuous definition of ‘wholly present’, or we Trenton Merricks finds the standard, negative definition must deny that the debate between perdurance theories and of ‘wholly present’ unsatisfactory. The standard account of endurance theories turns on this notion. To complicate matters, being ‘wholly present’ can be taken to amount to ‘not having there is some pressure, particularly from Trenton Merricks, to temporal parts’. Merricks says, “ Enduring, it would seem, just give more than a negative definition, such as ‘not consisting of is lasting over time, but not by way of temporal parts. I think an temporal parts’. That is to say, there is some contention over account of endurance can be provided that says more than that what would count as a perspicuous definition of ‘wholly enduring objects are not perduring objects.” 7 Certainly there is present’. Furthermore, Merricks insists that ‘wholly present’ a sense in which Merricks is right to suggest that this negative cannot be defined without recourse to presentism. He says, “ I account of ‘wholly present’, and hence of endurance, is think that there is no way at all to make sense of an object’s uninformative. Knowing that enduring objects are not ‘being wholly present at every time at which it exists’ without perduring objects does not necessarily tell one what the nature of an enduring object is, and subsequently, does not really tell 2 Lowe, E.J., “ Lewis On Perdurance Versus Endurance” , Analysis 47 (1987), p. one what it is for an object to be wholly present. Specifically, 152. 3 Sider, Theodore, “ Four-Dimensionalism” , The Philosophical Review 106 (1997), p. 209. 6 Merricks, Trenton, “ Persistence, Parts and Presentism” , Nous 33:3, (1999). p. 4 Sider, p. 213. 229. 5 Markosian, Ned, “ The 3D/4D Controversy and Non-Present Objects” , 7 Merricks, Trenton, “ Endurance and Indiscernibility” , Journal of Philosophy, Philosophical Papers 23:3, (1994). April, (1994). 2 Proceedings of the Kent State University May 4th Philosophy Graduate Student Conference not having temporal parts may be a necessary feature of namely, presentism. With regard to the first assumption, he enduring objects, but it hardly seems sufficient. For it is says: possible that there be objects which don’t have any parts at all, but which certainly do not strike us as enduring objects. We can It does not follow from the fact that, necessarily, O exists iff O’s parts exist, imagine there being momentary micro-particles which by that O has all of its parts necessarily. That is, it does not follow from ‘in every world, O exists iff O’s parts’ that ‘in every world, O exist iff O’s parts definition do not persist, and hence cannot be enduring objects, in every world exist’. Likewise, it does not follow from ‘at every time, O whether or not they have parts. We might very well desire a exist iff O’s parts exist’ that ‘at every time, O exists iff its parts at every time more informative definition, and as metaphysicians, it would exist.8 not be odd to insist upon it. In light of these considerations, Merricks offers what he Here I think Merricks nicely exploits a point about modal scope. takes to be an informative definition of ‘wholly present’. For With this point understood I think it becomes clear that his Merricks, an object O is wholly present iff all of O’s parts exist. definition of ‘wholly present’ does not commit us to According to him, this notion serves to distinguish perduring mereological essentialism. and enduring objects, for if O is a perduring object that exists But in order to avoid this commitment, and at the same now and existed at some time in the past, then O has a past time have ‘wholly present’ as the distinguishing feature temporal part which does not exist now. On the other hand, between perduring and enduring objects, Merricks finds himself since enduring objects don’t have temporal parts, it is not the committed to presentism. Presentism holds that the only objects case that if O is an enduring object then O has some temporal that exist are presently existing objects. This commitment can part which does not exist now. If O is an enduring object and O be brought out by considering the following quotation: “ A exists now, then all of O’s parts exist now. perduring object is not wholly present at each time at which it Merricks’ only concern with this definition has to do with exists. Assume O is a four-dimensional object that existed in the the possible commitment to mereological essentialism. past, and exists now. O has a past temporal part P that does not Mereological essentialism is the doctrine that whatever is a part exist now.” This is true only if presentism is true, for if there are of O at any time at which O exists is a part of O at every time at objects which exist which do not presently exist, then it would which O exists.
Recommended publications
  • Parts of Persons Identity and Persistence in a Perdurantist World
    UNIVERSITÀ DEGLI STUDI DI MILANO Doctoral School in Philosophy and Human Sciences (XXXI Cycle) Department of Philosophy “Piero Martinetti” Parts of Persons Identity and persistence in a perdurantist world Ph.D. Candidate Valerio BUONOMO Tutors Prof. Giuliano TORRENGO Prof. Paolo VALORE Coordinator of the Doctoral School Prof. Marcello D’AGOSTINO Academic year 2017-2018 1 Content CONTENT ........................................................................................................................... 2 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS ........................................................................................................... 4 INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1. PERSONAL IDENTITY AND PERSISTENCE...................................................................... 8 1.1. The persistence of persons and the criteria of identity over time .................................. 8 1.2. The accounts of personal persistence: a standard classification ................................... 14 1.2.1. Mentalist accounts of personal persistence ............................................................................ 15 1.2.2. Somatic accounts of personal persistence .............................................................................. 15 1.2.3. Anti-criterialist accounts of personal persistence ................................................................... 16 1.3. The metaphysics of persistence: the mereological account .........................................
    [Show full text]
  • Duration, Temporality and Self
    Duration, Temporality and Self: Prospects for the Future of Bergsonism by Elena Fell A thesis submitted in partial fulfilment for the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy at the University of Central Lancashire 2007 2 Student Declaration Concurrent registration for two or more academic awards I declare that white registered as a candidate for the research degree, I have not been a registered candidate or enrolled student for another award of the University or other academic or professional institution. Material submitted for another award I declare that no material contained in the thesis has been used in any other submission for an academic award and is solely my own work Signature of Candidate Type of Award Doctor of Philosophy Department Centre for Professional Ethics Abstract In philosophy time is one of the most difficult subjects because, notoriously, it eludes rationalization. However, Bergson succeeds in presenting time effectively as reality that exists in its own right. Time in Bergson is almost accessible, almost palpable in a discourse which overcomes certain difficulties of language and traditional thought. Bergson equates time with duration, a genuine temporal succession of phenomena defined by their position in that succession, and asserts that time is a quality belonging to the nature of all things rather than a relation between supposedly static elements. But Rergson's theory of duration is not organised, nor is it complete - fragments of it are embedded in discussions of various aspects of psychology, evolution, matter, and movement. My first task is therefore to extract the theory of duration from Bergson's major texts in Chapters 2-4.
    [Show full text]
  • Travelling in Time: How to Wholly Exist in Two Places at the Same Time
    Travelling in Time: How to Wholly Exist in Two Places at the Same Time 1 Introduction It is possible to wholly exist at multiple spatial locations at the same time. At least, if time travel is possible and objects endure, then such must be the case. To accommodate this possibility requires the introduction of a spatial analog of either relativising properties to times—relativising properties to spatial locations—or of relativising the manner of instantiation to times—relativising the manner of instantiation to spatial locations. It has been suggested, however, that introducing irreducibly spatially relativised or spatially adverbialised properties presents some difficulties for the endurantist. I will consider an objection according to which embracing such spatially relativised properties could lead us to reject mereology altogether in favour of a metaphysics according to which objects are wholly present at every space-time point at which they exist. I argue that although such a view is coherent, there are some good reasons to reject it. Moreover, I argue that the endurantist can introduce spatially relativised or adverbialised properties without conceding that objects lack spatial parts. Such a strategy has the additional advantage that it allows the endurantist not only to explain time travel, but also to reconcile our competing intuitions about cases of fission. The possibility of travelling back in time to a period in which one’s earlier self or one’s ancestors exist, raises a number of well-worn problems (Grey, 1999; Chambers, 1999; Horwich, 1975 and Sider, 2002). In this paper I am concerned with only one of these: how is it that an object can travel back in time to meet its earlier self, thus existing at two different spatial locations at one and the same time? Four-dimensionalists have an easy answer to this question.
    [Show full text]
  • Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: Why the Unsubstantiality of the First Debate Implies That of the Second1
    1 Presentism/Eternalism and Endurantism/Perdurantism: why the 1 unsubstantiality of the first debate implies that of the second Forthcoming in Philosophia Naturalis Mauro Dorato (Ph.D) Department of Philosophy University of Rome Three [email protected] tel. +393396070133 http://host.uniroma3.it/dipartimenti/filosofia/personale/doratoweb.htm Abstract The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”. In this respect, I will conclude that also the debate about persistence in time has no ontological consequences, in the sense that there is no real ontological disagreement between the two allegedly opposite positions: as in the case of the presentism/eternalism debate, one can be both a perdurantist and an endurantist, depending on which linguistic framework is preferred. The main claim that I want to defend in this paper is that the there are logical equivalences between eternalism and perdurantism on the one hand and presentism and endurantism on the other. By “logical equivalence” I mean that one position is entailed and entails the other. As a consequence of this equivalence, it becomes important to inquire into the question whether the dispute between endurantists and perdurantists is authentic, given that Savitt (2006) Dolev (2006) and Dorato (2006) have cast doubts on the fact that the debate between presentism and eternalism is about “what there is”.
    [Show full text]
  • Unity of Mind, Temporal Awareness, and Personal Identity
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, IRVINE THE LEGACY OF HUMEANISM: UNITY OF MIND, TEMPORAL AWARENESS, AND PERSONAL IDENTITY DISSERTATION submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY in Philosophy by Daniel R. Siakel Dissertation Committee: Professor David Woodruff Smith, Chair Professor Sven Bernecker Associate Professor Marcello Oreste Fiocco Associate Professor Clinton Tolley 2016 © 2016 Daniel R. Siakel DEDICATION To My mother, Anna My father, Jim Life’s original, enduring constellation. And My “doctor father,” David Who sees. “We think that we can prove ourselves to ourselves. The truth is that we cannot say that we are one entity, one existence. Our individuality is really a heap or pile of experiences. We are made out of experiences of achievement, disappointment, hope, fear, and millions and billions and trillions of other things. All these little fragments put together are what we call our self and our life. Our pride of self-existence or sense of being is by no means one entity. It is a heap, a pile of stuff. It has some similarities to a pile of garbage.” “It’s not that everything is one. Everything is zero.” Chögyam Trungpa Rinpoche “Galaxies of Stars, Grains of Sand” “Rhinoceros and Parrot” ii TABLE OF CONTENTS Page ACKNOWLEDGMENTS v CURRICULUM VITAE vi ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION xii INTRODUCTION 1 CHAPTER I: Hume’s Appendix Problem and Associative Connections in the Treatise and Enquiry §1. General Introduction to Hume’s Science of Human Nature 6 §2. Introducing Hume’s Appendix Problem 8 §3. Contextualizing Hume’s Appendix Problem 15 §4.
    [Show full text]
  • Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W
    W. Zimmerman dialectica Vol. 59, N° 4 (2005), pp. 401–457 The A-Theory of Time, The B-Theory of Time, and ‘Taking Tense Seriously’ Dean W. Zimmerman† ABSTRACT The paper has two parts: First, I describe a relatively popular thesis in the philosophy of propositional attitudes, worthy of the name ‘taking tense seriously’; and I distinguish it from a family of views in the metaphysics of time, namely, the A-theories (or what are sometimes called ‘tensed theories of time’). Once the distinction is in focus, a skeptical worry arises. Some A- theorists maintain that the difference between past, present, and future, is to be drawn in terms of what exists: growing-block theorists eschew ontological commitment to future entities; pre- sentists, to future and past entities. Others think of themselves as A-theorists but exclude no past or future things from their ontology. The metaphysical skeptic suspects that their attempt to articulate an ‘eternalist’ version of the A-theory collapses into merely ‘taking tense seriously’ – a thesis that does not imply the A-theory. The second half of the paper is the search for a stable eternalist A-theory. It includes discussion of temporary intrinsics, temporal parts, and truth. 1. Introduction Sadly, the great metaphysician J. McT. E. McTaggart is now remembered mainly for what must be his worst argument: the infamous argument for ‘the unreality of time’. But even this ‘philosophical “howler” ’ (as C. D. Broad rightly called it1) includes enough insightful analysis to have made it a natural starting point for most subsequent work on the metaphysics of time.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporal Parts and Spatial Location
    Temporal parts and spatial location Damiano Costa Abstract. The literature offers us several characterizations of temporal parts via spatial co-location: by these accounts, temporal parts are roughly parts that are of the same spatial size as their wholes. It has been argued that such definitions would fail with entities outside space. The present paper investigates the extent to which such criticism works. Keywords: temporal parts, spatial location, events, four-dimensionalism, perdurance. § 0. Introduction Temporal parts of an entity – according to current vulgate – incorporate “all of that entity” for as long as they exist (Heller 1984; Sider 2001; Olson 2006). For example, a temporal part of Sam incorporates “all of Sam” for as long as it exists. One immediate consequence of this fact is that some “smaller parts” of Sam, like his brain and hearth, do not count as temporal parts of Sam, because they do not incorporate “all of Sam” at a certain time. A suitable definition for temporal parts must exclude such “smaller parts”. In this regard, two approaches have been put forward, a mereological one (Simons 1987; Sider 1997; Parsons 2007) and a spatial one (Thomson 1983; Heller 1984; McGrath 2007). On the one hand, the mereological approach says that such “smaller parts” of Sam are not temporal parts because they don’t overlap every part of Sam at a certain time. On the other hand, the spatial approach roughly says that such “smaller parts” of Sam are not temporal parts because a temporal part is of the same spatial size as its whole for as long as that part exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Objects, Events, and Property-Instances
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 13 Events and Objects in Perception, Cognition, and Language Article 2 2019 Objects, Events, and Property-Instances Riccardo Baratella University of Tubingen̈ Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc Part of the Metaphysics Commons, and the Philosophy of Language Commons This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Baratella, Riccardo (2019) "Objects, Events, and Property-Instances," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 13. https://doi.org/10.4148/1944-3676.1121 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication December 2019 Volume 13: Events and Objects in Perception, Cognition, and Language pages 1-16 DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.4148/1944-3676.1121 RICCARDO BARATELLA University of Tübingen OBJECTS,EVENTS, AND PROPERTY-INSTANCES ABSTRACT: The theory of events as property-instances has been considered one of the most widely accepted metaphysical theories of events. On the other hand, several philosophers claim that if both events and objects perdure, then objects must be iden- tified with events. In this work, I investigate whether these two views can be held together. I shall argue that if they can, it de- pends on the particular theory of instantiation one is to adopt.
    [Show full text]
  • Objects in Time : Studies of Persistence in B-Time
    Objects in Time : Studies of Persistence in B-time Hansson Wahlberg, Tobias 2009 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Hansson Wahlberg, T. (2009). Objects in Time : Studies of Persistence in B-time. Department of Philosophy, Lund University. Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. LUND UNIVERSITY PO Box 117 221 00 Lund +46 46-222 00 00 Objects in Time Studies of Persistence in B-time Tobias Hansson Wahlberg Lund University Department of Philosophy 1 Objects in Time: Studies of Persistence in B-time Tobias Hansson Wahlberg © 2009 Tobias Hansson Wahlberg Cover picture: Sydney Harbour Bridge. © Hansson Wahlberg Printed by Media-Tryck, Lund, November 2009. ISBN 978-91-628-7972-3 2 For Lena, Idun and Hannes 3 4 Contents Acknowledgements .................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Endurantism, Perdurantism and Special Relativity
    The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. , No. October ISSN – ENDURANTISM, PERDURANTISM AND SPECIAL RELATIVITY B S D. H T A. J There are two main theories about the persistence of objects through time. Endurantists hold that objects are three-dimensional, have only spatial parts, and wholly exist at each moment of their existence. Perdurantists hold that objects are four-dimensional, have temporal parts, and exist only partly at each moment of their existence. We argue that endurantism is poorly suited to describe the persistence of objects in a world governed by special relativity, and it can accommodate a relativistic world only at a high price not worth paying. Perdurantism, on the other hand, fits beautifully with our current scientific understanding of the world. We use only the implications of the Lorentz transformations, without appeal to geometrical interpretations, dimensional analogies or auxiliary premises like temporal eternalism. I. INTRODUCTION Philosophical puzzles about the persistence and change of physical objects have received much recent attention from metaphysicians. There are two main competing theories about how non-momentary objects relate to time: endurantism (or three-dimensionalism), and perdurantism (or four- dimensionalism). David Lewis roughly characterizes these terms thus: Let us say that something persists iff, somehow or other, it exists at various times; this is the neutral word. Something perdures iff it persists by having different temporal parts, or stages, at different times, though no part of it is wholly present at more than one time; whereas it endures iff it persists by being wholly present at more than one time.1 Endurantism, then, is the view that objects have three spatial dimensions and move through time.
    [Show full text]
  • Temporal Parts and Timeless Parthood
    Temporal Parts and Timeless Parthood Eric T. Olson University of Sheffield abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless parthood: a thing's having a part without temporal qualification. Some find this hard to understand, and thus find the view that persisting things have temporal parts--four- dimensionalism--unintelligible. T. Sider offers to help by defining temporal parthood in terms of a thing's having a part at a time. I argue that no such account can capture the notion of a temporal part that figures in orthodox four-dimensionalism: temporal parts must be timeless parts. This enables us to state four-dimensionalism more clearly. 1. “Four-dimensionalists” say that things persist by having temporal parts spread out across time. A thing exists at a time, they say, by having a temporal part located just at that time. So I exist in 1975 by having a temporal part that exists throughout that year and only then; I exist now by having another temporal part that exists only now. “Three- dimensionalists,” by contrast, say that at least some things persist without having temporal parts. The event that is the history of a person or a dog might have temporal parts, but people and dogs themselves have none. Better, three-dimensionalism says that some persisting things lack proper temporal parts: maybe anything that exists at some time is a temporal part of itself, just as anything whatever a part of itself. Three- and four-dimensionalists disagree about whether persisting things have temporal parts other than themselves.
    [Show full text]
  • Relativity and Three Four-Dimensionalisms
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by RERO DOC Digital Library Published in Philosophy Compass 11, issue 2, 102-120, 2016 1 which should be used for any reference to this work Relativity and Three Four-dimensionalisms Cody Gilmore1*, Damiano Costa2 and Claudio Calosi3 1UC Davis 2University of Fribourg 3University of Neuchâtel Abstract Relativity theory is often said to support something called ‘the four-dimensional view of reality’. But there are at least three different views that sometimes go by this name. One is ‘spacetime unitism’ (as we call it), according to which there is a spacetime manifold, and if there are such things as points of space or instants of time, these are just spacetime regions of different sorts: thus space and time are not separate manifolds. A second is the B-theory of time, according to which the past, present, and future are all equally real and there is nothing metaphysically special about the present. A third is perdurantism, according to which persisting material objects (rocks, trees, and human beings) are made up of different temporal parts located at different times. We sketch routes from relativity to unitism and to the B-theory. We then discuss some routes to perdurantism, via the B-theory and via unitism. Introduction Relativity theory1 is often said to support something called ‘the four-dimensional view’ of reality. But there are three independent views that go by this name: (i) spacetime unitism, as we call it, according to which spacetime is more fundamental than space or time, and points of space and instants of time, if they exist at all, are just spacetime regions of different sorts; (ii) the B-theory of time, according to which the past, present, and future are all equally real and there is nothing objectively special about the present; and (iii) perdurantism, according to which material objects are four-dimensional wholes made up of different temporal parts.
    [Show full text]