<<

Logique & Analyse 161-162-163 (1998), 219-266

NAÏVE THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART I

Alan WEIR

This is the first part of a two-part paper in which I try to provide a logical foundation for a coherent naïve , one somewhat different from those existing foundations provided by logicians in the paraconsistent and relevant logic traditions. Part I is in three sections, plus an Appendix. In this part of the paper I outline a revision of motivated by a desire to retain , notwithstanding the antinomies which show it to be trivial even in quite weak logics (such as, R and El ). I follow here a common paraconsistent approach by separating naïve set theory into three components: i) the proper set-theoretic or rules, ii) the opera- tional rules for the logical constants and iii) the structural rules for the logical constants. The idea is then to retain naïve set theory by modifying only the latter so as to generate a substructural logic. 2ap pHroaoch wdifefervs efrorm the tusuhal paeracon sistent ones by laying down struc- cturaul conrstrar intes onn Cut,t or generalised transitivity of entailment, in such a way that the resulting system straddles the paraconsistent/non-paraconsis- tent boundary as it is usually drawn. In §I I illustrate the main ideas of the ' n e o - socmleawshast ipcoamlp' o ufslyr tearmm it, ewitwh reospreckt to, th e simplified case of gappy seamantics, sdeveloping a neo-cIlassical acc ount of entailment. The second sewction dei velopls this lfurther by looking at how the notion of indeterminacy can be used to lay down non-classical structural constraints which yield a logic suitable for -inducing discourses such as set theory. The final section applies these ideas to set theory and shows how to develop naïve set theory, and more generally all mathematics representable in standard set theory, in the neo-classical framework. I t is argued that the 'classical

I See J.K. Slaney, ' RW X is not Curry Paraconsistent• in Brady and Routley (eds.) Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent. (N/Rinchem Philosophia Verlag, 1989) pp. 472-480.

2 myR 'Naïve Set Theory is Innocent!', Mind 107, (1998) pp. 763-798. e a o n s w h y o n e s h o u l d n o t f o l l o w o r t h o d o x y i n r e j e c t i n g n a ï v e s e t t h e o r y a r e g i v e n i n 220 ALAN WEIR

recapture' o f standard mathematics is achieved more smoothly in this framework than in the framework of dialetheic naïve set theory. All of this on the assumption of the soundness of the neo-classical frame- work, something which cannot be demonstrated classically but which must be demonstrated within the naïve set theory itself. The sequel paper con- cerns itself mainly with the issues of soundness and completeness for the neo-classical system.

§I: Neo-classical logic

In order to illustrate the main ideas of the amendments to the structural rules I am proposing I will use the simple framework of Lukasiewiczian, (or strong Kleene) 3i.e . all these operators are classical over (True, False) but of s'gaeppmy' asentetnicecs are gappy —I represent gap by ' 0 ' — and conjunctions sare false if at least one conjunct is false, otherwise gappy; as usual, disjunc- tion is the dual of conjunction: f o r c o n j u Q Q n c t i 1o n T 0 F P I T 0 , 3 T T 0F T T T T d i P s &j0 00F P 0 T 0 u n c Ft F F F F T i o n a n d P -P n e T T g a 00 t i o F F n , The idea here is not that indeterminacy in naïve set theory can be represented by truth value gaps, as in the Lukasiewiczian semantics, for that way lies only 'super-paradox' in the shape of set-theoretic variants of

3 pp.0 169-171, s ome results o f whic h are presented i n Luk as iewic z and Tars k i, 'Un'tersuchungen den Aussagenkalkill', Comptes Rendus des séances de la Société des Sci.e nces et des Lettres de Varsovie 23, (1930) pp. 30-50; S. Kleene Introduction t o MeJtamathematics. (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1952) p. 334; (the Lukasiewicz and strong Kleene three-valued systems diverge over the conditionals). . L u k a s i e w i c z * 0 l o g i c e t r n j w a r t o s c i o w e r , R u c h F i l o z o l i c z n y , ( L w 6 w ) 5 , ( 1 9 2 0 ) NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONS1STENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1221 the strengthened liar. Indeterminacy in set theory, if not elsewhere, is not best accommodated within a classical metatheory with extra values (gaps in the Kleene/Lukasiewicz semantics behave algebraically much like third values). Rather one ought to work with just the usual values but within the framework of a non-classical logic in the semantic metatheory. But which logic? The point of starting from gappy semantics in a classical metatheory is to get an approximation to the right logic, a fallible guide to the non- classical logic which should be used in a more adequate non-gappy seman- tics. If the guide turns out to be faulty, one can always return to the gappy semantics and try again to achieve a better approximation. The semantic theory for this part, then, will be of the above gappy type. But what is of particular interest here, and is not fixed simply by the valua- tion , is the question of which account of entailment one should adopt. Take the two standard classical model-theoretic accounts of entail- ment for multiple conclusion systems: X ] Y iff there is no valuation in which all wffs in X are true and all in Y false. X 2 Y iff in every valuation in which all wffs in X are true, one in Y is true. Equivalent in classical semantics, these come apart when indeterminacy is taken into consideration, 4te rmeinsatpe ein cevieary ladmissiblel y model. 5 Thus let P be true and U be a neces- isarilyf gap py sentence; then {P t}fi rseth ancctoeaunit rlosf e] n ta ilment does not exclude failure of truth-preservation aUnd canr surely eb be seut asidet for t hat reason. The second, however, is also too sdtroneg oas nan eact couenst of c onsequence since (U) entails2 P, for P false, U as before, so that falsity is not preserved upwards. n c oe s t This is a defect if one thinks that there is no logical asymmetry between we n h t ai i l -down)ward truth-preservation and upwards falsity preservation: withc unfhalse pre misses and false conclusions are as bad as arguments with tairue premistser s and u.ntrue conc lusions. Here I take the middle value to be eT h ie n d e -

4 pre0servation, from premisses to conclusions, not of truth but rather of membership in some setn of designated values. However it is arguable that this approach does not take the failure of ebiv alence seriously, restoring it at the level of designated versus undesignated value. c o5 preEdications of necessarily empty terms such as 'the greatest prime ' and certain typesm of liar sentence. mx oa nm rp el se ps ow nh si ec th oh ta hv e fb ae ie ln us ru eg og fe bs it ve ad lf eo nr cn e ic se ts os da er fi il ny eg ea np tp ay is le mn et ne n t ic ne ts ei rn mc sl ou fd e a t o m i c 222 ALAN WEIR

unfalse. One upshot of this view is that Priest's dialetheic logic LP, formal- ly speaking the strong Kleene logic with T,F1 as the middle (also desig- nated) value cannot be a genuine logic. 6w hiIchf is oneintheer true tnoar falsek e thens L P allows inferences which are not {truthT pres, ervFing (1from T premisses to T,F1 conclusions). Suppose, on the tother hanod, one a ccepts with the dialetheist that in the middle case there is both truth eand falsity. In that case if one accepts inferences from T to IT,FI anotwithstanding their failure o f upwards-falsity preservation then one vshould aaccept linferenuces freom (T,F) to F, notwithstanding their failure of truth-preservation because they preserve falsity upwards. To maintain this symmetry would result, of course, in trivialisation yet Priest recognises (In Contradiction pp. 104-105) that falsity preservation upwards is as essential to entailment as truth-preservation downwards. He is forced, then, into a counter-intuitive failure to link entailment with by means of the usual equivalence A —›B iff A 1 3 , ( a conditional encapsulating the entailment ). If both accounts are wrong, what can the right notion of entailment be? My approach here will be to abandon the rather conservative (in its holding to a form of bivalence) designated/undesignated dichotomy and look to analogies with how one ought to pattern acceptances and rejectings o f components of inferences. Consider the following ' n e o - cofl saosunsdinceassl f'o r da sechefmiatnic iinfterei noce nrule: Inference rule R is sound just when for any instance I of the rule:

For any conclusion C and premiss P of instance I, (a) any valuation in which all premisses of I are true and all conclusions but C are false is one in which C is true and (b) any valuation in which all conclusions are false and all premisses but P are true is one in which P is false.

Similarly a sequent X Y is sound just when it satisfies the above clause with members of X classed as premisses, members of Y conclusions. d7e vTianht ai cscount is still a model-theoretic one and I will focus mainly on entailment construed model-theoretically, in this part o f the paper. An

6 SoSme o f t he t rouble here i s caused b y Pries t 's attachment t o t h e biv alent deseignated/undesignated dichotomy: as indicated, he cannot leave the middle or glut value unede signated on pain o f validating ex falso qtwdlibet, contrary t o his paraconsistent principles. G .7 truPtIh preservation clause —when all premisses are true the conclusion is. rf io en se td ,i Is nl Ci o k ne ts rm au dl it ci tp il oe nc .o (n Dc ol ru ds ri eo cn hl to :g Ni tc jt hh oe fn fo ,n 1e 9c 8a 7n )a em se pn ed cc il aa lu ls ye C( ha a) pt to et rh Fe is vt ea .n d a r d NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1223 alternative account, deriving from Bolzano, is to define entailment in terms of truth-preservation o f arbitrary substitution instances. Truth is either taken as primitive or defined in terms o f some distinguished model or valuation. Arguably this perspective makes better sense with respective to the non-contingent language of mathematics where there is no variation of truth value across 'possible worlds' —represented by models— but I will leave this account aside till Part The neo-classical account is motivated by the idea that in, for example, multiple conclusion v E —from A v B conclude A,B— it is perfectly legitimate to accept A v B ('The baby will be a boy, or a girl', say) whilst accepting neither disjunct but not acceptable, while accepting the premiss, to reject one disjunct unless one accepts the other. Similarly for &I, one may reject the conclusion ('The baby will be a boy and a girl', for exam- ple) without rejecting either conjunct premiss; but it would be wrong, if one rejected the conclusion, to accept one premiss unless one rejected the other. However there is a problem with this account of soundness. For logic consists in more than one-step inferences: we need structural rules telling us how to put operational rules together to form extended proofs. But consider now an sentence P which is gappy in some valuation y. Since I have eschewed a supervaluational approach in favour of Lukasiewiczian connectives, P & -P is also gappy so the entailment P & -P I fails neo-classically, where 1 is some necessarily false absurdity constant. As there are no multiple premisses or conclusions, the neo-classical truth of the claim that P & -P entails I requires in the upwards falsity-preservation direction that if I is false in valuation v, which of course it is, then so is P & -P; but this fails since P & -P is gappy. (Similarly P v -P fails to be a neo-classical logical truth.) But despite the neo-classical falsehood o f P & -P I there are proofs of P & -P 1- I in which every step is neo- classically correct, e.g. the following in a Gentzen-style system:

P & - P P & - P - P

&E preserves truth downwards and falsity upwards and so is clearly neo- classically correct, but so too is the natural deduction -E rule: from P,-P conclude C, for any C (including the absurdity constant I ) . The truth- preservation direction is trivial (at least if one is already predisposed to accept -E ) —there is no valuation which makes both premisses true— 224 ALAN WEIR

whilst in other direction neo-classical correctness requires that if _I_ is false, which it is in every valuation, then if P is true, -P is false and if -P is true P is false. But this does indeed hold in every valuation by the Lukasie- wiczian rules for S o to preserve neo-classical soundness globally we have to amend the classical structural rules which permit us to chain to- gether the 8zE and -E inferences in the above fashion. The problem here is that firstly the simple -E inference, though neo- classically correct, is 'ininimax' unsound: —that is the minimum premiss value can be greater than the maximum conclusion value, on the natural ordering True > 0 > False— (this can occur in classically sound rules only in Kleene models in which some wffs in the inference take the gappy value); and secondly, chaining together minimax unsound but neo-classi- cally correct inferences can generate, as we have just seen, derivations of conclusions which do not even neo-classically follow from the overall premisses, never mind follow in 'minimax' logic. This problem arises for disjunctive and standard natural deduction vE as well as -E. How, then, should we amend the structural rules to accommodate the neo-classical perspective on entailment? One response, along the lines of contraction-free or linear logic systems, would be to use a sequent system in which sequences rather than sets of wffs as antecedents and succeedents and blame the problem on multiple occurrences of the trouble- some wf f P - P in the above. The definition o f soundness I just gave, after all, is ambiguous between reading premisses and conclusions as sets of wffs, or as occurrences o f wffs in something more structured, say sequences o f wff occurrences. I f one took the latter course, one might restrict contraction of multiple occurrences to certain syntactically speci- fiable contexts, perhaps by distinguishing, as some relevantists, do different modes of combination of wffs in sequents —e.g. extensional versus intensional combination. 8do inAg lso,t hesopeuciagllyh where non-extensional operators are concerned, the tprocheduere hars neo in tuitive basis —it is hard to see what the rational signifi- mcance isa in they numb er of times one makes an assumption. It could be jbustified seolely as a novel amendment to our standard practices motivated by overall considerations of coherence, or some such. p r a g m I want to suggest a rather different amendment to our standard practices tahougth onie wchich I think has a little more intuitive basis, for example in rthe ligeht of thae way classical logic seems to break down in such cases as sthe Soroites panradox. The idea is that we place global restrictions on proofs swhich block the general transitivity of entailment yielding a non-transitive fnotion of enotailment in which transitivity fails in a controlled fashion yet r

8 S e e , e . g . S t e p h e n R e a d R e l e v a n t L o g i c . ( O x f o r d : B l a c k w e l l , 1 9 8 8 ) C h a p t e r F o u r . NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONS1STENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1225

holds widely enough to permit that chaining together of proofs which is essential in order to derive the standard results of classical mathematics. 9 If one looks at the problematic proof above, it is noteworthy that a 'dodgy' wff, P & —P, occurred in the overall assumptions on which both premisses for —E were based. My suggestion (at a first approximation) is that we rule this out, at least for minimax unsound rules, so that we require wffs which occur in the antecedent of more than one premiss of a sequent system inference rule, not to be 'dodgy'. And since it was gappiness that allows neo-classically correct minimax unsound rules to chain together in such a way as to lose the property of neo-classical correctness, the obvious way to interpret 'dodginess' is by failure to take one of the determinate truth values True or False. Formalising the determinateness of a wff, for the moment, as Det P. this suggests the following sequent —E rule:

X (1) P Given (2) —P Given Zi, (3.i) Det Q Given, VQEXnY

X,Y, (3)C 1,2, [3.i. I E I], —E

Here X , Y . areqbuirbedr that U Z , n (X u Y) = 0 . In general I will omit the index set I iel e v i a t ewhsere it is clear from the context what it is and bracket the Xpremiss co nsequents by '[ and ']' as above. Where X n Y = 0 we get the basic operational form of the —E rule, with u no determinacy restriction. Thus the classical proof of an arbitrary sentence QY from P & —P is invalid and transitivity fails since we have P & —P F P, P. & —P F —P and P. —P H Q but not P & —P Q . We do. though. have a rXestric,ted form of ex falso quodlibet in which we can conclude anything we I 5 ' a b b r e v 9 i a Ten0nant. Anti-Realism and Logic. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1987) Chapter 17 and T. Smiley, 'tEnttaeilment and Deducibility', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (1959) pp. 233-254 essphec ially pp. 233-234 and §2 (following on from work by Geach and von Wright). XDucmmett con siders but rejects abandonment o f transitivity o f entailment in 'Wang's Paradox'. Truth and Other Enigmas. (London: Duckworth. 1978) P. 252. u r 1 l o 1 g 3 i 1 c a i n a n d s i w t h i o s h a v e m o o t e d o r a d v o c a t e d c u r t a i l m e n t s o n t r a n s i t i v i t y i n c l u d e N e i l 226 ALAN WEIR

like from a contradiction, in conjunctive form, if we know that the conjunc- tion P is determinate, that is we do have Det(P & -P), P & -P F Q . 1 (W) hat, then, does determinacy amount to? In a semantics permitting truth value gaps, the obvious of the Det operator is one which maps true to true, false to true and gap to false. A problem with this account is that it follows that all sentences of the form Det P are them- selves determinate whereas we will see when turning to naive set theory that we need to allow for higher-order indeterminacy. One could model higher-order indeterminacy either by generalising from three values to a multi-valued semantics or by introducing a modal account of determinacy, but neither approach is entirely adequate for naïve set theory. As remarked at the outset, the problem ultimately arises because we are working within a framework of non-bivalent semantics with a classical metalanguage in which we assume excluded middle for semantic pronouncements such as P is gappy' Th is has the effect of representing indeterminacy in too de- terminate a fashion, as it were: —as the determinate absence of a certain type of value. A more adequate treatment of indeterminacy will be outlined in part ll in which one works only with two values but does so within a semantically closed theory, with no metalanguage/object language distinc- tion and in which excluded middle is not forthcoming. For the present, when considering a gappy approximation, I will stick to the above crude bi- valent account of determinacy. However there is another problem with this account. Thus far I have treated every Kleene valuation as admissible. Since the degenerate valua- tion in which every atom is gappy is therefore admissible, no wff of the form Det P, where P contains no occurrences of Det, is ever true in all admissible models since all such wffs are gappy in the degenerate valua- tion. Hence any such Det P sentence has the same status as any contingent 'empirical' sentence. This is arguably counterintuitive: if 'the table in the room next door is brown or not brown' fails to take a determinate truth value, through reference failure or vagueness for example, then on many (though not all) accounts of the matter, this failure is of a very different type from the failure of 'the table is brown' to be true, when the table is painted blue. The failure o f determinacy in the former case is more a 'linguistic' matter of the terms of the sentence failing to connect properly with objects and properties than the factual matter o f the objects and properties referred to failing to combine in the world in the required way. If this way of thinking is right, it seems reasonable that some, at least, true

1 1 3 anaI lnyst is of the notion of determinacy given below. u i t i v e l y w e w o u l d w a n t t o h a v e D e t P F D e t ( 1 3 8 4 — P ) , a r e s u l t w h i c h f o l l o w s f r o m t h e NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1227

Det P sentences should be given a status at least in between ordinary empirical non-logical sentences and logical truths. One way to effect this in formal terms is to single out a A of the atoms which are to have fixed determinacy status together with a valuation @ to play the role of the actual world; our interest will be in valuations @ in which a healthy number of A atoms take a non-gappy truth value and also a few A atoms are gappy. Say that a valuation y is admissible iff every atom in A which has a truth value in h a s a truth value in 1 ,o p(popsitee or nhe)a anpd severy tA ahtom wehich is gappy in @ is gappy in v. The set A and valuation @ generate a set AXDET (which thus has to be thought of as taking A and @ as parameters) such that AXDET is the set of all those wffs of the form Det P or –Det Q which are true in all admissible models. The upshot of this is that our definition of neo-classical entailment is parallel to that of neo-classical soundness but relativised to A and @ as parameter: —a set of wffs X neo-classically entails a set Y (written X Y) iff:

a) F o r any wff C in Y, in any admissible valuation v in which all wffs in X are true but all in Y but C are false, C is true in v. b) F o r any wff P in X. in any admissible valuation y in which all wffs in Y are false but all in X hut P are true, P is false at v.

Likewise X Y is a neo-classically correct sequent just when X neo- classically entails Y. In what follows, though, I will stick to single con- clusion logics. If we wish to develop a which is complete with respect to s o defined, we shall have to similarly relativise I- so that it includes not only the 'logical' rules but also includes, as axiomatic princi- ples regarding determinacy, the wffs of the AXDET set generated by the particular A and @ in terms of which i s defined. What logic, then, is sound with respect to such an entailment notion? Well, any 'minimax' sequent rule is sound for every AXDET. That is, if we take (single conclusion) sequent rules to have the schematic form:

X P„, X„ P„ I U P 0

y then so are all the Pi, since all the premiss sequents are neo-classically correct; hence so is C by the minimax entailment. Whilst if C is false in y but all of the wffs in U X i b u t A 0<111 aentaril Ce, at least one of the premiss succeedents is false, say Pk, in which tcaser by uthe neeo-c lassical correctness of Xk P k , A E Xk and is false in r. Minimax soundness is a mechanically decidable principle, fo r finite i n saluent rules, but we are interested in a proof system which we can take to nvaïve set th eory having passed the test o f soundness with respect to a st ystemh admeitting nindete rminacies, albeit in the cruder gappy fo rm o f Ks leenei valuations.n c One set of rules we can use are the minimax sequent reules w hose general form is: t h eX ( PX1 (2) i(p[P/ Q1 1 MM m) i n i G mwhere (pa[P / Q1 rexsults from ip by uniform substitution of a sub-formula P by Qi and where v e Pis A and Q is - - A n or P is ---A and Q is A or P is A & B and Q is B & A Or P is AV B and Q is BV A or P is A & B and Q is —(—A v —B) or P is —(—A v —B) and Q is A & B or P is A v B and Q is —(—A & —B) or P is —(—A & —B) and Q is A v B or P is (A & (B & C)) and Q is ((A & B) & C) or P is ((A & B) & C) and Q is (A & (B & C)) or P is (A v (B V C)) and Q is ((A V B) v C) or P is ((A V B) v C) and Q is (A v (B V C)) or P is (A & (B V C)) and Q is ((A & B) v (A & C)) or P is ((A & B) V (A & C)) and Q is (A & (B v C)) or P is (A v (B & C)) and Q is ((A B ) & (A V C)) or P is ((A y B) & (A V C)) and Q is (A y (B & C))

In addition standard sequent form natural deduction vI, &E and &I rules (without any determinacy restriction on overlapping assumptions in both premiss antecedents) are minimax sound as is the Mingle rule: NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONS1STENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1229

X ( 1 ) A Sz. -A G i v e n X (2) B v -B I Mingle which is a derived rule of the logic RM which extends relevant logic R by addition of the Mingle scheme." This rule will not please a rele- vantist, just as the double elimination principle above will not please the intuitionist but the rules do preserve minimax soundness. So too, in a slightly more degenerate way, do the following reductio rules:

X, A I X,- A 1_ X A X A

(Here I both intuitionist and classical reductio ad absurdum rules as -I rules though strictly the classical rule is a form of negation elimination.) These -I rules are redundant in the context of the others where X.A C L, L a language lacking Det and I : —the degenerate Kleene assignment shows that for any set of wffs there is a Kleene evaluation in which no members of the set take the value false so that no sequent of the form X. A I is ever minimax correct. The non-classical amendments then come in with the minimax unsound -E, as we have seen, and also with minimax unsound vE. For vE, we need to restrict the standard sequent natural deduction rule to:

X (I ) P v Q Given Y,P (2) C Given Z,Q (3) C Given Wi, i E I ( 4 . i ) Det R G i v e n , VR E (X n (Y u Z))

X,Y,Z, U W , ( 5 ) C 1 , 2 , 3 [4.i, i E v E

We require also that U W , n (X u Y u Z) = 0. iel

The idea behind the restriction is that for the non-minimax vE rule we require ally wff which is both an antecedent of the major premiss and also

1 I See Anderson and Belnap, Entailment Volume 1. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975) §29.5 especially the —(A -4 A ) —> (B B ) together with theorem RM67 (p. 397) (A —0 A) (-0 (—A MA). 230 ALAN WEIR

an antecedent of one or other of the minor premisses to be determinate. The rule is neo-classically sound.

Proof: i) Truth preservation: this is much as in the classical case. Suppose all the given input sequents are entailments and that all of X,Y,Z, U W i , i E i are true in admissible valuation y. Then by line I, P v Q is true in y, so one or other disjunct is. Whichever is the case, line 2 or else line 3 establishes that C is true in v. ii) Falsity preservation (upwards): suppose that C is false in y and all of

X,Y.Z, U W i a r e(El je t tcanrnout bee a member of a Wi set else all of X,Y,Z are true contradicting, by ipart in) abov e, the falsity of C. If A e (X n (Y u Z)) then since all of the Wi are true, by the 4.i premisses, A has a determinate truth value in v; since it v is not true, it must be false as required. I f A 0 (X n (Y u Z)) then either ab) all ouf X are true in v or else b) all of Y u Z are. t A Case a): —by the correctness of line (1) P y Q is true in v hence one of . the disjuncts is, suppose without loss of generality that it is P. By the S coirrectness of line (2) in the rule above, A E Y and is false. n Cacse b) By the correctness of lines (2) and (3) both P and Q are false in e y h ence so is P y Q. By the correctness of line (1), A E X and is false U in v. El W ,A similar , somewhat less convoluted, proof establishes the soundness of –E. n We need, o f course, a structural rule embodying the reflexivity o f ( derivability. One such is a rule of hypothesis: X uX (I) A Hyp. Y uwhere A E )( o r else we could use the special case where X = I A I to Zwhich we must then add an expansion rule: ) 0X ( 1 ) A G i v e n ,X,Y ( 2 ) A) I Exp. A I have also assumed throughout a truth constant T true in all admissible models and the absurdity constant I featuring in the negation rules and NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1231

interpreted as false in all models. are wffs provable from the o f antecedents 12 (which I will represent by ' — ' ) so that we provide for T the axioms:

— ( I ) Det"T A x i o m T

Here Det"T is T prefixed by any finite number (including zero) of occur- rences of Det. Similarly we add for I the axiom:

— ( I ) De tn -I A x i o m I

This gives us (where n 0 in the T and I axioms) the 'purely logical' neo-classical derivability notion I-1. But in line with the thought that some determinacy claims are not contingent in the ordinary sense, we consider this notion always to be augmented, in interesting cases, by a non-trivial set of determinacy axioms AXDET which take the form:

- ( I ) Det P D e t P E AXDET — ( I ) -Det P - D e t P E AXDET

The effect of the determinacy axioms, therefore, is that determinacy con- straints in non-minimax rules such as -E and vE do not bite with respect to wffs in AXDET. The following principles are also sound for our Det operator under the given interpretation:

i) I f P then D e t P: (as special cases: if D e t P then Det(Det P), if k -(De t P) then D e t (-D e t (P )) ); ii) I f D e t P and D e t Q then D e t ( P & Q); iii) I f D e t ( P & Q) then not both - D e t P and - D e t Q: iv) I f D e t P and D e t Q then D e t ( P Q ) ; v) I f - D e t P and - D e t Q then - D e t ( P y Q); vi) D e t P iff D e t -P; - D e t P iff - D e t -P; vii) D e t P P -1 3 • In the mathematical case, these principles will be derived rules hut for the gappy semantics it will follow, from the definition o f i n terms of admissible models and of AXDET in terms of 2i and @, that all AXDET sets are closed under the corresponding rules. Thus corresponding to the second part of i) we have:

1 2 alte0rnr atively as the set of wffs derivable from T alone, and altered matters accordingly. w e c o u l d h a v e d e f i n e d t h e t h e o r e m s a s t h e s e t o f w f f s d e r i v a b l e f r o m a n y w f f o r 232 ALAN WEIR

— (1) Det P Given - (2 ) Det Det P I DET (i)

If Det P is a theorem it must be true in every admissible valuation hence Det Det P E AXDET. Note that we will not want, in the set-theoretic case, the principle Det P D e t Det P since there can be higher-order indeter- minacy and so it might be possible for Del P to be determinately indetermi- nate so that the principle goes from an indeterminate premiss to a false conclusion. The situation parallels that of the rule of necessitation in modal logic. We have, for any wff P, if 1- P then F P but it is not the case that for any wff P. P FD P. Corresponding to part y) we have DET v):

— (1) -Det P Given — (2) -Det Q Given — (3 ) -Det(1 3 y Q ) 1From, lines2 (1 ) and (2) we have it that P and Q are gappy in all admissible DmodelEs, hence -Det(P y Q) E AXDET. T The usual sort of inductive proof establishes, from the soundness of the various operational and structural rules, that the system as a whole is neo- )classically sound. Moreover it can readily be seen to be equivalent to a standard sequent form of classical natural deduction, in the special case in which AXDET = {Det P: P E L } for the effect is then that the determinacy constraints are dropped. More generally, we can distinguish three important categories of AXDET sets of determinacy axioms: consistent sets, that is sets which are such that it is not the case that AXDET I-1 I ; secondly complete sets, that is sets for which Det P or -Det P belongs to AXDET for every P in the language (or sublanguage). And finally, classical AXDET sets, that is sets such that Det P E AXDET, for every P in the language. In the Appendix, complete- ness is proved in the following form:

If X is finite and X,Q C L , where L is a complete subsector of the language, then if X Q then X F Q.

These results give us a fairly attractive form of 'classical recapture'. In particular, for classical subsectors —but only in such subsectors— of the language, classical reasoning is unrestrictedly licit. From this perspective, classical 'logic' is an amalgam of logic properly so-called, the neo-classical rules minus A X DE T axioms on the one hand with, on the other, an 'impure' , namely the very special case o f AXDET axioms in which AXDET consists in Det P for all P in the language. This special case NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1233

is appropriate for the very important but idealised and simplified cases initially studied by logicians: languages in which there is no reference failure, vagueness, paradoxicality and so forth. That should not blind us to the fact that it is a special case and classical 'logic', its structural rules such as generalised transitivity or Cut in particular, do not extend beyond that special case. Note, though, that the yE rule gives us as a derived rule, via a degenerate case with the major premiss taking the form P y P, a fairly broad, though not completely generalised, form of transitivity or Cut:

X ( 1 ) P G i v e n Y,P ( 2 ) C G i v e n X,Y ( 3 ) C 1 , 2 Cut if Det Q E AXDET, for Q E X n Y. In particular, we have neo-classically that if A I-1 13 and B I-1 C then A I-1 C. so that this simple form of transitivity holds regardless of the determinacy axioms. Is the resultant logic paraconsistent? Well, we have P,-P i-1 Q and P,-P Q that is neo-classical logic is 'explosive', in Priest and Routley's ter- minology" and so also non-paraconsistent in the first of their usages of the term. But we do not have in general, as we have seen, P & -P Q , hence do not have P & -P 1-1 Q only Det(P & -P), P & -P I-1 Q hence only P & -P Q for those P such that Det(P & -P) E AXDET. Neo-classical logic is thus paraconsistent in Priest and Routley's second sense —the existence of classically inconsistent but non-trivial theories— so that their assertion (ibid.) that the first sense entails the second fails for the neo-classical case.

§11: Determinacy Constraints and the Conditional

The effect of moving to the broader derivability notion 1- in terms of some AXDET set is, for particular choices of AXDET, to give some instances of a theorem schema of classical logic neo-classical theorematic status but withhold it from others. Suppose, for example, that for some atomic P and Q, Det P and -Det Q both belong to AXDET. Then I- P y -P from, for example. DET vii):

"'Systems of Paraconsistent Logic'. Chapter V of Paraconsistent Logic: Essays on the Inconsistent p. 151. 234 ALAN WEIR

- (1) Det P AXDET — (2 ) P v -P 1 DET vii) though F Q y -Q must fail since -Det Q E A X DE T so that there is an admissible valuation v in which Q is gappy and so Q v -Q is gappy, hence by soundness, we do not have 1- Q y -Q. How can this difference between wffs which are in formal terms indistinguishable be legitimated? It is instructive to compare the case of free logic here: most contempo- rary philosophers are suspicious of the 'Anselmian' idea that one can prove existence claims in a wholly a priori fashion. But classically one can prove existential theorems such as 3 x x = x, x ( F x v -Fx). One common response here is to say that these formulae are not genuine theorems, that 'unfree' classical predicate logic is not strictly correct and must be amended by some free logic restrictions on e.g. 31 and VE. However the resultant proof theory is messy, the response continues, and granted that we know for sure that something does exist and granted further that, for some languages, we know that all its terms are denoting, classical logic, applied to these languages, will not lead us into untruth from truth or from non- falsity into falsity. This strikes me as a reasonable attitude; I will suggest that we adopt a similar attitude to the use of classical logic in mathematics: it is entirely legitimate to use it for sub-languages —that of arithmetic and analysis say— where one is confident there is no danger of paradoxicality; but one should not, cannot, extend this unfettered use of classical to the full language of mathematics. But as with the case of free logic, it still holds true that notwithstanding the harmlessness and indeed utility of appealing to classical logic in 'safe' sublanguages such as arithmetic, the truth of particular instances of classi- cal theorems cannot be totally a priori. 'The table in the room next door is either square or not' cannot be known to be true without knowing that there is a table in the room next door. In the example above even though we have P v -P but not I- Q y -Q the first theorem cannot be known true in a totally a priori fashion, its truth is not a purely formal matter else it would indeed not be distinguishable in status from Q v -Q. On the other hand, no such classical theorem can be false in any admissible valuation (similarly no anti-theorem can be true). To be sure, if R is everywhere gappy then R & -R cannot be false in any valuation either, similarly R y -R cannot be true. But in the case of classical theorems (in the 'extensional' language LE of 84, v, T and I ) and classical theorems alone, we can have purely logical knowledge which reveals that i f every component of the wff is determinate, then it is true: only indeterminacy stands in the way of its truth, as it were. For every wff cp is minimax interderivable with a conjunc- tive normal form CNFkol where CNIF[cp] is a conjunction each of whose NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1235

conjuncts is a basic disjunction, that is a disjunct each of whose disjuncts is either an atom or the negation of an atom. (Similarly each wff is minimax interderivable with a disjunctive normal form DNF[(p], a disjunction of basic conjunctions.) If cp is a classical theorem, it is interderivable with a CNF[tpl which is such that each disjunction contains at least one atom together with its negation. We have, then,

Det A: A < I - 1 ço. where the premisses are the 'determinations' of each atom which is a sub- formula of tp, writing (x < _v) for x is a sub-formula of y. The proof is by DET vii) then v l then & I yielding CINIFI(pl to which we then apply mini- max transformations. This suggests a tripartite division of inferential relations into the analytic, the semi-analytic and the synthetic, particularly if one rejects the idea of indeterminacy de re. Where A I-1 B. the inferential relation between the two is an analytic relation whereas, e.g. if A is merely empirical evidence for B the relation is synthetic; if B follows from A classically but not A I-1 B, for example if B is a classical theorem and A any sentence, the relation is semi-analytic (whether or not A I- B). In particular, if I- A v –A, A E LE then the truth o f A cannot be known fully formally. This does not tell against the neo-classical notion of entailment and proof: it is not in the least evident that the proofs which occur in the real mathematical reasoning of number or set-theorists, or proof-theorists for that matter, are purely formal entities. In fact, the fallacy of equivocation and the existence of fallacies of context-shift strongly indicates that there is a non-formal aspect to proof. Putting the matter more positively, if we accept, pace dialetheists, that indeterminacy is always a matter of some pathological malfunction in the relation between words and the world, then we know a priori that 'nothing in the world', as it were, prevents classical theorems being true. Knowl- edge of its truth, though a posteriori, is in a fairly clear sense linguistic rather than empirical. For instance, when we know that the table in the room next door is either square or not, our knowledge here is knowledge that the phrase 'table in the room next door' links to the world in the normal way. And perhaps a similar story —of some sort of malfunctioning of the word:world lin k— can be told for other cases in which classical theorems fail. Sometimes this is put by saying that whilst classical logic is the correct logic of propositions not all classical theorems are correct, for they may fail 236 ALAN WEIR

to express propositions." But this can be a rather unfruitful way to put things: —virtually any deviant logic could be rendered 'classical' by this move of writing off sentences it classifies differently from classical logic as non-expressive o f 'propositions'. We need a clear sense o f proposition here: after all in the reference failure and vagueness cases the sentences are built up from meaningful units in the same ways as non-malfunctioning sentences. A fairly externalist notion o f proposition or perhaps a meta- physics of states of affairs would seem to be presupposed by this picture. However that may be, I assume the legitimacy of taking there to be some determinacy assumptions, in the language of mathematics, which can be treated as having a special axiomatic status though not themselves logical truths or sentences whose truth is determined by their form. The idea will then be that the antinomies show not the falsehood of naïve set theory but the indeterminacy of certain sentences, such as the Russell sentence. It would be awkward, however, if one had to introduce into the language of mathematics an operator 'Det' foreign to mathematics as hitherto prac- tised. This will not prove necessary, however, as determinacy in mathe- matics can be analysed in terms of a modal conditional —>. Of course the same objection can now be raised: it may be claimed that modal and intensional notions are alien to contemporary mathematical practice, so that this manoeuvre is radically revisionary. To be sure, this Quinean doctrine of the o f mathematics is controversial with many arguing that modal notions —of possibilities of construction say— are not archaic ones, confined to the history of ancient Greek geometry, for example, but are in fact part and parcel of contemporary mathematics.I 5us e HI woillw maekev oef ar m odatl conhditioenal will be very limited. The main need for such an operator arises from the goal o f arriving at a semantically closed theory: —it is natural to represent the entailment relation in the object language as an iterable operator —> Moreover it is arguable that one use o f ' if t h e n ' in natural languages is as a sort o f heavily context- dependent entailment conditional. The intuition (albeit not universally shared, as remarked) that mathematics is a cleanly extensional discipline can be explained by saying that mathematical sentences are non-contingent so that the intensional conditional collapses into the extensional.

1 4 theK Lriar Paradox. (Oxford: Clarendon, 1984) pp. 53-8'2, footnote 18, p. 65. i p k1 5e 1985), Charles Chihara, Constructibility and Mathematical Existence. (Oxford: Clarendon, ,C f 1990), Hilary Putnam, 'Mathematics without Foundations'. Journal o f Philosophy 64, '. (19S67) pp. 5-22, Geoffrey Hellman. Mathematics without . (Oxford: Clarendon, 1989).O ut te lw ia nr et oS fh a Tp hi er o r( ye od f. T) rl um te hn 's ,i io n Ra .l M a rt th ie nm ea dt .i Rc es c. e( nA tm Es st se ar yd sa om n: TN ro r u t h aH no dl l a n d , NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1237

This is the picture I will propose but starting, of course, from a multi- valued conditional in o u r Lukasiewicz/Kleene approximation to the indeterminacies of set theory. Kleene and Lukasiewicz, in fact, diverged in their treatment of the three-valued conditional Lukasiewicz favouring this extensional one:

Q PDI T 0 F T T 0 P 0 T TO F T T T whereas Kleene's connective has gap (here represented by 0 ) as the output value in the middle case of 0 D 0 . The Kleene connective, however, cannot be a good representative of neo-classical entailment since the sin- gular inference from an everywhere gappy premiss to an everywhere gappy conclusion is neo-classically sound, trivially preserving truth 'downwards' and falsity upwards. The obvious modal generalisation o f Lukasiewicz' conditional is:

(1) P Q is true at a world w just in case if P is true at w*, w* accessible from w, so is Q and if Q is false there so is P. (2) P Q is false iff there is a world vt a,nd Q false at w*. *(3 ) aInc allc eothers s ciabsesl e(i.e. (1) and (2) fail but P is true at an accessible worldf r at owhicmh Q is gappy, orw P is gapp y at one at which Q is false) P w—› Q isi gappty at w.h P Howevert rthis conditionalu e is also not quite right as an object language surrogate for model-theoretic entailment since a singular from a true premiss to a gappy and thus untrue conclusion, o r from a gappy, unfalse premiss to false conclusion is determinately incorrect neo-classi- cally. So instead I will use a simpler semantics:

P —› Q is true at a world w just in case if P is true at w*, w* accessible from w, so is Q and if Q is false so is P; in all other cases, P —› Q is false.

To be sure this means that the gappy semantics cannot accommodate higher-order indeterminacy of conditionals since they all have a determi- nate truth value in each valuation and we shall see in the case of naïve set theory that an ineluctable higher-order indeterminacy in conditionals will 238 ALAN WEIR

always be with us (the Curry paradox shows this, fo r one thing). As remarked in connection with the primitive Det operator, however, the only adequate way to handle higher-order indeterminacy is to work with a non- classical logic in the semantic metatheory (expressed, ideally, in the object language itself), something which is postponed to Part The intended interpretation o f , moreover, is as a special type o f intensional conditional, namely one which represents logical entailment. Hence the standard interpretation will be one in which each model is just the set of all admissible valuations, models differing solely over which is the actual one, and in which the S5 semantics pertains so that each world is accessible from every other one. It follows from this that A —* B is true in valuation v in model M iff it is true at all valuations in all models. What, next, of the proof theory for —)? Intensional conditionals can be incorporated proof-theoretically without disturbing (too much) the opera- tional rules by dint of the relevantists' distinction between intensional and extensional combination of wffs in sequents. But for those who think that the number of times a hypothesis is assumed is rationally irrelevant, a more set-theoretic architecture is possible if we think of antecedents sets as sets of wffs indexed by some initial set of the ordinals, that is as sets whose members take the form (P, f o r P in some set X of wffs and 11 < k for some finite ordinal k and such that for every i < k there is some Q E X with (Q. E X*. For details, see the Appendix. However I have suggested that in the case o f the non-contingent language of mathematics, the intensional conditional is equivalent to the extensional. Working on that assumption, I will dispense with the ordinal tagging in uses of the conditional in set theory and hence use the usual sequent natural deduction -91 and —) E rules; subject however to neo-classi- cal constraints as follows. The I rule is:

X,P (I) Q Given Yi ( 2 . i ) Det R i G i v e n , V R i ( 3) P Q I 12•il -) E X subject to the usual sort of condition, namely that X n U Y, O . So the je idea is that given a proof of Q from P together with some determinate as- sumptions X, we can conclude on the basis of X and the distinct set of as- sumptions which generate determinacy of X, that P Q . The —)E rule is: NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1239

X (1) P —› Q Given (2) P Given Zi (3.i) Det Ri VRiEXnY

X (El ' I (We have here a similar sort of restriction to the one in place for —E: we 're quire determinacy o f the assumptions which occur in both premiss Use quent antecedents. Similarly we lay down also the disjointness condition: ( U 4,c/ Z ) w/ h ich I give for the general intensional case and not just the special case of Q inte rest in which i s interpreted as entailment and subject to S5 seman- 1tics. ( , XA lthough we have dropped for present purposes the modal apparatus and 2re strictions as unnecessary in the mathematical case, there are still some u 1principles which are valid for extensional conditionals but which fail in the Y 3neo-classical case, most notably: ) . = i Q P —) Q; and ii*) —P P Q 0 l T.he se principles fail for a neo-classical entailment conditional, even where — PS and Q are non-contingent, since, if Q is gappy at v but P true there then P > e Q is false at v but Q is merely gappy, contrary to falsity preservation E uepw ard. Gappy P and false Q provide a similar counterexample to ii*). The utsual proofs of these two principles are blocked, without appeal to the mhodal apparatus, by the neo-classical determinacy restrictions: 1e (1)Q Hyp 4A (2-)-P- p Ip (1) —P Hyp 2e (2) P Hyp 1n,2 (3) Q 1,2 —E 4d (4)-P -4-9 3 i 7 Inx e ach application the premiss sequent ensuring that all assumptions other thf an the antecedent of the conditional are determinate (i.e. Q in the first coase, —P in the second) is missing. r s o u n d n e s s p r o o f s f o r — › 240 ALAN WEIR

However the neo-classical restrictions on -› I block the usual derivation of the following transitivity principle:

X (I) P Q Given (2) Q R Given Zi (3.i) Det Ai VAi EXnY

X, 1 iE/ 1 1 ,th ough it is sound neo-classically (see Appendix again) assuming an S5 Usemantics for. Hence I will add the above principle as a primitive rule for , likewise similar principles of contraposition and permutativity. The Z variant rule with <4 in place of -) is easily derived, using &I and &E but I iw ill often cite the variant just as an instance of Transitivity, for reasons of (brevity. 4 The introduction o f the conditional then allows us to define the Det )ope rator. The obvious definition is P RDet P T ( 1 3 v A3)16 1 ,For if P has a truth value in all valuations, (P v -P) is true in all valuations 2henc e so is T ( P v -P ) as required. Conversely, i f P is gappy in [valuation y then so is P v -P hence in any valuation vv, T -) (P v -P) is 3false since there is an accessible y (our semantics being S5) at which T is true (it is true everywhere) but P v -P is untrue. . An alternative definition of indeterminacy and thereby determinacy is in iterms of what one might call the antinomicity of P, that is the obtaining of ]P - P which requires that P be gappy in all admissible valuations. TAbbreviating P 44 -P by Ant P, one strong principle which is sound with rrespect to it is the following: a n— ( I ) Ant P -› (Ant Q -> (P 44 Q) Ma ximin . s .This may be seen as a sort of generalisation of our mingle rule from P & -P conclude Q y -Q, hence the 'Maximingle' or 'Maximin.' nomenclature. If both P and Q are everywhere gappy, as the antecedents require, then P Q is everywhere true.

I tp s6o that we can abbreviate this definition of determinacy as D (q)v N o t e t h a t s i n c e — ) i s a s t r i c t e n t a i l m e n t c o n d i t i o n a l , T — › ( p a m o u n t s t o t h e n e c e s s i t y o f NAIVE SET THEORY. PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1241

What is the relationship between antinomicity and indeterminacy? Clear- ly if P is gappy in all valuations then Ant P is true. However suppose P is gappy in some but not all valuations. Then Det P is false but Ant P is not true, since in those valuations in which P is not gappy, we have each side of the biconditional taking different values. However if we consider a language such as mathematics in which, at least in the traditional concep- tion, no sentence is contingent, the two notions should coincide since each sentence takes the same value in all possible worlds. Hence, for the lan- guage of naïve set theory, we are justified in equating antinomicity and indeterminacy, and so adding as an axiom Ant P <4 -Det P:

— (1 ) (P <4 -P) 44 -(T ( P y -P)) A n t / De t Axiom

This, together with Maximingle, extends the power o f the system by enabling us to prove, rather than take as primitive, the DET principles i) to vii) set out earlier. For example: i) if I- P then 1- Det P: ( 1(2) P V -11 I VI — ()3 ) T -› (P V -13 ) 2P -v) IIfG I - D e t P and - D e t Q then -D e t (P Given i(1) -Det P (2) -Det Q Given v (3) (P - P ) -(T ( P y -P)) Ant/Det (4)e (Q <4 -Q) -(T ( Q y -Q)) Ant/Det (n5) P - P 1,3 4-0 E (6 ) 2,4 <4E 1( 7 ) ( 5 ) - 4 ( ( 6 ) (P 44 Q)) Maximin. )(8 ) P Q 5,6, 7 -0E x 9 -( Hyp. 10 Q9(10)P Hyp. 10 )(I1 )Q 8,10 <4E 12 P(12)Q Hyp. 9 y(13)Q 9,11,12 yE 9 Q(14) -Q 6, 13 <4E 9 (15) -P as 9: 14 9 (16) -P - Q 14, 15 Scl 9 (17) -(P V Q) 16 MM. (18) (PV Q) - 17 19 (19) -(P y Q) ( Hyp. P V I Q ) 242 ALAN WEIR

19 (2 0 ) —P 19 MM. 19 (2 1 )P 5,20 E 19 ( 2 2 ) P V Q 21 v I - (2 3 ) —(1 22, —>1 )- V (2 4 ) Ant (P Q ) 18, 23 &I I—Q (2)5 ) Ant (P y Q) — D e t (1 Ant/Det ()— (2P6 ) — Det (P y 1 Q) ) One final rule for f l o w s naturally from the intended interpretation of —) as encapsulating logical entailment in the object language. Let * be some uniform substitution of wffs for atomic wffs. Then we ought to be able to conclude (P —) Q ) * fro m P Q : i f P entails Q then any substitution instance of P entails the substitution instance, under the same uniform substitution, o f Q. More precisely, the following rule should be sound:

X ( I ) P —) Q H y p X ( 2 ) (P —) Q)* I - > SThUe pBroof of soundness is fairly simple granted the following lemma:

Substitution Lemma: If * is any substitution function and v any valuation then there is a valuation w such for all wffs P, P has the truth status (true, false or gappy) in 14 ,For suppose all of X are true in valuation t-' '1T h7te hnb athuter et is P a( v*aPlu ati on w— at which› P* is true and Q* is not or Q* is false hQand aP)* iss *not. I t folilows fsrom the Substitution Lemma that there is a invaluantion u sutch tha t either P is true at u but Q is not or Q is false at u but P vtis not,r .henceu, by oure S5 s emantics for , P Q is false at v contradicting the correctness of line (1). As for falsity preservation, suppose (P —) Q)* is faalse at v atnd all of X but A are true there. Then there is a valuation w at v . which P* is true and Q* is not or Q* is false and P* is not and so by the Substitution Lemma, as before, a valuation u at which P is true and Q is not or at which Q is false and P is not hence P Q is false at v whence by the correctness of line one, A is false at v. E Now the Substitution Lemma is easily proven in the case of simple Kleene semantics. Since any permutation of truth values (including gap) to atoms is a valuation, for any valuation v we read off the value of A* in v and assign it to A to generate valuation w. Proof by induction shows that all

7 simpIle set of wffs hut the argument is unaffected by the complication. n t h e f u l l m o d a l c a s e — s e e t h e A p p e n d i x — X w i l l b e a s e t o f i n d e x e d w f f s , n o t a NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1243

wffs in w have the truth status of their images under *• But the Lemma is blocked neo-classically since not all Kleene valuations are admissible. However if we are careful about what counts as a legitimate substitution function, an amended form of the Lemma, sufficient for the purposes at hand, will go through. Let us say that a substitution function * is admissible ill for all wffs A, if A* A then both Det A* and Det A belong to AXDET. In other words, the only formula on which non-trivial substitutions may be performed are axiomatically determinate ones and one may only substitute a similarly determinate formula for them. Hence A*, if it is distinct from A, cannot take a gappy value and for every admissible valuation there is an admis- sible variant in which A takes true and one in which it takes value false, since A is determinate. Ou r soundness proof goes through as before relative to a restricted form of S U B in which only atoms whose deter- minations are in AXDET are substituted for.

§III: Naive Set Theory & Classical Recapture

Let us now see how these logical ideas can be applied to naïve set theory. Here, I acknowledged, gappy semantics no longer apply though neither does the principle of bivalence since neo-classically we do not have (in general) excluded middle in the background logic. Moreover the previous sections have dealt solely with propositional logic and the logical frame- work for mathematics must encompass quantificational logic or something of similar power. Actually, I will argue in the second part of this article that the widespread dismissal of infinitary logic as 'of merely technical' inter- est, as not 'real logic', is mistaken and seek to broaden the logical appara- tus by generalising the propositional togic in an infinitary direction. For this final section of this part, however, I will assume a fairly obvious exten- sion of the above ideas to second-order logic. So, in line with the usual analogies (to be taken literally in Part II) between & and V and y and B. we will assume the standard VI. VE and 31 operational rules are legitimate since &I, & E and v l are all unrestricted neo-classically. BE must be restricted, however, in line with the restriction on vE, that is, taking the first-order case as example:

X (1) 3xcpx Given 2 (2) wx/a Hyp. Y,2 (3) C Given Z.i (4.i) Det Ai AiEXnY 244 ALAN WEIR

X 1,2,3 [4.i] 3E ' iE l Y Zwh ere U Z lE1 (i n 4( WXe n eed also, for full second-order logic, an axiom scheme of compre- uhensio n. Indeed I will use an even stronger form in order to derive the g) e neralised set comprehension axiom scheme, the scheme whose instances Y ) aCre all wffs which result from the substitution of any open sentence for ço in t=he follow ing (thus y may occur in cp): 0 3ayVx(x E y 4--> (px) n Gdranted that set-theoretic principle we can strengthen the second-order ctomprehension scheme to: h e3RVF1 ,...F„,,Vxl, ...x u insn which R may occur free in cp. Fo r it follows from generalised set cuomprehension that for any assignment o -sa, u cth(o thR atf forr eaney n +m long sequence a, a E [3 just in case the variant o f vlo a r i a b l e s , m+i) satisfies cp(F1, ...F „,, x , ...x tc(- Fhl 1 e, .r . e. nsets assigned to variables by a n d o iaw s s )-c;a n tushe tihse s trehngtohenledd sescon d-order comprehension scheme to generalise asFh „i , , e'a. weAavkner nedaïv en set t heory. sci a e t wc Soincnhe ourv e logicr sr ise seelcoynd, -o rder we can define the identity relation by t=u [lxc i ,3 0a- s drhe rivaeble: iw- es sca t p os= h n a le l rs i (1) t = t = I os• e f e , c(s tF 1 twd h e e Xi o(1) cpx/t Given f (2) t=u G i v e n n,g s . . Z.iV (3.i) Ai AieXnY Xan p.s F ( U (4) cpx/u 1 , 2 [3.il pt X Zte l l„h , , t i -ye wi here t and u are any singular terms, U n (X u Y) = 0 and cpx/m is the -.x i i e l r>te sult of replacing all free occurrences of x in (p by the singular term m. X,h ut )e ar nm do f t ha et fo ot lh le oc wo ir nr ge ps rp io n cd i pn lg ev sa r ei ga ab rl de iF n1 go ir dx ei n( ti i= t y a r e NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1245

Now for the non-logical part, the set theory. Naïve set theory admits of many formulations first-order versus second-order, axiomatic versus rule based, as primitive versus term-forming class operator as primitive etc.— and the differences can be significant relative to variations in back- ground logical framework. The rule form of Frege's Axiom V is perhaps the simplest way to present naïve set theory in a framework of introduction and elimination rules (here for the class abstraction operator) but for the neo-classical framework we need E as primitive, not defined, and so a slightly more complex system of joint rules for E and f I:

X ( 1 ) t E fx: (pxI G ive n X ( 2 ) (px/t 1 E l f ) E

X ( 1 ) (px/t I Given X ( 2 ) t E Ix: çoxl 1 E if I

From this theory we can derive not only naïve set comprehension but also the stronger generalised set version:

(I) a flix(Fx cp (x, f x: Fr})) Comp. 2 ( 2 ) Vx(Fx t p (x , f x : Fx))) Hyp. 2 ( 3 ) Ft 4-* cp(t,(x: Fix)) 2 VE 4 ( 4 ) Ft Hyp. 4 ( 5 ) t E fx: Fx1 4 E/f (6) Ft -* t E fx: Fx) 5 7 ( 7 ) t E (x: Fx) H- yp. 7 ( 8 ) Ft i7 E lf I E (9) t E ix: Fx1 -) Ft l8, - I (10)t E (x: FxI 44 Ft 6,9 &I 2 ( 1 1 ) t E F x I 44 (p(t.(x: Fx)) 3, 10 Trans. 2 ( 1 2 ) Vx(x E Ix: Fx1 4 Il VI 42 ((1p3 )( x3_,vV{ xx(x: E y 44 cp(x,y)) 12 31 F x(14)) 3y) Vx)(x E y t p (x , y )) 1,2, 13 3E

The

V.vVy0olz(z Ex z E y) - t = y ) is taken as primitive (it can be thought of as doing no more than distin- guishing classes from properties). So we will assume as our background set theory the E lf I 1 and E rules with strengthened second-order comprehension and extensionality. Such a 246 ALAN WEIR

powerful system clearly needs to be tamed by a non-classical logic. In neo- classical logic, the usual proofs o f antinomy are blocked, given that AXDET is a consistent set o f determinacy axioms,. relative to the set- theoretic ru le s. 1by8 a pFplyoinrg naïve principles to the Russell set r = x: x E x} is defused and itrannssfortmaed ninstead into a demonstration that the combined assumptions cthaet r ,E r and its determination are determinate are jointly inconsistent: t h 1 (I)rEr Hyp. e1 (2) r E r 1 Eif E 3u ( 3 s) Detu r E r H y p . a1,3 (4)l 1 1,2, [3] -E 3d (5)e r Er r 4 -I 3i (6)v ra E r 5 E/f 7t ( 7i ) Doet Det r E r H y p . 3,7n (8) 1 5,6 [7] o Bf y the (deriva ble) determinacy principle Det i): —if Det P is an axiom then Daet Dent P is a theorem, we cannot have Det r E r as an axiom. But if Dt et Deti r E r belongs to AXDET, then -Det r E r e AXDET is a theorem. Nnote thoat the restriction on -41 means that -Det r E r, that is -(T -4 (r E r r E r), does not neo-classically entail -(r E r y r E r) hence -Det r E r m y can be an axiom without, disastrously (even in neo-classical terms) -(r E r g r E r)e being an axiom also. n For aneother example, take the Curry set c = lx: x E x -+ ) ; the usual proofr ofa antinomy is blocked as follows: t e Id (1)c E c Hyp. 1 (2)cEc-)1 1 C/11 E 3 (3) Det c E c Hyp. 1,3 (4) I 1,2 [3] -4 E 5 (5) Det Det c E c Hyp. 3,5 ( 6 ) c E c -4 L 4 ( 5 ] -)1 3,5 (7) c E c 6 Eil ) 1 8 ( 8 ) Det Det Det c E c H y p . 3,5,8 ( 9 ) I k - 7 - 4 & g i - -- > -Here the final application of -*E is not even legitimate since one of the Edeterminacy antecedents —Det Det c E c, at line 5, is also one of the

1 8 sue0s fin volved in showing this that Part II is largely devoted. c o u r s e t h a t t h e r e e x i s t s s u c h a c o n s i s t e n t s e t n e e d s t o b e p r o v e n , a n d i t i s t o t h e i s - NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1247

assumptions in other premisses for sequent E . Even if we complicate the rule to allow this,I 9a catseh wehe re indeterminacy of conditionals is needed: Det c E c cannot be maxioomastic tbut c E c is equivalent to c E c s o we have a conditional wwhich eis ind eterminate, or at least not axiomatically determinate. c Morae gennerally we can note that P - P Q fails, and indeed that P <4 -P is perfectly coherent neo-classically: p r o v e(1) P -P Given 2i (2) sP Hyp. 2l (i3) -P 1,2, n4 (4e) Det P Hyp. 92,4 (5) 1 2,3 [4] -E 4. (6) -P 5, -I 4H (7e) P 6 E r8 (8e) Det Det P Hyp. 4, ,8 (9 ) I 6,7 [8] -E t h oso that uneo-classical logic also provides a framework for handling anti- gnomic shentences such as the Liar. In Part 11 we will look at strengthened liar type sentences such as A: (-Tr A v -Det A) which says of itself that it is , untrue or indeterminate, cases where we need to introduce higher-order iwndeterminacy though this is something the indeterminacy of conditionals feorces us to accept anyway. Overall the conclusion to be drawn is that the wh ise should refrain from accepting or rejecting such sentences as r E r tahough for some, at least, we may be able to affirm that they are indeter- mv inate or indeterminate to some higher degree. e What form, then, should the set of determinacy axioms AXDET take for naïve set theory? I suggest taking a gung-ho attitude here: —adopt a set M which is maximally consistent in the sense that M is consistent but adding sentences Det P or -De t P not already in M induces inconsistency. O f course we can have no Cartesian certainty that some given set of determin- acy axioms we are working with is consistent: —but if inconsistency should appear, we simply weaken the determinacy axioms accordingly. This approach, I want to argue, achieves a very smooth classical recapture, that is, it validates nicely the standard mathematical practice o f using

I 9 andT also to X n Y then Z .) hD e t Astaned s, requiiring sthat U z, and (X n Y) be disjoint, has the consequence that F is not simply a cn o t h e AXDET F r o 1 b u t o m f o v e r t p h e a l l d l ie t e r i m c i n a c s y a a p t r e m s i i i s s e m p s o . l e T n r h w r e o u r u l u l e l d t e b o a e u s s s i t e t i . p u l a t i n g t h a t i f A b e l o n g s t o a d e t e r m i n a c y a n t e c e d e n t Z i 248 ALAN WEIR

classical logic (and, indeed, naïve set theoretic principles) when working in 'safe' areas, such as arithmetic, analysis or the lower reaches of set theory. To illustrate this I sketch how the cumulative hierarchy features in the neo-classical framework. Let us start first of all with the ordinals, the back- bone of the orthodox cumulative hierarchy. We could introduce a binary term-forming order-type operator and an abstraction principle similar to Axiom V or else utilise the classic definition o f ordinals as equivalence classes 2Th0e equivalence relation is that of being an order-preserving . But oit wv iell be simpler to use the von Neumann idea of defining ordinals as rtra nsitive sets over which E is a well-ordering. Naïve comprehension then gives us ON the set of all ordinals. But is ON w e l itself an ordinal, is it a member of itself? Classically either answer to such l - questions leads to disaster —in particular, the Burali-Forti paradox. Neo- classicallyo r d we have a way out: ON E ON, like r E r, is indeterminate, we ceanr aiffirm —(T —› (ON E ON y ON E ON)) and so be resolutely agnostic onn gthes qu estion whether ON belongs to itself or not. ( Now to work with the ordinals, we need recursive definition. But one of tAhe virtues of the 'loopy' ultra-impredicative form of the generalised com- ,prehension set axiom is that we get 'for free'. Indeed it enables Rus to prove the existence of sets corresponding to arbitrary inductive defini- )tions where standard set theory permits, in general, only positive inductive idefinitions. .2us1 to Iprnov e the existence of the cumulative hierarch); V epago ian(gra tht roi ugEh any oOf theN hard) w ork of proving recursion theorems! The cwinductiveu i l at r dhefionitioun its as follows, where (a,x) E V is more familiarly w. ritten as x E V w, ta h i (a,x) E V (4 Vy (y E e. t x — ) ( ] ) 3 g e n ahnd t

Plus as y = a + /3, (and thus incurring obligations to prove uniqueness, see b e lo w 2 2 )y = (a + /3) <4 p = 0 8 4 y = a b i n V P = 8 a r y ' & = Lim it /3 & y , U(c x +5() o r o d i ( n a a where 8' is the +success or of 5. namely 8 u 151. We can use recursion again lto extend + to an infinitary operation v i a the equations (which can be 1 arecast as instances of generalised comprehension): d 3 d1 (0i) = ) t1(fi o. n: (fi X ) , À a limit 4 +a . . i+J f : f 3 X Here (f: a+1 1—> X) is an indexing function from the ordinal a+1 into some s1 tset X of ordinals and f(a is the restriction of that function to a. Then we 1can define binary a X g directly, as the sum of the a sequence whose h - set X is just 101 (i.e. the ith term of the sequence is 0, for each i E e-a) and go on to extend to arbitrarily long products then to exponentiation. n) A s fo r cardinals, these could be taken in the standard fashion as initial dXordinals or we could use the Frege/Russell definition of the cardinal of x as e)the set of all sets equinumerous with x. Since we have a U, f=with x E U x = x , we have a greatest infinite cardinal oc with x Eoc <4 x i1 (J, where abbreviates the definition of equinumerosity. 1 will call 00 n(superinfinity, the number o f all things. The existence o f the greatest eicardinal oc thus vindicates Frege's early theory of cardinals and Russell's d(early p osition, as expressed in 1901 (both later abandoned, of course): b' There is a greatest of all infinite numbers, which is the number of all ya things altogether, of every sort and kind. It is obvious that there cannot : ) be a greater number than this C a n t o r has a proof that there is no + f ( a + I 2 2 )comAprehension in the form VA - n 3 a! y c p x y 3 lf t 1 V . v V y f x = e y r 4 4 n ( a p x y ) t i w v h e r e . e f w c o a n u o l c c u d r i b n e c t p . o t a k e f u n c t i o n t e r m s a s p r i m i t i v e a n d h a v e f u n c t i o n a l 250 ALAN WEIR

greatest number B u t in this one point, the master has been guilty of a very subtle fallacy, which I hope to explain in some future wo rk. 2 3 Of course Russell fails to pay heed here to Cantor's distinction between consistent and 'inconsistent', 'absolutely infinite', multiplicities such as the 'multiplicity' or 'domain' (i.e. naïve set) of all things. Once we treat of the superinfinite number of all things we are back in the region of paradox and antinomy likewise when we put an ordinal size on the length o f the cumulative hierarchy V . 2ge4n eraTl fhormi sof recdursoion bute sit do es show that defining the set into exis- ntence ois onet thing , being able to do things with it in neo-classical logic, e.g. iuse pmroof pby inductionu g isn anoth er. Similarly, mere recursion alone does that show that Plus is functional, i.e. o u r ce, 0, y) E Plus & c,y, [3, 5) E Plus y = 8 nor, for example, that ordered pairs under the Weiner-Kuratowski defini- tion, say, obey the law. A ll these things, proof by induction, functionality of Plus (which is provable given induction), the ordered pair law and so forth, will hold for a sub-language Lc which is classical, so that Det P E AXDET, for all P E L . One obvious proposal for such a classical sublanguage is the set of all wffs restricted to V , for some particular a. That is all quantifiers are restricted to V abound by a Vx governing a clause Vx(x E V ,afi e ri —.3xe ›g.o v.ere.nin.ag) a cclahuose ark(v E V a iqas bnou&udnd a ib. yvn. a .qit)uda intuief-iear aVlF c in ah cla use V F(F C V — ) ...) or by the dual clause for 3F. vs ea c ro ni da - b l e xo Hrered noew irs h o w we can get a very neat classical recapture since it ivindicaates rasll io f thea standardb l reasonings o f mathematicians, number- etheori sts, analysts, ZF and NBG set (and class)-theorists and so o n . F2do5e s sI ot, at any rate, so long as there is a consistent AXDET set which con- tains the determination of every wff in these sub-languages. So if a in the

2 3 MoBnthly 4, (1901) pp. 83-101. Reprinted in Mysticism and Logic. (New York: Barnes and Noeblre, 1971 edition) the quotation is from p. 69. t r a2 4n SeedA M ichael Dummett, Frege: Philosophy of Mathematics, (London: Duckworth, 1991) pp.s 3 16-317, Alan Weir, 'Dummett on ', Grazer Philosophische Studien 55, (19R98) pp. 65-101, see pp. 81-82. un e 2s5 a 1s r l se y el e el v n, e o' r pR y re o oc n be e ln d et o mW e ao s br , ok e uo v tn e it n nh t ce h oP o r s pi e on s rc u ai c tp h il a ne s gs D Co u af m tM m ea e gt t oh t re w ym h Ta o ht d ei e oc n rs y y, t wI h in a t t he i Br t in c ga a Ct n ai b to e en d ga o ol n r e i . e s e i t h e r . NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1251

restriction clauses V oL ,wcally i s a botut othe set-theoretic simulacra of the natural numbers. Similarly —on e wl ilel bet ju stified in reasoning fully classically about the , or utfunctiosns over the reals if the classical AXDET set for L in the first case, or for L shw + a y ofor) +L ie1 i sn c o n s i s t e n t , 2icla ssiicnal re astonhing efro m the axioms of ZF. But there will be consistent tn h i s,A XeDETc seots nof adll th.es e types if current standard mathematics is consis- tsient. Ai s n d cf a ic Howo fafr can on e reasonably assume we can go, in this direction? Con- sLider thee set o f all Small ordinals, where a set is Small if f there is no tn s h e bijectiontw h from the set onto the entire . I will use f i as a name for ci s l a s s aithis set. tV o is, o f course, the standard cumulative hierarchy. I f L n it e c a l tsc,l a isssical then we can reason classically and conclude that fi, being a class An t X hcof (downwards-closed) ordinals, is itself an ordinal. Hence it cannot be D, E elSmall (else it would belong, absurdly to itself) and so there is a bijection b Tf saof f i uontob the universe.- This gives us a well-ordering R of the universe, so lswith aRvy 4n4 b g ery • us- a g ts( By sticking our necks out a little further we can develop the theory of a eil x o1wfhole hierarchy of Big ordinals, the 'Last Number Class' as it were: ordi- icb y m.n als of the form f i + fi, f i sau s i n exgt2his ,la s t case, we define by recursion a function Is with domain to by the le, q ufaitiotns/ , oiEf o nvrM o r e np f(0)r =e c i s aVt f(i+h I ) = f (0 ee l y , wc.e 1 1 cvoi r d n the least solution to e =11c, a n d we can con iand define' c bY(i);o e= le r i U i=o lsvntin ueg on u pwards. So if L bs.ocfuall y classically about an initial segment of the last number class of super- infinite ordinals. I will assume in Part II that this assumption is innocent, eiAv, f o r bnesuntiol promvene gu ilty. a What, though, if i t the class of small ordinals is in fact to. Well, in that bldra , etfcase the universe is countable and anything beyond number-theory is illicit. lSi imilasrly, if f i is accessible, then ZF is too strong and so forth. How can eKhic l a s s i c t.i,a l otstt h e hg 2 6 rcnomT phrehe nsion, of Global Choice —see 'Applications of Paraconsistent Logic' in Brady ei ewande R outley (eds e.) op. cit. p. 374, fails to hold in full generality neo-classically. anvsc B t a soean r a onsr e a d euds o n n y wsa c a i or n mlnd d pltx R o lbu er u e t en t l enG e lt y p yio r ctb la o l o el a f sdC , sth i n io ai a - p lc a le r . a 2 c 6 o n s i s t e n t l o g i c w i t h g e n e r a l i s e d 252 ALAN WEIR

we decide what size the universe is, from the neo-classical naïve per- spective? There is no formal decision procedure or even criterion. One can demonstrate that to is small and so b y applying Cantor's Power-Set Theorem to to thereby showing that its power class is of higher . But this demonstration will only be accepted as such by someone who in effect thinks of to as determinate (more exactly, accepts T —* (f(C, oy f ( C ) C )(o neE:one mCapp, in,g from 1 ,3P)o,w erSet reasoning as applied to the set A of all cardinals accessible from w(Nwo )thh eine nonet wo il l accept as provable that there is at least one inaccessible, rtandeo so ) ac.cep t as legitimate classical reasoning with respect to ZFC (the C from the above argument for Global Choice). (S i xm i l a r l As remarked, nothing rules out the possibility that, having accepted, e.g. Ey that f(CA) E CA is determinate, one will later discover that antinomy is i f Cderivable by anyone reasoning neo-classically on that determinacy assump- (otion. I f Ln, turns eout to be non-classical, for t inaccessible, then one will ,asimply c havec to reevise one's estimate as to what is provable and so true; in 4p artictular osne w ill no longer treat full ZFC reasoning as legitimate. To ask -tof an accohunt of mathematics that it rule out any such future revision is to *edemand a C artesian certainty which is not possible even in mathematics. xC I finiash w itnh a cotmparison between the neo-classical and the dialetheic Eoaccounrts of i classicala recapture. On the neo-classical account, our actual xnpractice o f unrestricted classical reasoning is legitimate fo r the sub- ffragment of mathematical language in which all quantifiers are restricted to -a 'safe'1 set and if standard mathematics is classically consistent there will be such a safe set. This means that neo-classical logic in effect collapses ( x into classical with regard to standard mathematics. Where classical logic is )not co) nsist ent, outside the domain of standard mathematics, n e o - flcolgaics psroivcida els techniques for reasoning coherently about 'unsafe' sets such tas the universal set, the Russell set, the class of all ordinals and so on. Of hcourse the standard view is that there is nowhere outside the standard "do- emain" and w e do not reason about these sets, we simply deny they exist. pBut as a whole tradition from Frederic Fitch up to Graham Priest has per- usuasively argued, few, if any, have been able to stick consistently to the rofficial line: the proscribed sets have a persistent habit of resurfacing in the pguise of 'totalities' or 'collections' or 'domains' or some other such genteel oeuphemism, wherever an attempt is made to interpret or justify set theory. rNeo-classical logic saves us from the bad faith involved in all this. What about the dialetheic account of classical recapture? There seems to t be more than one: one recent idea is that the classical reasoning employed ein mathematics departments the world over is 'default' reasoning, legiti- dmate except when employed in inconsistent situations; and when reasoning NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1253

in number theory, analysis, ZFC and so forth one might suppose we have good reason to believe we are not in inconsistent situations. of27 d eTfahulti resa soningo bet airs osomne resemblance to the neo-classical idea of classical reasoning being safe in domains where the needed determinacy axioms hold. However the positions are, I think, really rather different. Priest cashes out the notion of default reasoning in terms of non-monotonic calculi, calculi in which simple and intuitive operational rules such as the disjunctive syllogism rule for y and —, are not universally valid. This is more counter-intuitive than the neo-classical position which validates this operational rule. But the point is not clear cut because of course what is a basic operational rule in one proof architecture can be derived via opera- tional plus structural rules in other. Still the more clear and obvious the rule one rejects, the less the initial plausibility of one's position. And a calculi is not plausibly viewed as a logic, I would argue, unless the rules it takes as basic single step operational rules are treated as globally correct. There is a stronger reason for thinking, however, that such calculi, how- ever useful they may prove in formalising non-deductive reasoning, are not genuine logics. For to say that X entails A is to say, on the intuitive rough gloss, that in any possible situation in which X is true A is; but in non- monotonic calculi, X A could hold yet A fail to hold in a situation in which X is true together with some other stuff Y. In an earlier account of classical recapture, (In Contradiction pp. 144— '48), Priest argues that the dialetheist can argue classically in areas where no contradiction is suspected, even when such reasoning is invalid accord- ing to the dialetheist, because invalid reasoning can be perfectly respect- able, as inductive reasoning shows. But the legitimacy of inference to the best explanation, for example, does not show that affirming the consequent is legitimate. Rather, the conclusion of an inference to the best explanation should, at least when we are being exact, be qualified probabilistically. But to reformulate mathematical practice so that, e.g. we may conclude only that it is probable that there are more reals than natural numbers, is not to recapture classical mathematics but to mangle it beyond recog- nition. This criticism highlights what I believe is the crucial failing of dialethe- ism in general, one which vitiates its claims to provide a rational recon- struction of mathematical practice. This failing is its inability to explain why abandonment of theories is sometimes rationally compelling. One of Priest's explanation is that when a theory entails something with lo w probability, say a 'malign' zero-probability contradiction, then it should be

2 7 1 3 u t s e e G . P r i e s t : ' I s A r i t h m e t i c I n c o n s i s t e n t ? , M i n d 1 0 3 , ( 1 9 9 4 ) p p . 3 3 7 - 3 4 9 . 254 ALAN WEIR

abandoned; (some atypically benign contradictions, have, for the dialethe- ist, probabilities greater than zero, e.g. one). Here 'probability' cannot be interpreted in frequentist terms but must be interpreted 'epistemically' either as an objective relation among arbitrary propositions —thus some type of a priori confirmation relation— or else subjectively à la Bayesians. If the dialetheist appeals to subjective probability, the game is up. Priest believes we can knowingly believe P & -P. Hence if we are extremely fond of a theory 0 but turn up a contradictory consequence P & -P we will presumably have no problem in believing P & -P, i.e. attaching subjective degree of probability one to it. At any rate there are no objective rational grounds which debar us from doing this, regardless of what 0 and P are, so that no refusal to abandon a theory can ever be objectively criticised. Hence it would seem that the dialetheist, in explaining when it is irrational to persist with a theory, must rely on a priori objective degrees of confir- mation or something of a similar nature. And the problem there is that she is then wedded to one of the least successful philosophical research pro- grammes of recent times. No such commitment is required o f the neo- classical approach, so on these grounds I conclude that it affords a superior classical recapture when compared to dialetheism. All granted the sound- ness of the system, of course, to which I turn in Part

Alan Weir Department of Philosophy The Queen's University of Belfast BELFAST BT7 INN N. IRELAND. [email protected]

APPENDIX: SOUNDNESS AND COMPLETENESS RESULTS

Soundness for the conditional

The inductive steps for many of the non-conditional operational rules in the proof of soundness for the neo-classical system have been considered in the main body of the article so I consider now the cases of the introduction and elimination rules for W e are especially interested in the intended inter- pretation of -) as representing logical entailment but for the soundness proof let us consider a more general interpretation. Thus our models are sets of worlds, worlds being just admissible valuations; but models need not include all admissible valuations, moreover we let the accessibility relation by any relation at all over the worlds of the model. NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1255

Since antecedents of sequents are sets of wffs indexed by some initial segment of the ordinals we need to add the idea of a sequence of worlds in model M being 'suited' for a sequent. If the antecedent is indexed by an n long segment then the sequence of worlds is suited if f it is of the form (wo, w „ ) with W1+1 accessible from I n the definition of entailment we then replace truth and falsity of wffs in a valuation by truth (falsity) in the ith world for a wff indexed by i, with truth and falsity for the succeedent wff defined by truth or falsity of the wff in w„ the 'end' world in the string. So a world-sequence satisfies a sequent iff neo-classical truth and falsity preservation hold with truth and falsity world-relativised as above. That is, X A is a neo-classically correct sequent just when for every admissible model M and every sequence (wi) of worlds of the model suited to X:

a) If all wffs in X are true relative to their assigned worlds in (ni) then A is true relative to w eb) For any wff P in X , ,2a n8dt ahill efin X Abut P are true relative to their assigned worlds then P is eifalsesn relatived to at least some of its assigned worlds. wf ao l r s l ed orHaveingl fthusa sett ioutv the semantics, we turn to the proof theory for wh(eich isw givei n by) the following introduction and elimination rules: .t o X,A+t (1)h B Given Yie (2.i) Det Ci Given, Ci E X e n X U (3) B I I d Et whwere X CIo 0 . 2 r 9 l is d o X f (1) A -4 B Given ( w (2) A Given Zi i (3.i)DetC1) VCiEXnY

X, Yx+, Z i l e i (whe4re ()X u Y) n 0 . Q is/ 1 , 2 8 2 1 4 [ .2 9 3 sS t r i 1 u c t 1 hl y —ts > hp E ae ta (k Pi ,n ag ), ot ch ci us rm se ia n Xs .t h e r e i s n o w f f P s u c h t h a t l ' ) , r _ r ) E X a n d P , 1 3 ) J Y , 256 ALAN WEIR

The notation in these rules is interpreted as follows A+ t (N, a )1 , where a = I I . L x, with i x the supremum of the indices in X . 3Yx+0 isT thhat ewe "silidde" tehe ainde xebd Y eandh X wi ffsn togdether so that their last in d e x 3w1or ld "past". Thus if X is I ( a3(13n0 d, ,0 ) ,w hils( t ifR X is, (P2a) a) nd) Y is (Pa, Q s—RQ 1 w e stIru cting X,Yx+ is: oc2 , Ra n a,) i f i x t h e n leave the indices on the wffs in X untouched and add w) 2 r i t (eRP nx e. ) t h e n -rde2su- l ting sets. tM) X h, Y xi + pbw) yio)f /IX < ILLY then leave the indices on Y untouched and add ( P v so_ i s +-rto 1tlhe indices in X. r a ( P a , tpd xs) - 1 en P I , Wade then form a sequence (wi) suited to X, YX+,UZ, b y aligning the go r Y Q I , ici et hienidices of (X, Yx+) and those of UZ, the latter in turn formed by aligning ns iE/ e" eanpd indices of all Zi sets. i 0 lr aPn,roo f of Soundness: di T Fl or 1 : Truth-preservation direction. Suppose all of X, U Y igO iE/ nil , a r e t r u e rcelative to (wi) a sequence of worlds suited to X whose 'end' world is w eyu ea,nl d s uppose A is true at w* accessible from w Xd,A+, all wffs are true at their respective worlds so that B is true at the end ;ewst world" h w* of (wi)Aw*. Suppose on the other hand B is false at such a w*. .io T h e n ( w i ) A w * Tt heen since all of X are true relative to (wi) and (wi)Aw* is suited to X,A+, 3tn 2 i s stthhne co urrectni esst of X,A+e d B yields the falsity of A in w*, as required. hX the o n1, ey "1 ,wX n+ yf fui ds sd ge1"S inc e we will only consider sequents, finite or infinite, which have are indexed by a foinpite ordinal string, there will always be a greatest index in X. hence the supremum of the ef ind0ices in X is in X itself. By the index of a set X of wff indices we will mean the least oirdinal containing all and only the indices in X. " , nY t Q ea 3 I nhIT d, de h3 2 ap1 . fY e r s2e . ow, f a— f R or lt mf 2wh r , ts ae o/ Tye h2 nI sx e, ex it au se bn on ns oi o ei v o n i e n o , to tf hf t et h fh eh e ie r ns u ie l tq e au re f yn o c r ae c s( o ev v n . i - ) f o r m e d b y a d d i n g w * a s t h e i + I t h e n d t e r m . NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1257

Falsity preservation. Suppose A —) B is false at w e a n d a l l o f i E l XP are tr.ue relative to Utheir appr opriatYe worlds in (wi). Thus there is a world w* accessible from w i b u t e s u c h bt ) Bh isa falset at w e ai nt dh e r i E I Adaisjoin tn)eiss condition,s all members X are true in their respective worlds nviolatingA o t trut.h p reservation. Since all of the Yi are true at their respective worlds, all members of X have determinate values at their worlds, by the Mi o rs e correctness of the 2.i sequents. P cannot be true at all its respective worlds oitn (wvi) roetherwr uise (wi)Aw* yields a counterexample to the correctness of line P(e1), eith er viola ting truth preservation, in case (a), or falsity preservation Euapwards, in case (b). Since P is determinate, it must therefore be false at Yst ome of its worlds as required. iw sFeor Trui t h -p re se rva t io n . Suppose all of X,Yx+, U Zi are true relative na c iE etno (wi) a sequence of worlds suited to X , Y x+ UZi and whose end world id j e t fBis w nieof X,Yx+) is Wp B y the definition of X,Yx+, all Y wffs are true relative to the end-sequent of (wi) of Y's length (i.e. the length of the ordinal osa nstring indexing Y). Hence by the correctness of the minor premiss, A is ttnrue at w ,od wheave that A -+ B is true at w bthe truth of B at w hp, yeo a s o.w hS ii ln c e w tr e q u i r e seFa ls ity Prieservsation . Suppose B is false at w h j e t afed .rac nc d e as ls l i b wl f f s eare true at all their assigned worlds except P. As before, P cannot occur in peoi mn X ' Y x eft+ Uorn paino of violationm of truth preservation. There are thus three cases: h nw( E ui)pe P oc curs in X but not Yx÷; ii) P occurs in YX+ but not X; iii) P occurs in lbtmoth —inh which ciase by the determinacy premisses 3.i it is non-gappy in all worlds. tsa iyCj ase i) iAll of Ye is truel at (ei, defined as above, hence A is true at w mdeotruncatiosn of (wi) by the deletion of the end term w a.req u eTyn ceih e(weli)d s a w o r l d - true. Since w tps- e - e i s ers u i t e a c c e s wed s i b l e omf o r f r riX o m lsw i w dst h p (ae a wn n hd d itw A cho r i hel d s mdw t uep r sfa u tin nde e a xi t itn w siw e toh b bni u yoc t tfh B hXa f e,l a cYl l oXw s n+f e s,f t tws h reb e u r ct e tP i ia t or ne 258 A L A N WEIR

follows from the correctness of the major premiss that P is false at some of its assigned worlds in (wi) C- ashe eii) nAlcl oef X is true at (wi) -a t wh te n c e A -efors -+o> B my thee cor Brectness of the minor premiss, P is false in some of its assigned worlds in (e i) hence in (wi). i,a s s s i g n Case iii) P is determinate so either true at all worlds assigned it or false in twe dr u e at least one. If the former, B is true at w aew o t r l w ein g.b Siync e tit ihs neot —tbyr huypt ohthe-sis— P is false relative to at least one pad s pworrlde. s e r v a t i o n .ci n rThe teransitaivity rule,s aodded ans a fu-rther primitive: Sc( iw n i c eX) (1) . P Q Given Bs (2) Q R Given isZi i (3.i)s Det Ai VAi EXnY fb a l sXl , Y. U Ze, ( 4 ) P -› R 1 , 2 [3.ii Trans. e 1E1 f ralso has to be shown to be sound. Here we assume X, Y. U Z , is formed by simple alignment of end-indices. l e i o m wTruth-preservation: Suppose all of X, Y, U Z j e ' worldsp in a suitable sequence (wi) and that P is true at a world w* acces- ,1 a r e t r u e isible nfrom t he et nd hworled wi r st uitable for X and Y both with w re e s p e c t i v e .ethr u eaW ats we * ta nhdt ebya i(2rk) Re is true at w*; Similarly if R is false at w* so is P. treSineceh sw*p eis eany c wtorlid vacceess ible from w ten wn o d ewFA, alPs ityo -np-res>rerdv altioRn:d Sup p.osie alsl of X, Y, U Z i but S are true in their i e l sBit r e u g ey m e a t s(respwe ctive worlds and P -› R is false at (w n( t s iE/ e (Ife e i )th.e uSsua l recasaonn; ifn it boelotng s to X n Y it is determinate but cannot be true )a . bon peain lo fo violnatingg tru th-preservation. So we consider only the cases awQl here (i) S bnelongs to X but not Y or else (ii) to Y but not X. In the first a t i Z dcisase, Q R iss true at (w i f o r (eacce ssible fro6m (w )ea.n d SP isi notc. Ief c ase a), Q is not true at w* by (2) hence P -) Q is false at P)(t wa t R iweb) Rh isis faclseh a t w* so by (2) Q is false at w''' whilst P is not. Hence P Q fe) i a t hl es e trsb h e r eaoy , ) tPb h e riyh e s itle r sui e ane n wdem o rR(a l d wi1n *s)t nSi oic tsc ofl ra blu )s Re ia st fs ao lm se eo f i t s w o r l d s i n t , . » a n d s o ( w i ) . I n c a s e NAÏVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1259 is false at (w e(e i) and so (wi) as required. The argument for the second case, S is in Y but )n ota X,n is dsim ilar. D o Thne ecxtensional rules all have to be complicated in the intensional frame- ework in order to handle the modal indices. For example, for —I a g a X,P (1)1 Given i nX (2) —P 1, —1 b y X,— P ( 1 ) _I_ G i v e n l Xi (2) P I, —I, n e X( ,P is to be interpreted as saying that P, in the first case, —P in the second, o1ccurs with the same index as ,Ltx. Hence for the first case in the falsity )preser,vation direction, i f —P is false at w Sesequence suite d to X. then P is true at w i,etheir ta worlds,hn ed Qes muston b de falsei f at s ome assigned world. Similarly we must swacompol licaltre t h le Edxpoa nsionf ruole. Two fsound e xpansion rules are: faX b u t (1) A G i v e n awQ o r l d - X,YX+ ( 2 ) A 1 , Expansion la r e st r (1) Au G i v een Xea ,YX ( 2 ) t A 1 , Expansion a Ht ere in the fi rst form of the rule, X,Yx+ is formed from X and Y just as withs —)E whilst in the second form we merely "end-align" the indexed sets oof wffs. To see the soundness of the first form, suppose all of X,Yx+ are mtrue relative to (wi) as defined for —)E above, likewise for the definitions of ew oeth e Y-length end-sequent of (wi) hence by the premiss sequent A is true at faw inPe a re true in (wi) hence all members of Y but P true in (e i), then, by the cor- rectness of the premiss, P must occur in Y and be false in some worlds in tda (e i sw )li ttle as we are able to, yielding in the minimal case the second form of the wpr hrule, and still preserve soundness. o.e e To incorporate the standard modal logics we simply alter the construction rBq nof the Y set in the third premiss o f the —) E rule. For example, i f the lyu caccessibility relation is reflexive this form of -4E is sound: dti e shr ( ie w nd i e. ) fI . if A n, s ih c to a iw n oe b nv e oe s fr e X, e ,A n Yi , xs w +f e ,a c al o ls u le l Ya d wt " fw n fe u sa d an g rd e ea " tl Y rl p um a e s rm t eb X le a ar s ts m io u vf c eX h t, o oY r (x a e+ s tb )u ,t 260 ALAN WEIR

X 1) A —› B Given (2) A Given Zi (3.i) Det Ci VCiEXnY

X, Yx, t J 1E1 z(subject to the same disjointness condition). Here YX is to be interpreted as ,in the previous paragraph. As to soundness, the argument is exactly the (sam4e a)s th e original form of e x c e p t that we drop w Qpworld; t here is now no need for a penultimate world in the soundness proof ,s incte hthee e ndp woerldn wu l t i m a t e ei1s aiccse sstibleh freom itself. This form of the rule then enables us to derive the re,ule nOE,d tha t is the rule if X D P then X I- P, with LIP T P , T the wnullary2 o lorgiclallyd trut h constant. The proof is: f[ o r X (1)T P Given b3 o t . (2) T Hyp. X.Th (3) P 1,2 ti h X (4) P Supp. e] — withX the principle at (4) being the suppression of the logical truth constant Ts) . e E t Similarl y if the accessibility relation is transitive we get the K4 and satronger logics adequate fo r such classes o f modal models by adding annother variant of —› E in which the Y wffs can be nudged two worlds d'past' the en d world of the sequences suited to the X world: t Xh (1) A —) B Given e (2) A Given ZY is (X, Yx++, UZ, ( 4 ) Q 1 , 2 [3.ij —>E e ( 3 t E .whilst for the Brouwersche we use a version of --)E in which this time the Xa wffs arel nudged one past the Y wffs. in X)d 1) A B Given D (2) A Given Zie (31) Det Ci VCi EXnY t XC, Y x (El -i ,V UC z ,i (E 4X )n QY 1 , 2 1 3 . i l — > E NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 126

Completeness

We prove completeness with respect to the gappy semantics and thus for the non-mathematical case in which we do not have the strong Maximingle rule equating indeterminacy and antinomicity. In its place, we add MM*:

— ( 1 ) -Det P G i v e n — ( 2 ) -Det Q G i v e n X (3) P Given X (4) Q 1,2,3 MM* which is trivially both truth-preserving and upwards falsity-preserving. We also consider -) to have the intended interpretation of a logical entailment conditional so models are essentially just the set of all valuations with each world accessible from any other. Define sublanguage L to be complete just when for all A E L, either Det A E AXDET or else -Det A E AXDET. Then we have, for finite X and with X,Q C L. L complete:

If X H Q then X HQ

Proof: We prove this by induction on the degree of the sequent X Q . where this is 1 + the maximum degree of the component wffs and where the degree of the wff ranks the number of nestings of the conditional: that is atoms have zero degree, the degree of (A -) B) is 1 plus the maximum degree of its immediate components and the degree of all other compounds is just the maximum degree of their immediate components. We need, in fact, to prove inductively both the above completeness result and the Conditional Lemma: If A B is true at some valuation y (equivalently at all valuations) then (A -) B)': if A -) B is false, then I--(A B ) where 'is any legitimate substitution function. We assume the result holds for all sequents of degree less than or equal to n and conditionals of degree n and prove both parts for degree n+1. The proof of completeness is by contraposition. So we assume Not: X h Q, where X Q is of degree n+1. The proof that Not: X H Q appeals to transformations into disjunctive and conjunctive normal forms after the fashion of Anderson and Belnap's for their system of tautological entail- ments in Entailment op. cit. §15.1. We note firstly that an inductive proof establishes that every sentence P takes the same value in every valuation as, and can be transformed by 262 ALAN WEIR

minimax rules into, a disjunctive normal form (DNF) i=1v P. i=twhere v Pi is a disjunction of basic conjunctions, 3tio3n oaf b absica sesnteinces -± A, each basic sentence of the form A or —A c.a toAom onra aj cnuonnditciont ail. o n b3cl4as sSiceaillmy ini tlo aannr elqyuiv galent conjunctive normal form (CNF) a conjunction aof bansic disyjunc tions, each such disjunction composed of basic sentences as above. cs e o n nt ej n u n c Leet P be the conjunction of all wffs in X, y Pi a DNF of P and Q i a CNFc of- Q. Then we have =11 ,1=1 • c a n Not: ( v Pi & Qf) b e t r a n s Ff or ootherwr ise mwe would have X 1- Q by: e d nX (1) eP &I's o - (2) v P i=1 i i=1v P 1=1N o i r m J(-1 Qi• ( a l 3 4 F X (5) Q 1:4 Cut ) ) o k Q r So there must be some Pi, Q Q N m i f o w i t h N Ino t : be a subs-proof of & Qi from P i with the following structure: G(r P i 1=1 i=1 i 1m - Qa i ) v i=v1 Pi (I ) V Pi Hyp. eel l s e ntFPI h e r Given eo wr PI o u Given l m d i s n d e e d 3 3 its Mscope. o r e3 4 the conditional in the completeness proof. eT h xi s ai cs ta l yd ,e av di ia sn jt un no ct ti io on no if nb wa hs i c hc no on oj cu cn uc rt r, eo nf c eo ou fr &s oe r, —d he as si ag n oe cd ct uo rs ri em np cl ei of fy yt ir ne a t m e n t o f NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONSISTENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1263

PI (m+2) 2:111+1 &I

( 0 Pil ( p )) 8LQ1 a s 2:tn+I &I 8(p+ I) S Z Q 4J Hence we know that there is some basic conjunction Pi, and basic dis- 9J < „, junction 9 ) siIuch that Not: (Pi F p )basic sentencpe in com mon, else Qi would be derivable by &E and vI from Pi. It followsl also that they cannot both be replete where a basic con- . I t f ov l l o w s junction or di-sjunction is replete if it has as constituents both A and —A, for t h a -Et tsomeh atome A. Thyis is so because otherwise the basic disjunction would be neo-classica1lly derivable this time using the mingle rule. c So asupponse0 Qn. at leoast, ist not replete (the argument in the other case is ssymmetrical)h a aand Pi isr of the form e s a & —Al nA' , & —yA,. & B1 ...B s 2 whe.re r may: be zero and no negate 3ca5n not hf a veB mDeit A k EB AXDET, for k r : for if so, then At & —At I- Q s.(sinc e thoen Fc+ Dect (Aut & r—At))s h ence by Cut Pi I- Qi since Pi H Ak & —At. Moreover there cannot be both an indeterminate conjunct (i.e. conjunct C i/ n 1 Pwith —Deti C E AX DET) of Pi and indeterminate disjunct D of Qi since then we would& have C F D by the MM* version of the maximingle ride and o r so Pi I- Qi. SuI ppose without loss of generality that all wffs in Qi are deter- mQinate (thei case wh•ere all in Pi are determinate is similar). WWe now proceeed to construct a counterexample valuation y. Suppose first of all, in order that the idea behind the valuation be made clear, that Pi and Qi contain no conditionals. We construct the valuation in stages firstly by assigning the value false to each basic sentence in Q/: this is possible since each disjunct is determinate and Q1 is not replete so that no two basic sentences share atoms. We then extend this partial valuation by assigning true to each B in dienter minate conjunct; similarly all the opposing Ak, —Ak formulae are left Pgap,py. Again the result is a partial valuation because no two B ts hasre e atnomtse annd cif eansy sentence shares an atom with a basic sentence in Qi >the sen tences are negates of one another and the Qi sentence is false. We rthen ex tend this valuation any way we like (but respecting AXDET, e.g. true or false for E with Det E E AXDET, gappy if —Det E E A X DE T) s u c h t 3 5 h a 1 . t B e . t A i i s s a d n e t e e r m i g n a t a e , t a e n o d f g B a i p f A t i o s e — a B c o r h B i s — A . 264 ALAN WEIR

over all other atoms to yield our admissible valuation v which is a counter- example to Pi H Q . since Qi is false and Pi is not, and so a counter- example to P H Q by the clauses for & and y. By contraposition, if X k Q then X 1- Q. But we must consider the more general case where Pi or Qi may contain conditionals. Here we apply the Conditional Lemma, which we have supposed holds of wffs of degree n or less and since X Q is of degree n-1-1, any conditional in X,Q must be of degree n at most. It follows from the inductive hypothesis that if a conditional is in Pi or its negation is in Qj then it cannot be false in any valuation. For if R —) S is false in valuation w then by the inductive hypothesis to the Conditional Lemma, h—(R —) S). Thus if —(R —› S) is in Qi then F Qi hence Pi I- Qi by expansion, contrary to hypothesis. Similarly R —) S cannot be in Pi else Pi h Qi by —E. Since (R —› S) is false in no valuations it is true in all valuations, given our bivalent semantics for —) and so true in our counterexample valuation y; hence it can be treated just like a determinate basic atom which is in Pi or whose negation is in Qi in generating a counterexample valuation: 3ot6h erI hfa,nd , Ro —)n. S is in tQi hor itse negation in P iv atluhatieonns ( heni cet by ourc Saemnantnics mo ustt b e false in all). For if true then 1- bR S eby the Conditional t r Lemu ma ine the special case of a null substitution function i n a We neend, then,y in order to tie up the proof, to prove the Conditional Lemma itself, for wffs of degree n4-1. I f any such wff E -4 F is true in a valuation then E H F . Since E —> F is of maximum degree n+1 so too is E H F hence by the completeness result for degree n+ I just established, E F so I- (E —> F)' by —) I followed by s u B . Suppose, on the other hand, E —› F is false. Then there is a counterexample valuation y in which (i) E is true and F untrue or (ii) F is false and E is non-false. In either case we use the S U B rule with respect to a substitution function * which assigns T to every subformula of E or F true in y, I to every wff false in v and I to every wff gappy in v where I is some sentence such that —Det I e AXDET (if there is no such sentence, the language is purely classical and we can consider a purely bivalent semantics which simplifies the proof). Since our language L is complete, * is a legitimate substitution function. Any wff A true or false in y is determinate so Det A

3 6 claIsns ical metatheory, for example— we can argue that if (R S ) is indeterminate and belaon gs to the complete sector of the language then we have outright –Det (R S ) E AXsDET, by our definition o f AXDET. Such conditionals can then be treated lik e indueterminate basic sentences in P in daetenrmdin ateQ sentence, including a conditional, in one of P sentenceb in the other. i t s o t, l9h a t , f1 e i of tr h e r e i s ea r x n a m i np d l e et e, r m i n a t e w s e c e a n n o t m h a a v e n a t n i c s w h i c h a l l o w s f o r i n d e t e r m i n a c y — b y d i n t o f w o r k i n g i n a n o n - NAIVE SET THEORY, PARACONS1STENCY AND INDETERMINACY: PART 1265

E AXDET, ally wff gappy there is indeterminate. The next fact we need is Lemma II:

If A is true in v then F A*, if A is false in y then 1- —A* and if A is gappy in y then —Det A*.

Proof of Lemma II. Proof is by induction on wff complexity over the set of all sub-formulae of E or F (which have maximum degree of n e s t in g n). The base step is easy (using the completeness of L). For an example of an inductive case for a non-conditional operator, consider A = (R&S). The case where A is true in y is easy. If A false in is y, one conjunct at least is false, say R. Then b y inductive hypothesis I- —R* so by minimax I- -(R* & S*) but this wf f is just [ (R& S )] * . Suppose, finally, that A is gappy at y because, for example, R is true but S is gappy. Then 1- —Det A*. If not, by completeness I- Det A* even though, by inductive hypothesis, I- -Det S*. But this is impossible, by soundness, since otherwise we would have the following proof.

(1) Det (R* & S*) Given (2) R* Given 3 ( 3 ) R* & S* • Hyp. 3 ( 4 ) S* 3 &E (5) —Det S* Given (6) —Det —S* 5 Det 3 ( 7 ) —S* 4,5,6 MM* 3 ( 8 ) 4,7 [I] —E (9) —(R* & S*) 8 —I (10) —R* v —S* 9 Minimax 11 (I 1 )—R* Hyp. 11 (1 2 ) —S* 2, 11 —E 13 (1 3 ) —S* Hyp. (14) —S* 10, 12, 13 vE (15) S* 5,6, 15 MM* (16) I 14, 15 —E

So much for 'extensional' operators: we have finally to prove Lemma fl for conditionals sub-formulae of E or F. But these must have degree n or less. Here we appeal to our overall inductive hypothesis applied to the Conditional Lemma. (Once again we need not consider the case of gappy conditionals but in a semantics which allowed for indeterminacy we would have outright —Det(R —› S) E AXDET, for indeterminate R —› S.) If R —) 266 ALAN WEIR

S is true in y then as we have seen I- (R -3 S)' for any legitimate substi- tution function such as *. If R -3 S is false in v then there is a valuation w at which either R is true and S not true —and so I- R* and either I- -S* or I- -Det S*; or S is false and R not false in which case I- -S* and either I- R* or I- -Det R*. Either way I- -(R -3 S)* by a proof of the same type as that in proof of the Conditional Lemma to be given next. Returning, then, to the proof of the Conditional Lemma for the inductive stage of degree /H-1 sequents, we have still to prove that I- -(E -› F) when E -) F is false and we noted there were two cases. In case (a), E is true at and F is untrue. By Lemma II, we have I- E* and I- -Det F* or 1- -E*. The right disjunct here provides an easier case so we consider the left disjunct. Given that I- -De i E* and that our conditional is determinate there must exist the following proof:

I (l)E-3F Hyp. I ( 2 ) E* F * 1 - (3)> S E*U GivenB 1 (4) PI' 2,3 ->E — (5 ) -Det E* G i v e n — (6 ) -Det -F* 5 Det vi) I (7) -E* 4,5,6 MM* — (8 ) Det E -3 F A X D E T I (9) 1 4,7 [81 -E — ( I 0) -(E -3 F) 9 -I

The argument in case (I)) is similar. Note that by omitting line I and letting line (2) by an example of the rule of hypothesis the above proof could be transformed into a proof that -(E -› F )the required result I- -(R -› S)* in the proof of Lemma II above. This com- 3pletes the proof of Completeness and the Conditional Lemma. E . A p r o o f o f s i m i l a r t y p e g i v e s u s