Foreword a Perspective on ‘Plasticity’

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Foreword a Perspective on ‘Plasticity’ Foreword A perspective on ‘plasticity’ Mary Jane West-Eberhard Smithsonian Tropical Research Institute Anyone interested in the nature of living organisms and their adaptive evolution will be stimulated by reading this book. I am no exception. But I have an advantage, the opportunity to write a Foreword, with freedom to comment—or even emote, opine, and reminisce—about the topics at hand without even the corrective of peer review to put a brake on runaway ruminations. I apologize in advance for citing my own work in sections where I am trying to substantiate a thought without doing a proper review. Start with the word ‘plasticity.’ It seems designed to befuddle the uninitiated because it does not bring to mind any obvious characteristic of living organisms, which are not plastic quite in the manner of elastic belts, rubber bands, bubble gum, or food packaging. I could be accused of having promoted the word plasticity by using it as one of four in a book title: Developmental Plasticity and Evolution (West- Eberhard 2003). But those four words cost more hours of agonizing indecision than any other set of four in a book of more than 300,000 words (yes, too long—so it was designed to be read in pieces). The problem with ‘plasticity’ was that it already had a definition, in terms of reaction norms of primarily quantitative traits. But that definition did not readily suggest all that needed attention, which included plastic- ity-facilitated developmental reorganization of qualitatively distinctive phenotypes. [Schlichting (2021) in this volume, citing Uller and colleagues (2020), notes some of the same reservations that I had about beginning with reaction norms.] I decided to adopt a broad version of the established definition: the ability to respond to an envi- ronmental input with a phenotypic change. For my purposes, plasticity might better have been called ‘responsiveness’ or ‘condition sensitivity.’ But plasticity already had a public. And the plasticity public was being enlarged at the time by important books and reviews. So I stuck with the word ‘plasticity.’ This quandary over terms indicates why the word ‘developmental’ as a modi- fier of plasticity is important. Development implies attention to mechanisms and invites looking at responsiveness to both external and internal environments— responsiveness of the phenotype at all levels of organization from the molecular to the behavioral, including internal responsiveness to gene products. Attention to developmental plasticity picks up Darwin’s thoughts where they left off—with a struggle to understand the causes of selectable variation. Those struggles were summarized in Darwin’s theory of pangenesis, which includes what we could now call a molecular theory of the gene, postulating tiny gemmules that, like genes, were seen as being found throughout the body and as mediating both the transmis- sion and the expression of traits. The history of Darwin’s ideas about development ix x Foreword and evolution, including the idea of phenotypic plasticity, is traced in Costa’s (2021) masterful chapter in this volume, beginning with Darwin’s ideas as a young man and intertwined in his thoughts about variation and selection until the end of his life, most remarkably in his two volumes on variation (Darwin 1868). Costa then traces the fate of those ideas through the history of evolutionary biology into the present, giving an unprecedented account of the history of developmental plasticity in evo- lutionary biology. Costa’s history is exciting because it shows the connections between Darwin’s ideas and current ones that seem to us to be ‘new’ (see also West-Eberhard 2003, Chapter 8; 2008b). Rediscoveries are no less exciting when their origins can be traced to Darwin or before. But Darwin’s achievement in this area is a lesson in humility for those who suffer from the amnesia that seems to generate new- discovery cycles with a periodicity of about 30 years for almost any idea in evolutionary biology. We now benefit from data that Darwin lacked, including concrete information on gene expression that allows us to see how the material basis for transmission and expres- sion is the same—the dual nature fulfilled by the ‘gemmules’ he imagined. I think that Darwin would have been especially fascinated by the chapter in this book (Lister 2021) showing how fossils can now be used to substantiate the importance of developmental flexibility in the origin of morphological transitions. The same could be said regarding a chapter by Bonduriansky (2021) on non-genetic inheritance and epigenetic effects of the environment, a good entrée into an area that has enormously expanded in the last two decades. This book is sprinkled with histories. Costa’s (2021) history on Darwin and the causes of phenotypic variation is complemented by Sultan’s (2021) reminder of the long history of studies of plastic responses; Scheiner and Levis (2021) on the history of ideas about genetic assimilation; Diamond and Martin (2021) on the history of the plasticity as buying time for genetic adjustments to environmental change; Levis and Pfennig (2021) on the history of ideas about plasticity-led evolution; and Futuyma (2021) and Pfennig (2021, Box 3.2), both of whom track plasticity concepts to the 20th-century synthesis with genetics. Histories invite asking: what has changed in the past? And what might be chang- ing now? The rest of this essay reflects thoughts about those questions. They are based on 60 years of personal observation that started in 1959 with a lab section in zoology at the University of Michigan, taught by a newly hired assistant profes- sor, Richard Alexander, who later became a prominent evolutionary biologist. As an undergraduate and graduate student in zoology, I learned—and internalized—the synthesis that put genetics at the center of evolutionary biology. Mayr (1991), in his own history, characterized ‘The Synthesis’ as a consensus that developed between geneticists (who focused on genes) and naturalists (who focused on phenotypes). It meant that we were all thinking and talking in terms of genes, even those of us who, like me, were naturalists working primarily on phenotypes (e.g., morphology, behavior, or taxonomic traits). A major change between that era (what I will call it the ‘Synthesis Era’) and the present age is an increased focus on the phenotype, including its development and plasticity. The 20th-century synthesis had not too much of genes but too little of phe- notypes and their development. Here I briefly discuss some of the changes implied Foreword xi by a shift in evolutionary biology toward increased attention to the phenotype, espe- cially its developmental plasticity. I also respond to some opinions, expressed in the present volume, that indicate resistance to such change. On the nature of selection. It is sometimes said that the role of plasticity for evolu- tion is ‘controversial’ (see Futuyma 2021; Levis and Pfennig 2021; Pfennig 2021 and references therein). That seems to raise doubts about its importance. There may be unresolved questions about the role of developmental plasticity in a particular case or in a particular pattern of evolutionary genetic change, just as there may be unre- solved questions about the role of mutation or of selection. But there can be no doubt that developmental plasticity needs to be recognized, alongside genes, as playing an important role in Darwinian (adaptive and social/sexual) evolution, one that needs to be taken into account by any general description of how Darwinian evolution works. Here is a quick summary of the rationale for that assertion: • Darwinian evolution requires heritable change due to selection. • Selection depends on the existence of phenotypic variation. • All phenotypic variation comes from variation in development. • All variation in development comes from its responsiveness to inputs from two major sources—the genome and the environment. • Therefore, developmental plasticity—developmental responsiveness to environmental inputs—is important for Darwinian evolution. An important point is that selection does not depend on the presence of genetic variation. It only requires phenotypic variation that affects fitness, regardless of the proximate cause of that variation. Of course, a genetic response to selection (genetic evolution) does depend on the presence of genetic variation. Note also that genetic change in response to selection—adaptive evolution—if it occurs, necessarily depends on, and therefore follows, selection. In this sense genes are virtually always followers in adaptive phenotypic evolution, a point (with one kind of exception) fur- ther discussed below. Failure to appreciate the fact that selection acts on variation in phenotypes—not genotypes—has led to some interesting mistaken ideas. One of my favorites, as a female animal behaviorist, is the ‘lek paradox’ (Borgia 1979). This is the seemingly paradoxical idea that female choice for traits in males—traits that are not associated with any direct fitness benefit (such as paternal care)—persists, even when strong sexual selection might be expected to eliminate genetic variation. The implication is that without genetic variation females would no longer choose. But female choice does not depend on genetic variation (Borgia refers to ‘genetic choice’). Instead, it depends on phenotypic variation among males which could persist indefinitely with- out genetic variation. Sexual selection would not stop. It would simply stop affecting evolution. The lek paradox has
Recommended publications
  • Modularity As a Concept Modern Ideas About Mental Modularity Typically Use Fodor (1983) As a Key Touchstone
    COGNITIVE PROCESSING International Quarterly of Cognitive Science Mental modularity, metaphors, and the marriage of evolutionary and cognitive sciences GARY L. BRASE University of Missouri – Columbia Abstract - As evolutionary approaches in the behavioral sciences become increasingly prominent, issues arising from the proposition that the mind is a collection of modular adaptations (the multi-modular mind thesis) become even more pressing. One purpose of this paper is to help clarify some valid issues raised by this thesis and clarify why other issues are not as critical. An aspect of the cognitive sciences that appears to both promote and impair progress on this issue (in different ways) is the use of metaphors for understand- ing the mind. Utilizing different metaphors can yield different perspectives and advancement in our understanding of the nature of the human mind. A second purpose of this paper is to outline the kindred natures of cognitive science and evolutionary psychology, both of which cut across traditional academic divisions and engage in functional analyses of problems. Key words: Evolutionary Theory, Cognitive Science, Modularity, Metaphors Evolutionary approaches in the behavioral sciences have begun to influence a wide range of fields, from cognitive neuroscience (e.g., Gazzaniga, 1998), to clini- cal psychology (e.g., Baron-Cohen, 1997; McGuire and Troisi, 1998), to literary theory (e.g., Carroll, 1999). At the same time, however, there are ongoing debates about the details of what exactly an evolutionary approach – often called evolu- tionary psychology— entails (Holcomb, 2001). Some of these debates are based on confusions of terminology, implicit arguments, or misunderstandings – things that can in principle be resolved by clarifying current ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B
    Transformations of Lamarckism Vienna Series in Theoretical Biology Gerd B. M ü ller, G ü nter P. Wagner, and Werner Callebaut, editors The Evolution of Cognition , edited by Cecilia Heyes and Ludwig Huber, 2000 Origination of Organismal Form: Beyond the Gene in Development and Evolutionary Biology , edited by Gerd B. M ü ller and Stuart A. Newman, 2003 Environment, Development, and Evolution: Toward a Synthesis , edited by Brian K. Hall, Roy D. Pearson, and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2004 Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach , edited by D. Kimbrough Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2004 Modularity: Understanding the Development and Evolution of Natural Complex Systems , edited by Werner Callebaut and Diego Rasskin-Gutman, 2005 Compositional Evolution: The Impact of Sex, Symbiosis, and Modularity on the Gradualist Framework of Evolution , by Richard A. Watson, 2006 Biological Emergences: Evolution by Natural Experiment , by Robert G. B. Reid, 2007 Modeling Biology: Structure, Behaviors, Evolution , edited by Manfred D. Laubichler and Gerd B. M ü ller, 2007 Evolution of Communicative Flexibility: Complexity, Creativity, and Adaptability in Human and Animal Communication , edited by Kimbrough D. Oller and Ulrike Griebel, 2008 Functions in Biological and Artifi cial Worlds: Comparative Philosophical Perspectives , edited by Ulrich Krohs and Peter Kroes, 2009 Cognitive Biology: Evolutionary and Developmental Perspectives on Mind, Brain, and Behavior , edited by Luca Tommasi, Mary A. Peterson, and Lynn Nadel, 2009 Innovation in Cultural Systems: Contributions from Evolutionary Anthropology , edited by Michael J. O ’ Brien and Stephen J. Shennan, 2010 The Major Transitions in Evolution Revisited , edited by Brett Calcott and Kim Sterelny, 2011 Transformations of Lamarckism: From Subtle Fluids to Molecular Biology , edited by Snait B.
    [Show full text]
  • The Impact of Component Modularity on Design Evolution: Evidence from the Software Industry
    08-038 The Impact of Component Modularity on Design Evolution: Evidence from the Software Industry Alan MacCormack John Rusnak Carliss Baldwin Copyright © 2007 by Alan MacCormack, John Rusnak, and Carliss Baldwin. Working papers are in draft form. This working paper is distributed for purposes of comment and discussion only. It may not be reproduced without permission of the copyright holder. Copies of working papers are available from the author. Abstract Much academic work asserts a relationship between the design of a complex system and the manner in which this system evolves over time. In particular, designs which are modular in nature are argued to be more “evolvable,” in that these designs facilitate making future adaptations, the nature of which do not have to be specified in advance. In essence, modularity creates “option value” with respect to new and improved designs, which is particularly important when a system must meet uncertain future demands. Despite the conceptual appeal of this research, empirical work exploring the relationship between modularity and evolution has had limited success. Three major challenges persist: first, it is difficult to measure modularity in a robust and repeatable fashion; second, modularity is a property of individual components, not systems as a whole, hence we must examine these dynamics at the microstructure level; and third, evolution is a temporal phenomenon, in that the conditions at time t affect the nature of the design at time t+1, hence exploring this phenomenon requires longitudinal data. In this paper, we tackle these challenges by analyzing the evolution of a successful commercial software product over its entire lifetime, comprising six major “releases.” In particular, we develop measures of modularity at the component level, and use these to predict patterns of evolution between successive versions of the design.
    [Show full text]
  • Task-Dependent Evolution of Modularity in Neural Networks1
    Task-dependent evolution of modularity in neural networks1 Michael Husk¨ en, Christian Igel, and Marc Toussaint Institut fur¨ Neuroinformatik, Ruhr-Universit¨at Bochum, 44780 Bochum, Germany Telephone: +49 234 32 25558, Fax: +49 234 32 14209 fhuesken,igel,[email protected] Connection Science Vol 14, No 3, 2002, p. 219-229 Abstract. There exist many ideas and assumptions about the development and meaning of modu- larity in biological and technical neural systems. We empirically study the evolution of connectionist models in the context of modular problems. For this purpose, we define quantitative measures for the degree of modularity and monitor them during evolutionary processes under different constraints. It turns out that the modularity of the problem is reflected by the architecture of adapted systems, although learning can counterbalance some imperfection of the architecture. The demand for fast learning systems increases the selective pressure towards modularity. 1 Introduction The performance of biological as well as technical neural systems crucially depends on their ar- chitectures. In case of a feed-forward neural network (NN), architecture may be defined as the underlying graph constituting the number of neurons and the way these neurons are connected. Particularly one property of architectures, modularity, has raised a lot of interest among researchers dealing with biological and technical aspects of neural computation. It appears to be obvious to emphasise modularity in neural systems because the vertebrate brain is highly modular both in an anatomical and in a functional sense. It is important to stress that there are different concepts of modules. `When a neuroscientist uses the word \module", s/he is usually referring to the fact that brains are structured, with cells, columns, layers, and regions which divide up the labour of information processing in various ways' 1This paper is a revised and extended version of the GECCO 2001 Late-Breaking Paper by Husk¨ en, Igel, & Toussaint (2001).
    [Show full text]
  • Modularity in Animal Development and Evolution: Elements of a Conceptual Framework for Evodevo
    JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL ZOOLOGY (MOL DEV EVOL) 285:307–325 (1999) Modularity in Animal Development and Evolution: Elements of a Conceptual Framework for EvoDevo GEORGE VON DASSOW*AND ED MUNRO Department of Zoology, University of Washington, Seattle, Washington 98195-1800 ABSTRACT For at least a century biologists have been talking, mostly in a black-box sense, about developmental mechanisms. Only recently have biologists succeeded broadly in fishing out the contents of these black boxes. Unfortunately the view from inside the black box is almost as obscure as that from without, and developmental biologists increasingly confront the need to synthesize known facts about developmental phenomena into mechanistic descriptions of com- plex systems. To evolutionary biologists, the emerging understanding of developmental mecha- nisms is an opportunity to understand the origins of variation not just in the selective milieu but also in the variability of the developmental process, the substrate for morphological change. Ultimately, evolutionary developmental biology (EvoDevo) expects to articulate how the diversity of organic form results from adaptive variation in development. This ambition demands a shift in the way biologists describe causality, and the central problem of EvoDevo is to understand how the architecture of development confers evolvability. We argue in this essay that it makes little sense to think of this question in terms of individual gene function or isolated morphometrics, but rather in terms of higher-order modules such as gene networks and homologous characters. We outline the conceptual challenges raised by this shift in perspective, then present a selection of case studies we believe to be paradigmatic for how biologists think about modularity in devel- opment and evolution.
    [Show full text]
  • The Emergence of Modularity in Biological Systems
    The Emergence of Modularity in Biological Systems Zhenyu Wang Dec. 2007 Abstract: Modularity is a ubiquitous phenomenon in various biological systems, both in genotype and in phenotype. Biological modules, which consist of components relatively independent in functions as well as in morphologies, have facilitated daily performance of biological systems and their long time evolution in history. How did modularity emerge? A mechanism with horizontal gene transfer and a biological version of spin-glass model is addressed here. When the spontaneous symmetry is broken in an evolving environment, here comes modularity. Further improvement is also discussed at the end. 1 Introduction Modularity is an important concept with broad applications in computer science, especially in programming. A module, usually composed of various components, is a relatively independent entity in its operation with respect to other entities in the whole system. For a programmer, the employment of a module will increase the efficiency of coding, decrease the potential of errors, enhance the stability of the operation and facilitate the further improvement of the program. Coincidently, the nature thinks the same in its programming life: various biological systems are also in a modular fashion! Let us take the model organism fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster as an example to sip the ubiquitous modularity in biological systems. In view of morphology, Drosophila is a typical modular insect, whose adult is composed of an anterior head, followed by three thoracic segments, and eight abdominal segments at posterior[1](Fig. 1). Such a kind of segmentation is induced by a cascade of transcription factors in the embryo. First, maternal effect genes which are expressed in the mother’s ovary cells distribute cytoplasmic determinants unevenly in fertilized eggs, which thus determines anterior-posterior and dorsal-ventral axis.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolution of Networks for Body Plan Patterning; Interplay of Modularity, Robustness and Evolvability
    Evolution of Networks for Body Plan Patterning; Interplay of Modularity, Robustness and Evolvability Kirsten H. ten Tusscher1,2*, Paulien Hogeweg1 1 Theoretical Biology and Bioinformatics Group, Department of Biology, Faculty of Science, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands, 2 Scientific Computing, Simula Research Laboratory, Oslo, Norway Abstract A major goal of evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo) is to understand how multicellular body plans of increasing complexity have evolved, and how the corresponding developmental programs are genetically encoded. It has been repeatedly argued that key to the evolution of increased body plan complexity is the modularity of the underlying developmental gene regulatory networks (GRNs). This modularity is considered essential for network robustness and evolvability. In our opinion, these ideas, appealing as they may sound, have not been sufficiently tested. Here we use computer simulations to study the evolution of GRNs’ underlying body plan patterning. We select for body plan segmentation and differentiation, as these are considered to be major innovations in metazoan evolution. To allow modular networks to evolve, we independently select for segmentation and differentiation. We study both the occurrence and relation of robustness, evolvability and modularity of evolved networks. Interestingly, we observed two distinct evolutionary strategies to evolve a segmented, differentiated body plan. In the first strategy, first segments and then differentiation domains evolve (SF strategy). In the second scenario segments and domains evolve simultaneously (SS strategy). We demonstrate that under indirect selection for robustness the SF strategy becomes dominant. In addition, as a byproduct of this larger robustness, the SF strategy is also more evolvable. Finally, using a combined functional and architectural approach, we determine network modularity.
    [Show full text]
  • Modularity in Signaling Systems
    Modularity in Signaling Systems Domitilla Del Vecchio Department of Mechanical Engineering, Laboratory for Information and Decision Systems (LIDS), MIT, 77 Massachusetts Ave, Cambridge, MA 02139 E-mail: [email protected] Modularity in Signaling Systems 2 Abstract. Modularity is a property by which the behavior of a system does not change upon interconnection. It is crucial for understanding the behavior of a complex system from the behavior of the composing subsystems. Whether modularity holds in biology is an intriguing and largely debated question. In this paper, we discuss this question taking a control systems theory view and focusing on signaling systems. In particular, we argue that, despite signaling systems are constituted of structural modules, such as covalent modification cycles, modularity does not hold in general. As in any engineering system, impedance-like effects, called retroactivity, appear at interconnections and alter the behavior of connected modules. We further argue that while signaling systems have evolved sophisticated ways to counter-act retroactivity and enforce modularity, retroactivity may also be exploited to finely control the information processing of signaling pathways. Testable predictions and experimental evidence are discussed with their implications. 1. Introduction The idea that modularity is a general principle of biological organization and that signaling systems, in particular, are modularly assembled has been considered and discussed by several researchers [1,10,21]. In particular, a modular systems approach to understanding information transfer in signaling networks has been proposed as a way to defeat the complexity of networks [4,20,24,25]. For example, signaling pathways involved in caspase activation have been studied through a modular approach to determine the key contributors in triggering apoptosis [9].
    [Show full text]
  • Varieties of Modules: Kinds, Levels, Origins, and Behaviors RASMUS G
    116JOURNAL OF EXPERIMENTAL R.G. WINTHER ZOOLOGY (MOL DEV EVOL) 291:116–129 (2001) Varieties of Modules: Kinds, Levels, Origins, and Behaviors RASMUS G. WINTHER* Department of History and Philosophy of Science, and Department of Biology, Indiana University, Bloomington, Indiana 47405 ABSTRACT This article began as a review of a conference, organized by Gerhard Schlosser, entitled “Modularity in Development and Evolution.” The conference was held at, and sponsored by, the Hanse Wissenschaftskolleg in Delmenhorst, Germany in May, 2000. The article subse- quently metamorphosed into a literature and concept review as well as an analysis of the differ- ences in current perspectives on modularity. Consequently, I refer to general aspects of the conference but do not review particular presentations. I divide modules into three kinds: struc- tural, developmental, and physiological. Every module fulfills none, one, or multiple functional roles. Two further orthogonal distinctions are important in this context: module-kinds versus mod- ule-variants-of-a-kind and reproducer versus nonreproducer modules. I review criteria for indi- viduation of modules and mechanisms for the phylogenetic origin of modularity. I discuss conceptual and methodological differences between developmental and evolutionary biologists, in particular the difference between integration and competition perspectives on individualization and modular behavior. The variety in views regarding modularity presents challenges that require resolution in order to attain a comprehensive,
    [Show full text]
  • The Body Plan Concept and Its Centrality in Evo-Devo
    Evo Edu Outreach (2012) 5:219–230 DOI 10.1007/s12052-012-0424-z EVO-DEVO The Body Plan Concept and Its Centrality in Evo-Devo Katherine E. Willmore Published online: 14 June 2012 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012 Abstract A body plan is a suite of characters shared by a by Joseph Henry Woodger in 1945, and means ground plan group of phylogenetically related animals at some point or structural plan (Hall 1999; Rieppel 2006; Woodger 1945). during their development. The concept of bauplane, or body Essentially, a body plan is a suite of characters shared by a plans, has played and continues to play a central role in the group of phylogenetically related animals at some point study of evolutionary developmental biology (evo-devo). during their development. However, long before the term Despite the importance of the body plan concept in evo- body plan was coined, its importance was demonstrated in devo, many researchers may not be familiar with the pro- research programs that presaged the field of evo-devo, per- gression of ideas that have led to our current understanding haps most famously (though erroneously) by Ernst Haeck- of body plans, and/or current research on the origin and el’s recapitulation theory. Since the rise of evo-devo as an maintenance of body plans. This lack of familiarity, as well independent field of study, the body plan concept has as former ties between the body plan concept and metaphys- formed the backbone upon which much of the current re- ical ideology is likely responsible for our underappreciation search is anchored.
    [Show full text]
  • Phenotypic Plasticity and Modularity Allow for the Production of Novel
    Londe et al. EvoDevo (2015) 6:36 DOI 10.1186/s13227-015-0031-5 EvoDevo RESEARCH Open Access Phenotypic plasticity and modularity allow for the production of novel mosaic phenotypes in ants Sylvain Londe1*, Thibaud Monnin1, Raphaël Cornette2, Vincent Debat2, Brian L. Fisher3 and Mathieu Molet1 Abstract Background: The origin of discrete novelties remains unclear. Some authors suggest that qualitative phenotypic changes may result from the reorganization of preexisting phenotypic traits during development (i.e., developmental recombination) following genetic or environmental changes. Because ants combine high modularity with extreme phenotypic plasticity (queen and worker castes), their diversified castes could have evolved by developmental recombination. We performed a quantitative morphometric study to investigate the developmental origins of novel phenotypes in the ant Mystrium rogeri, which occasionally produces anomalous ‘intercastes.’ Our analysis compared the variation of six morphological modules with body size using a large sample of intercastes. Results: We confirmed that intercastes are conspicuous mosaics that recombine queen and worker modules. In addition, we found that many other individuals traditionally classified as workers or queens also exhibit some level of mosaicism. The six modules had distinct profiles of variation suggesting that each module responds differentially to factors that control body size and polyphenism. Mosaicism appears to result from each module responding differently yet in an ordered and predictable manner to intermediate levels of inducing factors that control polyphenism. The order of module response determines which mosaic combinations are produced. Conclusions: Because the frequency of mosaics and their canalization around a particular phenotype may evolve by selection on standing genetic variation that affects the plastic response (i.e., genetic accommodation), develop- mental recombination is likely to play an important role in the evolution of novel castes in ants.
    [Show full text]
  • Dispositional Properties in Evo-Devo in L
    This is a pre-print version of Dispositional Properties in Evo-Devo in L. Nuño de la Rosa and G. Müller (eds.) Evolutionary Developmental Biology: A Reference Guide. The final publication is available at Springer via http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33038-9_64-1 Dispositional Properties in Evo-Devo Christopher J. Austin and Laura Nuño de la Rosa Abstract In identifying intrinsic molecular chance and extrinsic adaptive pressures as the only causally relevant factors in the process of evolution, the theoretical perspective of the Modern Synthesis had a major impact on the perceived tenability of an ontology of dispositional properties. However, since the late 1970s, an increasing number of evolutionary biologists have challenged the descriptive and explanatory adequacy of this ―chance alone, extrinsic only‖ understanding of evolutionary change. Because morphological studies of homology, convergence, and teratology have revealed a space of possible forms and phylogenetic trajectories that is considerably more restricted than expected, evo-devo has focused on the causal contribution of intrinsic developmental processes to the course of evolution. Evo-devo‘s investigation into the developmental structure of the modality of morphology – including both the possibility and impossibility of organismal form – has led to the utilisation of a number of dispositional concepts that emphasise the tendency of the evolutionary process to change along certain routes. In this sense, and in contrast to the perspective of the Modern Synthesis, evo-devo can be described as a ―science of dispositions.‖ This chapter discusses the recent philosophical literature on dispositional properties in evo-devo, exploring debates about both the metaphysical and epistemological aspects of the central dispositional concepts utilised in contemporary evo-devo (e.g., variability, modularity, robustness, plasticity, and evolvability) and addressing the epistemological question of how dispositional properties challenge existing explanatory models in evolutionary biology.
    [Show full text]